37
1 eiaslp.v5b, 8-12-14 Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications for Genetic Testing Policy Richard Peter * , Andreas Richter ** , Paul Thistle Abstract: We examine the endogenous value of information in an insurance market where there is potential adverse selection due to individual differences in the efficiency of loss pre- vention technology. We show that with observable preventive effort for all risk types, classi- fication risk is alleviated or might even be overcome: If people can adjust their loss prevention behavior to the information acquired, information might be valuable. We show that the relevant policy regimes can be Pareto ranked, with full disclosure being the prefered regime and an information ban the worst regime. This has important public policy implications for the areas of genetic testing and HIV testing. Keywords: information value, prevention, adverse selection JEL-Classification: D11, D82, G22, G28 * Munich Risk and Insurance Center, LudwigMaximiliansUniversitaet Munich, EMail: [email protected], Phone: +49 89 2180 3882 ** Munich Risk and Insurance Center, LudwigMaximiliansUniversitaet Munich EMail: [email protected] Phone: +49 89 2180 2171 Department of Finance, University of Nevada Las Vegas, EMail: [email protected], Phone: +1 702 895 3856

Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

1  

  

eiaslp.v5b, 8-12-14

Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention:

Implications for Genetic Testing Policy

Richard Peter*, Andreas Richter**, Paul Thistle†

Abstract: We examine the endogenous value of information in an insurance market where

there is potential adverse selection due to individual differences in the efficiency of loss pre-

vention technology. We show that with observable preventive effort for all risk types, classi-

fication risk is alleviated or might even be overcome: If people can adjust their loss prevention

behavior to the information acquired, information might be valuable. We show that the

relevant policy regimes can be Pareto ranked, with full disclosure being the prefered regime

and an information ban the worst regime. This has important public policy implications for the

areas of genetic testing and HIV testing.

Keywords: information value, prevention, adverse selection

JEL-Classification: D11, D82, G22, G28

                                                       * Munich Risk and Insurance Center, Ludwig‐Maximilians‐Universitaet Munich, E‐Mail: [email protected], Phone: +49 89 2180 3882 ** Munich Risk and Insurance Center, Ludwig‐Maximilians‐Universitaet Munich E‐Mail: [email protected] Phone: +49 89 2180 2171 

† Department of Finance, University of Nevada Las Vegas, E‐Mail: [email protected], Phone: +1 702 895 3856 

Page 2: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

  

Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention:

Implications for Genetic Testing Policy

1 Introduction

There are many situations in which individuals must decide whether to learn about the

potential risks they face. Consider, for example, an individual deciding whether to take a

genetic test. Under which conditions will individuals choose to be tested and acquire

information about their risk? Insurance possibilities impact the value of information, i.e., the

extent to which insurance companies utilize potential customers’ information is crucial in

determining whether individuals decide to become informed. In addition, individuals may

adjust their risk mitigation behavior in response to the information acquired, which in turn

has implications for insurance pricing. Put differently, health risks are not only determined by

individuals’ risk types, but also by environmental factors over which individuals have some

control.

In this paper, we examine public policy toward the use of information from genetic tests

by insurers.1 Public policy decisions about the use of test information will affect the markets

for health insurance, life insurance, annuities, and long-term care insurance. Bundorf,

Herring and Pauly’s (2010) and Handel’s (2013) results are consistent with adverse selection in

employer provided health insurance. Finkelstein and Poterba (2002, 2004) and He (2009)

provide evidence of adverse selection in annuity markets and life insurance markets,

respectively. Zick, et. al (2005) find that individuals who had postive predictive tests for

Alzheimer’ disease substantially increased their purchase of long-tem care insurance. Oster, et.

                                                       1 In the paper, we focus on the use of genetic tests. The same issues arise for HIV tests, where low cost home and

mail-order tests are readily available. Similar issues also arise in liability insurance. This is particularly the case

for the development of new products and new technologies where the firms must decide whether to determine

the potential risks to consumers and the potential liability, as well as what steps it will take to mitigate those risks.

Page 3: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

2  

  

al (2010) report „strong evidence of adverse selection“ (p. 1048). Asymptomatic individuals

who have tested poitive for Huntington’s disease are five times more likely to own long-tem

care insurance as otherwise comparable individuals.2 The increasing availablity of mail-order

genetic tests for a wide range of conditions has the potential to change the distribution of

information in these insurance markets. Public policy can either exacerbate or mitigate

advese selection in these markets.

This paper also extend the literature on the incentives to acquire information in

insurance markets.3 Milgrom and Stokey (1982) show that, if ex-ante efficient contracts are

negotiated in a complete market economy, the social value of subsequently generated

information is zero, as it cannot create new investment opportunities. The question then arises

why individuals should decide to become informed at all. Crocker and Snow (1986) show that,

when it is costless, using categorical variables in pricing insurance increases welfare.

Rothschild (2011) shows that the government can offer partial social insurance such that

lifting a ban on categorical discrimination is weakly welfare increasing, even if categorization

is costly. Garidel-Thoron (2005) argues that, in dynamic insurance markets, allowing insurers

to share loss information decreases welfare. These analyses assume individuals are

exogenously endowed with knowledge of their risk type.

Other researchers have examined environments where individuals are initially

uninformed. Crocker and Snow (1992) demonstrate that if insurers can observe whether

individuals are informed or not and if consumers do not have prior private information, then

the private value of information is negative. This implies that information will not be obtained

and that insurance deters diagnostic testing. Tabarrok (1994) discusses the potential threat of

uninsurability through genetic testing, because insurance coverage for high risk types might be

too expensive. He suggests genetic insurance as a possible solution to the classification risk

                                                       2 The broader evidence on adverse selection is mixed. In addition to risk-based selection, there is also evidence

of selection on other dimensions. See Cohen and Siegelman (2010) for a survey of empirical research on adverse

selection in insurance markets.

3 See Crocker and Snow (2013) for a survey of the literature on risk classification and the value of information in

insurance markets.

Page 4: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

3  

  

posed by genetic testing. Strohmenger and Wambach (2000) model an insurance market with

state-dependent consumer preferences and treatment costs exceeding the individual’s

willingness to pay. Then additional risk classification can be welfare enhancing under

symmetric information, but there is the threat of complete market failure under asymmetric

information about risk types. Doherty and Thistle (1996) re-analyze the private value of

information and find that it is non-negative only if insurers are unable to observe the

informational status of the consumers or if individuals are able to conceal their informational

status. This demonstrates the crucial role of the regulator when it comes to the question of how

to handle information from genetic tests or from risk classification devices in general for the

purposes of insurance purchasing. In Doherty and Posey (1998) the value of a treatment option

for tested high risks is examined. However, when thinking about health related risks or

liability risks, one observes that uninformed consumers or low risks will also invest in risk

mitigation. Our model will take this into account. The incentive to acquire information

depend on the tradeoff between the gains from reducing the inefficiency due to adverse

selection and cost of classification risk.

The literature has focused mainly on the canonical Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976)

model. However, both heterogeneity of risk types, and heterogeneity of individual measures of

prevention seem to be important, especially in the contexts of health risks.4 In these situations,

information also has clinical value, since it lets individuals choose loss prevention more

efficiently.

Consider, for example, genetic testing for breast cancer risk. A mutation of the genes

BRCA1 and BRCA2 is known to be associated with a higher risk for breast or ovarian cancer

(Thompson et al., 2002). However, since the 1970s substantial medical progress has been made

in therapies for breast cancer, especially when detected early (Goldhirsch, et. al, 2007). It is

a reasonable assumption that a positive result for a BRCA1 or BRCA2 mutation will change

                                                       4 In their seminal work, Ehrlich and Becker (1972) distinguish between self-protection, i.e., investments to reduce the probability of loss, and

self-insurance, i.e., investments to reduce the size of a loss. Common in the insurance literature is also the terminology loss prevention for the

former and loss reduction for the latter risk management device. In this paper we focus on loss prevention.

Page 5: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

4  

  

individual prevention behavior in terms of the frequency of seeing a doctor to detect

indications of breast cancer as early as possible. But for individuals who might not know their

genetic make-up or those who have tested negative, the interplay between risk relevant factors

and risk type also determines their final probability of disease.5 Similarly, there are genetic test

that indicate an increased risk for heart attack, hypertension and Type 1 and 2 diabetes, as well

as other diseases where lifesytle choices affect the risk of developing the disease. These, and

many other genetic risks, are multifactorial because individuals do not just passively acquire

information, but can adjust their risk-relevant behavior in response to the information.

However, the lifestyle choices of uninformed individuals and individuals with a negative test

result will also matter when it comes to determining the probability of falling ill. Their choices

cannot be ignored. More generally, the interplay between risk type and factors that can at least

partially be controlled by consumers determines the insurable risk. Einav et. al (2013) report

that individual choose insurance, at least in part, based on their anticipated response to

coverage.

These examples demonstrate that focusing only on an exogenously given distribution of

risks in the population is insufficient to judge the incentives to obtain information in an

adverse selection framework. When decision-makers can react to the information acquired by

adjusting loss prevention effort the information has clinical value. This does not only apply to

“bad news”. Consequently, the risks are endogenous for all individuals. The clinical value of

information adds a dimension to the tradeoff between the costs of adverse selection and

classification risk in determining the value of information. We show, for example, that with

symmetric information the value of information can be positive; when loss prevention is not

possible the value of information is unambiguously negative.

The extent of potential adverse selection and classification risk is determined in large

part by regulations governing the use of test results by insurers. Regulation varies widely

                                                       5 In the case of breast cancer typical (endogenous) risk factors are nutrition habits, alcohol consumption, smoking before the age of 16 and

exercising habits amongst others (Colditz and Frazier, 1995; Thune et al., 1997). In general, any habits that might disturb the hormonal

balance might lead to moderate increases in breast cancer risk.

Page 6: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

5  

  

across juristictions and across insurance markets, ranging from bans on the use of genetic test

results to voluntary restrictions to no regulation.6 In the U.S, the use of genetic information is

governed by the Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act (HIPAA) of 1966 and

the Genetic Information and Nondiscrimination ACT (GINA) of 2008. Taken together, these

laws effectively prohibit the use of genetic information (including family health history) in

determining coverage or premiums in both group and individual health insurance for

asymptomatic individuals. These laws do not apply to life insurance, annuities or long-term

care insurance. Most U.S. states have enacted similar laws for health insurance, however, 30

states have no legislation regarding the use of genetic information in life insurance, annuities

or long-term care insurance (National Conference of State Legislatures, 2008a, 2008b).

Canada has no specific legislation governing the use of genetic information. While

Canadian insurance companies do not require genetic tests, they may request the results of any

tests that have been performed. The situation is similar in Australia and New Zealand. The

Oviedo Convention, which is binding on the members of the European Community that have

signed it, prohibits discrimination against a person on the basis of their genetic hertiage.

Austria, Belgium, France, Portugal, Sweden and Switzerland have passed legislation that

effectively prohibits the use of genetic tests by insurance companies; Belgium makes an

exception for life insurance policies above approximately $150,000. U.K. insurers have

aggreed a moratorium on the use of genetic tests (except life insurance policies above

£500,00).7 Individuals are allowed to disclose favorable genetic test results to rebut family

hitory information. In South Africa, insurers have agreed to a Code of Conduct under which

they may not require genetic tests. Previous tests, but not their results, must be disclosed to

the insurer. Most Asian and African countries have not enacted legislation regulating the use

of genetic information by insurers.

We consider four possible policy regimes and analyze the incentives for individuals to

                                                       6 See Joly, Braker and Le Huynh (2010) and Otlawski, Taylor and Bombard (2012) for surveys of regulatory

regimes regarding the use of genetic information.

7 The U.K. moratorium has been in place since 2001 and has been extended until at least 2017.

Page 7: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

6  

  

take genetic tests and analyze insurance market outcomes. We analyze a duty to disclose or

mandatory disclosure regime under which individuals must provide the results of any genetic

tests to insurers. We consider a “code of conduct“ under which the fact that a test has been

taken must be disclosed but the test results cannot be used by the insurer. We also consider a

consent law or voluntary disclosure regime under which individuals can choose whether or

not to reveal test results. Finally, we examine a ban on genetic testing under which neither

the fact that a test has been taken nor the test result can be used by the insurer.

The policy regime is important in detemining the value of information and the resulting

insurance market outcome. If consumers‘ information status is observable, then insurers can

condition the policies they offer on information status. This exacerbates the classification

risk. The value of information is negative unless information has sufficient clinical value. If

consumers‘ information status is not observable, insurers must offer the same policies to

informed and uniformed. Then the value of information is non-negative, regardless of

whether information has clinical value. Based on the resulting insurance market outcomes,

we are able to ex ante Pareto rank (from the point of view of an untested individual) the

different policy regimes. The clinical value of information affects the Pareto ranking, but

ultimately does not affect the policy recommendation.

The paper proceeds as follows. The next section outlines the basic model and introduces

the different prevention technologies. Section 3 introduces adverse selection by allowing for

different assumptions on the observability of informational status and risk type of consumers.

Section 4 analyzes welfare and ranks the policy alternatives and section 5 discusses public

policy implications and concludes.

2 The Basic Model

2.1 General Assumptions

Following the classical insurance demand literature, we consider risk-averse individuals

with utility of final wealth , which is assumed to be strictly monotonic and concave

Page 8: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

7  

  

( ′ 0, ′′ 0). Let 0 be initial wealth which is subject to incurring a loss of with

probability . Individuals may choose effort which reduces the probability of loss and

comes at costs of . The cost of effort is increasing and convex ( ′ 0, ′′ 0).8 Also note

that we assume costs to be separable.9

We assume that the probability of loss consists of a component that is exogenous and of a

component over which the individual has some control and which is in that sense endogenous.

For instance the probability of an illness depends on the genetic make-up, e.g., whether one

has a genetic predisposition to heart disease or hypertension, and on behavior regarding other

risk relevant factors, e.g., nutrition, smoking and drinking habits, or lifestyle in general.

Furthermore, as in Doherty and Posey (1998), treatment decisions and their effectiveness will

typically depend on the level of information. In this respect, we mean by preventive action any

behavior by the individual that might decrease the probability of illness.

We assume that individuals are identical except for prevention technology, such that a

fraction of the population is considered high risk and a fraction = 1 – is considered

low risk. High risk individuals have the loss probability while low risks have the loss

probability . We assume and are strictly decreasing and strictly convex. For any

given level of effort, high risks face a higher loss probability than low risks, formally 1

0, for all . However, individuals might not (yet) know to which risk class

they belong and hence assume an average loss probability of due

to rational expectations.10 Subscript U denotes the uninformed individual.

To analyze heterogeneous prevention technologies we introduce the positive difference

function : as in Hoy (1989). Following his terminology we distinguish

between the three cases of constant difference (CD) for which ′ 0 , decreasing

                                                       8 Adopting the terminology of Ehrlich and Becker (1972) we consider self-protection only. An analysis of the value of genetic information if

consumers may choose a loss reduction or self-insurance action can be found in Barigozzi and Henriet (2011). 9 We abstract from heterogeneity in the dimension of prevention cost. Separability is sufficient for the first order approach to be valid

(Rogerson, 1985; Jewitt, 1988). 10 We abstract from ambiguity aversion. Formally, being uninformed corresponds to having a lottery between either the high risk or the low

risk probability, which is disliked by ambiguity-averse decision-makers. For a study of effort choices under ambiguity aversion refer to Snow

(2011) and Alary et al. (2013).

Page 9: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

8  

  

difference (DD) for which ′ 0, and increasing difference (ID) for which ′ 0. DD

corresponds to a situation where H-types have the more efficient technology compare to the

L-types. For instance, there might be a promising treatment option available that significantly

lowers the probability of a severe case of the disease. The current situation regarding HIV

treatment could be an example for that case. CD resembles a situation where H-types are

equally efficient at loss prevention as L-types, e.g., if there is no effective treatment available

and the detection of a genetic mutation simply means enhanced likelihood of the occurrence

of a specific disease. In the case of ID, H-types are even less efficient than L-types in

prevention meaning that the genetic mutation not only carries with it an elevated probability

of the occurrence of the disease, moreover the means of preventing the occurrence are no

longer efficient compared to healthy people without the mutation. Let us make an important

clarifying remark regarding terminology. We speak of risk type in order to distinguish high

risks with prevention technology from low risks with prevention technology . We

speak of informational status to distinguish uninformed individuals with prevention

technology from informed individuals with prevention technology or .

2.2 Effort Choices Without Insurance

We initially assume that insurance is not available. Then the individual’s expected utility

is given by

1 , ∈ , , ,

with first-order condition

′ ′ ′ 0. (1)

Optimal effort is chosen such that it balances marginal benefit from prevention and

marginal cost. Let denote optimal effort for a type individual. It is straightforward to

show that under CD we have , under DD we have and under ID

we have . This is intuitively plausible as the marginal cost of prevention does

not depend on type. Therefore, in case of CD where marginal benefit from prevention is equal

Page 10: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

9  

  

among types everybody choses the same effort level. Under DD H-types have the more

efficient technology so that the optimal effort is higher. This is reversed in the case of ID.11

The value of information is defined as the change in expected utility from acquiring the

information

. (2)

The value of information is zero in the CD case. For the other two cases, we have

0,

where the inequality holds due to the optimality of and , respectively. In the ID and DD

cases, the information has clinical value, as individuals use the information to adjust their

effort levels to their loss prevention technology. As Savage (1954) points out, the individual is

free to ignore the information and hence it cannot be disadvantageous. This option value of

information raises the value of information. We assume throughout that individuals choose

to become informed if the value of information is non-negative.

2.3 Actuarially Fair Insurance Coverage

Now assume that insurance is available in a perfectly competitive market at actuarially

fair prices. We first abstract from informational asymmetries, i.e., the insurer is able to observe

both informational status and risk type. This is a situation in which the insured has a duty to

disclose.

In our example of health risks, this corresponds to a situation where the insurer must be

informed about whether a genetic test has been conducted and, if so, what the results were.

This might be the case if the insurance company paid for the test, perhaps as a part of more

general medical examination. In this case it seems particularly reasonable that the insurance

company has some information on average precautionary measures taken by an average

individual, a low risk individual and a high risk individual, and therefore considerations of

                                                       11 Due to the endogeneity of loss prevention effort the indifference curves over final wealth in the two states of the world might not be

convex. They are decreasing in any case due to the envelope theorem, but the curvature reflects effort adjustments. Technical conditions to

ensure convexity are long-winded and not very insightful so that we assume convexity wherever needed.

Page 11: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

10  

  

moral hazard can be neglected.

An insurance policy , , consists of a premium, , a coverage level, , and a

level of prevention activity, . Expected utility is then

1 1 .

Since the market is competitive, insuring a proportion of the loss comes at a premium of

for a type individual. We know from classical insurance demand theory that

full insurance coverage will be obtained, see for instance Mossin (1968).12 The objective of a

type individual is therefore to maximize

,

which yields the first-order condition

′ ′ ′ 0,

where the prime denotes differentiation with respect to . We let denote the first-best

effort level for a type individual, and let denote the first-best policy for type .

For the CD case, the H-types and L-types are equally efficient at loss prevention.

However, H-types have a higher premium rate and therefore they will exert more effort to

reduce the premium. For the DD case, the H-types are more efficient at loss prevention than

the L-types, hence again they will exert more effort than L-types. So for the CD and DD cases

we have . For the ID case, there are two competing effects. H-types have a

higher premium rate which induces them to exert more effort than L-types. However, they are

less efficient at loss prevention and this induces them to exert less effort. Therefore, the overall

effect is ambiguous.

The value of information is given by

,                                                        12 Of course, Mossin (1968) abstracts from prevention and considers a fixed premium only, but in case prevention expenditures are observed,

optimality of full insurance coverage still holds.

Page 12: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

11  

  

for constants , 0. The risk premia and capture the effect of classification risk on

wealth and the cost of care, respectively. Again, the optimality of and implies that

that is, information has clinical value. However, this is not sufficient to guarantee that the

value of information is positive. Individuals who choose to become informed are exposed to

classification risk, and we cannot unambiguously sign .13 We conclude that the following

two conditions are sufficient for positivity of the value of information,

,

. (3)

If the insurance premium when uninformed exceeds the expected insurance premium when

informed plus a constant accounting for the aversion to classification risk, and if average

prevention effort is sufficiently below the effort of uninformed individuals, consumers will

decide to become informed and learn about their type.

Proposition 1 Let informational status and risk type be observable. The value

of information can be positive or negative. The inequalities in (3) are sufficient

for the value of information to be positive.

In the appendix we parameterize the heterogeneity in prevention technology and

demonstrate that DD tends to enhance the value of information. If high risks have an effective

treatment option, and therefore have the more efficient prevention technology, the “bad

news” from being a high risk is alleviated and information might still be valuable. We also

demonstrate that there are situations in the CD and ID cases where sufficiently efficient

treatment technologies can lead to a positive value of information.

This finding is related to Proposition 2 in Bajtelsmit and Thistle (2013) about the

                                                       13 In the absence of prevention, information has no clinical value but individuals are exposed to classification risk. Then the private value of

information with full insurance is given by for a positive risk premium 0, and is therefore negative.

Page 13: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

12  

  

incentive to acquire information in a competitive market for liability insurance. However, in

their analysis, heterogeneity in risk type corresponds to heterogeneity in loss size and

prevention technology is homogeneous across agents. Consequently, adverse selection cannot

be addressed as the insurer always observes amounts claimed. Proposition 1 is also related to

Doherty and Posey’s (1998) finding that the value of information can be positive or negative

and that a positive value of information stems from the treatment option for high risks. We

confirm their result and extend it to our more general setting. Even in situations of CD and ID

the opportunity to mitigate the risk can create informational value.

2.4 Level of Coverage and Optimal Effort

It is worthwhile to examine how the level of insurance coverage will influence the

optimal effort. In adverse-selection problems it is well known that the availability of coverage

might be restricted due to the informational asymmetry. This change in the availability of

insurance will typically be accompanied by a change in loss prevention effort.

For the moment, we take insurance coverage as exogenously given. (We relax this

assumption later in the analysis.) Consider an insurance policy with fixed coverage , and

actuarially fair premium . The objective function is then given by

1 1 ,

for ∈ , , . The first-order condition is

1

0,

where and are final wealth levels in the no-loss state and in the loss state, respectively.

Optimal prevention is chosen to balance the marginal benefit from the reduction of the loss

probability and the marginal benefit from reducing the insurance premium, and the marginal

cost of effort.

Let denote the solution of the first-order condition for a type individual with

coverage . Note that is the optimal effort level with full insurance. The implicit

Page 14: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

13  

  

function theorem yields

,

hence, sgn sgn . Now,

1 2

1 ′′ ′′ ,

so ∂ / ∂ is negative as long as the loss probability is less than 1/2 and the individual is

prudent.14 Under these circumstances higher insurance coverage induces the agent to exert a

lower prevention effort and substitute insurance for prevention. The marginal benefit from

prevention here consists of two components, the marginal benefit from the reduced loss

probability itself and the marginal benefit from a reduced insurance premium. Raising

insurance coverage has three marginal impacts. The marginal benefit from loss prevention will

be lower due to the increased coverage, but the marginal benefit of a lower insurance premium

is greater at a higher premium. The condition that the loss probability stays below 1/2 is

necessary and sufficient for the first effect to be dominant.15 However, there will also be an

income effect as more insurance coverage alters the wealth distribution which also affects the

marginal benefits regarding the premium reduction. In general, this third effect cannot be

signed unambiguously; prudence is sufficient to ensure it is negative.

3 The Value of Information

3.1 Preliminaries

Let us now assume that the insurer is unable to distinguish agents with respect to their

prevention technology. The insurer is able to monitor prevention effort, , but the efficiency

of prevention is private information. The question arises of how insurance can be offered in

                                                       14 Alternatively, a sufficient condition for negativity would be to assume a loss probability above 1/2 and imprudence which seems not

reasonable for the vast majority of applications. 15 As noted by Ehrlich and Becker (1972), the effect that observable prevention effort lowers the insurance premium can lead to comple-

mentarity between both risk mitigation instruments.

Page 15: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

14  

  

this set-up. In a Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) self-selection design, the equilibrium policies

( ∗, ∗ ) maximize expected utility for the low risks, subject to the self-selection constraint

and the individual policies satisfying breakeven (zero expected profit)

constraints. In addition, there is no other policy that, if offered, would earn non-negative

expected profit. The H-types will be offered full insurance, ∗ . The L-types can only be

offered partial insurance such that the H-types are just indifferent between their contract and

the L-type contract, i.e., the self-selection constraint is

. (4)

Since the choice of effort is observable, mimicry by H-types implies that they must

pretend to be L-types in terms of both the policy chosen and the effort level selected.

Therefore, we need to determine such that the H-types are unwilling to mimic the L-types.

Note that for 0 the LHS of (4) offers no insurance, and . For 1 the

left-hand side of (4) offers full coverage at the L-type rate, and . By

continuity there is at least one value of ∈ 0,1 where the self- selection constraint binds.16

Then H-types receive full and fairly priced insurance coverage and L-types obtain partial and

fairly priced insurance coverage that leaves H-types just indifferent between choosing and

choosing the L-type partial insurance contract ∗ and mimicking the L-type effort .

Hence, the amount of insurance for L-types will be endogenously determined via self-selection

to resolve the adverse selection problem.17

3.2 Unobservable Risk Type

We first consider the situation where informational status is observable but risk type is

not. For the health insurance example, this is the case in South Africa where insurers operate

                                                       16 In the cases CD and ID H-type indifference curves are flatter than L-type indifference curves, as in the standard model. For DD, where

H-type effort is higher than L-type effort for a given wealth profile, the resulting loss probability of high risks might be lower than the

resulting loss probability of L-types, which seems however an unrealistic case: The treatment option would be so efficient that the resulting

probability of disease is smaller than for healthy people. This can be excluded by assuming that does not decrease too quickly. For the

parameterization presented in the appendix the condition would be that be bounded from below. 17 We do not treat potential problems of equilibrium non-existence due to an insufficient share of high risks in the market in this paper, but

rather assume that all contract menus considered are stable equilibrium configurations.

Page 16: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

15  

  

under the Code of Conduct (Chapter 20) and may not ask or coerce the applicant to undergo

any genetic test in order to obtain insurance. However, all previous tests must be disclosed, i.e.,

the insurance company knows whether a test has been taken or not but not the result of the

test. Alternatively, the insurance company might pay for the tests, ans so knows the individual

is informed, but the test results are sent to the individual’s private physician for interpretation.

The insurer is then able to separately identify the informed and uninformed. The insurer

will offer the uninformed individuals full and fair insurance coverage and they choose effort

accordingly. For the informed H-types and L-types a self-selection design will be

implemented. Let ∈ 0,1 be the level of coverage where the self- selection constraint (4)

binds and be the level of effort chosen by an L-type under this policy. The endogenous

value of information is then given by

1

1

.

Comparing this to the situation where both informational status and risk type are observable,

we obtain

∗ 0.

This is positive since expected utility under full insurance and associated effort always exceeds

expected utility in a situation with partial insurance and associated effort. If the insurance

company can observe the consumers’ informational status, the value of information declines if

informed consumers cannot reveal their risk type.

Note also that under the assumptions of prudence and sufficiently small loss

probabilities, there is a substitution effect. The presence of H-types exerts a negative

externality on L-types as the availability of insurance coverage is restricted, which in turn

leads to substitution between insurance and loss prevention. This unambiguously raises

Page 17: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

16  

  

expenditures on care for L-types when risk type is not observable.18

Proposition 2 Let informational status be observable, then the value of

information can be posive or negative. The endogenous value of information is

larger if individuals are allowed to reveal their risk type when informed.

In a situation where individuals cannot undertake loss prevention measures, the value of

information when risk type is not observable will also be smaller than under complete

information and hence be negative.19 However, when information has clinical value, may

be positive. Consider for instance a situation where the insureds are highly risk-averse and

therefore place a high value on coverage. Hence, the insurance contract offered to L-types will

entail less than full coverage due to the information asymmetry, however, coverage will be

close to full due to high risk aversion. If in addition prevention is sufficiently effective, the

expected utility loss due to less coverage, which decreases the value of information, can be

partly compensated by investing more in prevention, so that the overall effect is not too strong.

Hence, the possibility that information has clinical value may alleviate the conclusion in the

literature that under this regime the value of information is always negative.

3.3 Unobservable Informational Status

In some situations, informational status is unobservable, but risk type can be credibly

revealed by the consumer. For example, there may be a consent law where results from genetic

testing can only be revealed with the consent of the consumer. Therefore, individuals will only

                                                       18 The marginal impact of the structure of prevention technology heterogeneity is difficult to assess. In the case of CD and DD, we still have

, as H-type and U-type utility is unaffected. However, under the conditions derived in section 2.4, L-types will exert more effort

compared to a situation with full insurance coverage. Hence, might no longer hold. 19 It is given by

2 1 1 ,

for the self-separating level of insurance coverage 1. With the same argument as above it will be lower than 1 due to lower expected

utility of L-types because the existence of unidentifiable H-types restricts the available coverage.

Page 18: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

17  

  

choose to reveal results if they are favorable.

Since insurers cannot directly observe information status, they need to correctly

anticipate consumers’ decisions. If they expect consumers to become informed, insurers will

offer to consumers who provide verification of a negative test result and to everyone

else. Individuals will choose to be tested since a positive result does not make them worse off

and a negative result makes them better off. The value of information is

0.

If they expect consumers will not become informed, insurers offer . Consumers get

the same policy whether or not they are informed, the value of information is zero and

consumers become informed. Becoming informed is a weakly dominant strategy.

Comparing this to the situation where both informational status and risk type are

observable, we obtain

∗ 0,

since full insurance is always preferred to partial insurance for a given loss probability. We see

that, given that the L-types can credibly reveal test results, moving from a regime where

informational status is observable to a regime where it is not increases the endogenous value of

information. This yields the following Propostion:

Proposition 3 If informational status is not observable but risk type can be

revealed by the consumer then the value of information is positive. The

endogenous value of information is higher if informational status is not

observable but risk type can be revealed by the consumer than when

informational status is observable.

The equilibrium depends on the assumption that individuals become informed if the

value of information is non-negative. If there is a small cost to testing, then there is an

equilibrium in which consumers remain uniformed. We consider this possiblility in the

welfare analysis. The result in the this proposition corresponds to Proposition 2 in Doherty and

Page 19: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

18  

  

Thistle (1996) where the value of information is shown to be non-negative if informational

status is unobservable or can be concealed.

3.4 Both Risk Type and Informational Status Unobservable

Finally, we analyze the situation where the insurance company cannot observe the

informational status of its customers and consumers cannot reveal their risk type even if they

wanted. This corresponds to a complete ban of genetic information in insurance. In this case

insurance companies are neither allowed to inquire whether tests have been taken, nor are

they allowed to use existing genetic information for rate-making. In some countries, there are

voluntary moratoria on the use of genetic information and in other countries there are

countries in which there is a government ban in place that completely prohibits the use of

genetic information.

Since insurers cannot directly observe information status, they again need to correctly

anticipate consumers‘ decisions. Under the ban consumers cannot provide verification of

their risk type. If they expect consumers to become informed, insurers offer and *LC ,

where *LC satisfies the self selection constraint VH( ) ≥ VH( *

LC ). Informed high risks

purchase , informed low risks purchase *LC and the uninformed also purchase *

LC . Then

the value of information is

∗ ∗ 0

since the self-selection constraint is binding and .

Individuals become informed since the value of informtion is non-negative. If they expect

onsumers will not become informed, insurers offer to everyone and the value of

information is again zero.

Proposition 4 Let informational status and risk type both be unobservable,

then the endogenous value of information zero.

Page 20: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

19  

  

Again, the equilibrium depends on the assumption that individuals become informed if

the value of information is non-negative. If there is a small cost to testing, then the

equilibrium in which consumers remain uniformed. We consider this possiblility in the

welfare analysis.

4 Welfare Implications

As shown in the last two sections, how policyholders’ information is used for

rate-making in insurance crucially impacts the value of information. After analyzing

informational incentives as implied by the contracts offered in equilibrium and the actions

taken by the individuals, we now focus on welfare implications of the different regulatory

regimes. When there is a duty to disclose the fact that a test has been taken and the test result,

the value of information is . When there is a code of conduct, so that the fact a test has been

taken, but not its results, must be revealed, then the value of information is . The value of

information is under a consent law, where test results can be credibly revealed, and is

under a ban on the use of any testing information.

The different policy regimes can be Pareto ranked. The welfare comparisons are ex

ante, that is, from the perspective of an uninformed individual. Consider, for example, the

comparison of the duty to disclose, where the value of information is I1, with the code of

conduct, where the value of information is I2. There are four cases, depending on whether

the value of information is positive or negative under each regime. The cases are summarized

in Table 1. In Case A, the value of information is negative in both regimes. In Case A both

regimes yield the same expected utility. In Case B, I1 < 0 while I2 >0. The fact that I1 < 0

implies that VU( UC ) > θHVH( HC ) + θLVL( LC ) > θHVH( HC ) + θLVL(CL*), so that individuals are

better off under the duty to disclose. In Case C, I1 > 0 implies the first inequality is reversed,

VU( UC ) < θHVH( HC ) + θLVL( LC ) so that individuals are better off under the duty to disclose.

Under Case D, since *LC provides partial coverage, we have θHVH( HC ) + θLVL( LC ) > θHVH( HC

Page 21: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

20  

  

) + θLVL( *LC ), so that individuals are again better off under the duty to disclose.

Table 1. Comparison of Duty to Disclose and Code of Conduct

Case Duty to Disclose Code of Conduct Policy

A I1 < 0, I2 < 0 VU( UC ) VU( UC ) Duty to Disclose

B I1 < 0, I2 > 0 VU( UC ) VH( HC ),VL( *LC ) Duty to Disclose

C I1 > 0, I2 < 0 VH( HC ),VL( LC ) VU( UC ) Duty to Disclose

D I1 > 0, I2 > 0 VH( HC ),VL( LC ) VH( HC ),VL( *LC ) Duty to Disclose

Proposition 5. The policy regimes can be ex ante Pareto ranked, with the duty

to disclose preferred to the code of conduct and consent regimes which are in

turn preferred to the ban on the use of information. The code of conduct and

consent regimes are non-comparable.

The remainder of the proof, which consists of case-by-case analyses of the pairwise

comparisons of the policy alternatives, is given in the Appendix.

The result in Proposition 5 can be compared to the outcome when information has no

clinical value (pH and pL are fixed). From Crocker and Snow (1992) and Doherty and Thistle

(1996), we know that the observability of consumer’s information status is critical in

determining the value of information. Under the duty to disclose and code of conduct

regimes, consumers‘ information status is observable. Under both of these regimes, the value

of information is negative (I1 < I2 < 0), so that individuals receive expected utility VU( UC ).

Under the voluntary discolsure and ban regimes, consumers‘ information status in not

observable. Under the voluntary disclosure regime, the value of information is positive (I3 >

0), and individuals receive expected utility of either VH( HC ) orVL( LC ). Finally, under a ban

on the use of genetic tests, the value of information is zero (I4 = 0). Assuming individuals

Page 22: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

21  

  

become informed, they receive either VH( HC ) orVL(CL*). Since I1 < I2 < 0 and *LC offers

partial coverage, the duty to disclose and code of conduct regimes are Pareto superior to the

consent law, which in turn is Pareto superior to the ban.

5 Discussion and Conclusion

We analyze alternative public polices toward insurers use of genetic tests. The

increasing availability and falling cost of genetic tests for a wide variety of different conditions

will change the informational environment within which insurance markets operate. Some

fear widepread “genetic discrimination“ if insurance companies are allowed to use genetic test

results to underwrite policies. On the other hand, insurance companies fear “regulatory

adverse selection“ if they cannot use genetic information but individuals can make insurance

purchase decisions based on genetic test results. There is some evidence that both

phenomena are occuring. There is a wide variety of regulatory regimes regarding the use of

genetic test information depending on the juristiction and on the insurance market. We

consider four policy alternatives, a duty to disclose, a code of conduct, consent law and an

information ban. All of these regulatory alternatives are in use in at least some insurance

markets in some juristictions.

We assume there is heterogeneity in loss prevention technology and individuals may or

may not be informed about their technology. This implies there is the potential for adverse

selection along the efficiency dimension of prevention. The inclusion of loss prevention seems

natural in many circumstances. If a genetic test reveals positive or negative results regarding a

specific mutation, individuals will adjust their lifestyle to the information acquired. There are

a large number of genetic tests that indicate an increased risk for diseases such as heart attack,

hypertenion and diabetes where lifestyle has an important role in determining whether the

individual will become symptomatic.

We find that there are two main factors that determine the value of information and

Page 23: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

22  

  

thereby insurance market outcomes. These factors are the observability of consumers‘

information status and the clinical value of information. If information status is observable,

then insurance companies can condition their policy offerings based on whether the consumer

is informed or not. This exacerbates the problem of classification risk. Then the value of

information is negative unless the information has sufficent clinical value. The regulatory

regimes where insurers can observe information status are the duty to disclose and the code of

conduct. If information status is not observable, insurers cannot condition their policy

offerings based on whether the individual is informed or not but must offer the same policies

to all. Then the value of information is non-negative whether or not informtion has clinical

value. The regulatory regimes where insurers cannot observe information status are the

consent law and the information ban These regimes provide incentives for, or at least do not

discourage, testing.

We are able to ex ante Pareto rank the policy regimes based on the insurance market

outcomes that they lead to. When information has no clinical value, the duty to disclose and

code of conduct produce the outcome where individuals choose not to take tests and purchase

the pooled full coverage policy. This outcome is Pareto superior to that of the consent law,

where individuals choose to be tested and purchase risk-type specific full coverage policies.

The consent law is in turn Pareto superior to the information ban, which leads to an outcome

where individuals choose to be tested and choose from a separating menu of insurance policies.

When information has clinical value, the duty to disclose is ex ante Pareto superior to the code

of conduct and consent law. The code of conduct and consent law are Pareto

non-comparable, but both are preferred to the information ban. The clinical value of

information does have an effect on the Pareto ranking of the policies. But regardless of

whether information has clinical value or not, the duty to disclose is at least weakly Pareto

superior to the other policy alternatives. Regardless of whether information has clincal value

or not, the information ban is Pareto inferior to all of the other policies and is the least

desireable policy alternative.

Page 24: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

23  

  

References

Alary, D., C. Gollier, and N. Treich. 2013. “The Effect of Ambiguity Aversion on Insurance and

Self-protection.” The Economic Journal 123 (573): 1188–1202.

Bajtelsmit, V., and P. Thistle. 2013. “Liability, Insurance and the Incentive to Obtain

Information about Risk.” Working paper, University of Nevada Las Vegas.

Barigozzi, F., and D. Henriet. 2011. “Genetic Information: Comparing Alternative Regulatory

Approaches when Prevention Matters.” Journal of Public Economic Theory 13(1): 23–46.

Bundorf, K., B. Herring, and M. Pauly. 2010. “Health Risk, Income and Employment-based

Heallth Insurance.” Forum for Health Economics and Public Policy 13(2): 1–33.

Cohen, A., and P. Siegleman. 2010. “Testing for Adverse Selection in Insurance Markets.” The

Journal of Risk and Insurance 77(1): 39–84.

Colditz, G., and A. Frazier. 1995. “Models of Breast Cancer Show that Risk is Set by Events of

Early Life: Prevention Efforts must Shift Focus.” Cancer Epidemiology Biomarkers &

Prevention 4(5): 567–571.

Crocker, K., and A. Snow. 1986. “The Efficiency Effects of Categorical Discrimination in the

Insurance Industry.” Journal of Political Economy 94(2): 321–344.

Crocker, K., and A. Snow. 1992. “The Social Value of Hidden Information in Adverse Selection

Economies.” Journal of Public Economics 48(3): 317–347.

Crocker, K., and A. Snow. 2013. “The Theory of Risk Classification.” pp. 281–313 in Handbook

of Insurance, G. Dionne (ed.) New York: Springer Science + Businessss Media.

Doherty, N., and L. Posey. 1998. “On the Value of a Checkup: Adverse Selection, Moral Hazard

and the Value of Information.” The Journal of Risk and Insurance 65(2): 189–211.

Doherty, N., and P. Thistle. 1996. “Adverse Selection with Endogenous Information in

Insurance Markets.” Journal of Public Economics 63(1): 83–102.

Page 25: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

24  

  

Ehrlich, I., and G. Becker. 1972. “Market Insurance, Self-insurance, and Self-protection.”

Journal of Political Economy 80(4): 623–648.

Einav, L., A. Finkelstein, S. Ryan, P. Schrimpf, and M. Cullen. 2013. “Selection on Moral

Hazard in Health Insruance.” American Economic Review 103(1): 178–219.

Finkelstein, A,. and J. Poterba. 2002. “Selection Effects in the United Kingdom Annuities

Market.” Economic Journal 112(476): 28–50.

Finkelstein, A. and J. Poterba. 2004. “Adverse Selection in Insurance Markets: Policyholder

Evidence from the U.K. Annuity Market.” Journal of Political Economy 112(1): 183–208.

Handel, B. 2013. “Adverse Selection and Inertia in Insurance Markets: When Nudging Hurts.”

American Economic Review 103(7): 2643–2682.

Garidel-Thoron, T. 2005. “Welfare-improving Asymmetric Information in Dynamic Insurance

Markets.” Journal of Political Econmy 113(1): 121–150.

He, D. 2009. “The Life Insurance Market: Asymmetric Information Revisited.” Journal of

Public Economics 93(9): 1090–1097.

Hoy, M. 1989. “The Value of Screening Mechanisms under Alternative Insurance

Possibilities.” Journal of Public Economics 39(2): 177–206.

Jewitt, I. 1988. “Justifying the First-order Approach to Principal-agent Problems.”

Econometrica 56(5): 1177–1190.

Joly, Y., M. Braker, and M. Le Huyhn. 2010. “Genetic Discrimination in Private Insurance:

Global Persepectives.” New Genetics and Society 29(4): 351–368.

Milgrom, P., and N. Stokey. 1982.” Information, Trade and Common Knowledge.” Journal of

Economic Theory 26(1): 17–27.

Mossin, J. 1968. “Aspects of Rational Insurance Purchasing.” Journal of Political Economy

76(4): 553–568.

Page 26: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

25  

  

National Conference of State Legislatures (2008a) Genetics and health insurance state

anti-discrimination laws, http://www.ncsl.org/research/health/genetic-non

discrimination-in-health-insurance-laws.aspx (last visited June 20, 2014)

National Conference of State Legislatures (2008b) Genetics and life, disability and long-term

care insurance, http://www.ncsl.org/research/health/genetic-nondiscrimination-

laws-in-life-disability.aspx (last visited June 20, 2014).

Oster, E., I. Shoulson., K. Quaid, and E. Dorsey. 2010. “Genetic Adverse Selection: Evidence

from Long-term Care and Huntington Disease.” Journal of Public Economics 94(11):

1041–1050.

Otlowski, M., S. Taylor, and Y. Bombard. 2012. “Genetic Discrimination: International

Perpectives.” Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 13: 433–454.

Palella Jr, F., K. Delaney, A. Moorman, M. Loveless, J. Fuhrer, G. Satten, D. Aschman, and S.

Holmberg. 1998. “Declining Morbidity and Mortality among Patients with Advanced

Human Immunodeficiency Virus Infection.” New England Journal of Medicine 338(13):

853–860.

Rogerson, W. 1985. “The First-order Approach to Principal-agent Problems.” Econometrica

53(6): 1357–1367.

Rothschild, C. 2011. “The Efficiency of Categorical Discrimination in Insurance Markets.” The

Journal of Risk and Insurance 78(2): 267–285.

Rothschild, M., and J. Stiglitz. 1976. “Equilibrium in Competitive Insurance Markets: An Essay

on the Economics of Imperfect Information.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics

90(4):629–649.

Savage, L. 1954. The Foundation of Statistics. John Wiley & Sons, Oxford, England.

Snow, A. 2011. “Ambiguity Aversion and the Propensities for Self-insurance and

Self-protection.” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 42(1): 27–43.

Page 27: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

26  

  

Strohmenger, R., and A. Wambach. 2000. “Adverse Selection and Categorical Discrimination

in the Health Insurance Markets: The Effects of Genetic Tests.” Journal of Health

Economics 19(2): 197–218.

Tabarrok, A. 1994. “Genetic Testing: An Economic and Contractarian Analysis.” Journal of

Health Economics 13(1): 75–91.

Thompson, D., D. Easton, and the Breast Cancer Linkage Consortium. 2002. “Variation in

BRCA1 Cancer Risks by Mutation Position.” Cancer Epidemiology Biomarkers &

Prevention 11(4): 329–336.

Thune, I., T. Brenn, E. Lund, and M. Gaard. 1997. “Physical Activity and the Risk of Breast

Cancer.” New England Journal of Medicine 336(18): 1269–1275.

Warheit, D., C. Sayes, K. Reed, and K. Swain. 2008. “Health Effects Related to Nanoparticle

Exposures: Environmental, Health and Safety Considerations for Assessing Hazards and

Risks.” Pharmacology & Therapeutics 120(1): 35–42.

Zick, C., C. Mathers, J. Roberts, R. Cook-Deegan, R. Pokorski, and R. Green. 2005. “Genetic

Testing for Alzheimer’s Diease and its Impact on Insurance Purchasing.” Health Affairs

24(2): 483–490.

Page 28: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

27  

  

Appendix

6 Value of Information without Insurance

Let us assume for simplicity that ′ for a constant ∈ . 0 resembles the

case CD, 0 the case ID, and 0 the case DD. Integration yields

′ 0 0 .

Taking as given, we obtain

0 0 ,

0 0 .

Rearranging (2) yields

∗ ∗ ∗

∗ ∗ ∗ .

Denoting by the value of information if ′ , we know that 0 0 .

Furthermore, as prevention is optimal and satisfies (1), we can exploit the envelope theorem to

obtain

0,

∗ ,

∗ .

Therefore, the marginal effect of a variation of on the value of information is given by

∗ ∗ ,

which is zero for 0, positive for 0, and negative for 0. Applying the implicit

function theorem, we can also calculate the second derivative to find that

∗ ∗

∗ ∗ .

For the special case of CD, i.e., 0, we find that

′′ ∗ 0, (5)

confirming that 0 0 is a local minimum. It is also a global minimum, as there are no

Page 29: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

28  

  

zeros of ∂ / ∂ except 0. The following picture illustrates a possible shape of .

Figure 1: Shape of the value of information function without insurance

Hence, it is clear that information about type is always valuable, as it allows individuals to

adjust their behavior in terms of risk management to the information acquired.

7 Value of Information with Full Information

Again, we choose the specification ′ to facilitate the calculation of marginal

effects of altering the structure of prevention technology heterogeneity. Prevention

technologies are as before. By use of the envelope theorem, we obtain

0,

′ ,

′ ,

Hence, we obtain for the endogenous value of information

Page 30: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

29  

  

′ ′

Under CD and DD, we have that , hence and therefore

∂ / ∂ is negative. Due to continuity, it will also be negative for a range ∈ 0, . Hence,

the value of information increases when moving from ID over CD to DD. Let us illustrate a

possible shape of in the following figure.

Figure 2: Shape of the value of information function with full insurance

The solid line represents a scenario where the value of information is always negative. Here

classification risk prevails and insurance deters information acquisition which is due to rather

inefficient prevention opportunities. The dotted line represents a situation where for some low

values of information is valuable and for high values it is not. This is a situation where

efficient prevention opportunities for high risks improve on the value of information and help

to overcome the deterring effect of classification risk. The dashed line represents a situation

where even for some positive values of information is valuable. Efficient risk mitigation

opportunities can alleviate classification risk up to the point that the private value of

information becomes positive, even if high risk individuals are equipped with the less

Page 31: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

30  

  

favorable prevention technology.

8 Numerical Example for a Positive Value of Information in the

Benchmark Case

In this section we provide a numerical example for a positive value of information if both

informational status and risk type are observable. We introduce quadratic loss prevention

technologies, discuss the case of risk neutrality with linear prevention costs and show how it

extends to the general set-up introduced above.

8.1 Quadratic Loss Preventione Technology

For analytical convenience we standardize effort to the unit interval ∈ 0,1 . Let loss

probability be given by with ∈ 0,1 , ∈ 1 , 2 and

∈ ,1 . Hereby 0 ensures that ′′ 2 0∀ and 1 entails that

the interval for is nonempty. 1 renders the parameter region for

nonempty and 2 lets ′ 2 0∀ . Finally, and 1

ascertain that 1 0 and 0 1 respectively.

We now incorporate prevention technology heterogeneity by specifying

and ,

with 0 1. Furthermore, shall be picked from the interval 1 , 2

and from the interval ,1 . We impose the condition 2 1 to ensure

that the first interval will be nonempty.20 For ease of exposition we define :

and then .

8.2 The Value of Information under Risk Neutrality and Linear Prevention Cost

Let us assume that utility is given by resembling risk neutral decision making

                                                       20 The second is nonempty in any case then.

Page 32: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

31  

  

and that prevention cost be given by for ∈ 0,1 . In this tractable case we obtain

for the endogenous value of information if both informational status and risk type are

observable.

The optimal effort levels maximize and

therefore satisfy the first order conditions 2 1 0.21 They are given by

. Let be contained in the open interval , , which is nonempty in

any case. This ensures that we only consider interior maxima and the first order approach is

legitimate.

Plugging the effort levels into the expression for , we obtain

0.

Hence, in this case the endogenous value of information is always positive which means that

uninformed individuals will from an ex-ante perspective always prefer to obtain information

and to adjust effort accordingly to staying uninformed and exerting effort based on average

prevention technology. The reason is that risk-neutral agents are not affected by classification

risk.

                                                       21 The second order conditions are satisfied, 2 0.

Page 33: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

32  

  

8.3 Extension to the General Model

In order to construct a numerical example with risk aversion and convex prevention cost

we use a parameterization that nests risk neutrality and linear cost of effort. Therefore let

and with 0 and 1 . The case above corresponds to the

choice , 0,1 . Now we can express the value of information as a function of these new

variables, , , and it is straightforward that is a continuous function of , .

From above we know that 0,1 0 and therefore we find an open neighborhood of 0,1

where it is still positive. Picking parameters 0 and 1 from that open environment

we obtain the example.

Appendix 9 Proof of Propostion 5

Recall that under the duty to disclose the value of information is I1, under the code of conduct,

value of information is , under the consent law the value of information is , and under a

ban on the use of test information the value of information is .

Table A1 compares the duty to disclose with the consent law. In Case A, the fact that I1 < 0

implies VU( UC ) > HVH( HC ) + LVL( LC ). This implies the the duty to disclose regime is

preferred. In Case B, where I1 > 0, the insurance market outcomes are the same under both

regimes and individuals not worse off under the duty to disclose.

Table A1. Comparison of Duty to Disclose and Consent Law

Case Duty to Disclose Consent Law Policy

A I1 < 0, I3 > 0 VU( UC ) VH( HC ),VL( LC ) Duty to Disclose

B I1 > 0, I3 > 0 VH( HC ),VL( LC ) VH( HC ),VL( LC ) Duty to Disclose

Table A2 compares the duty to disclose and the ban. In Case A, the fact that I1 < 0 implies that

VU( UC ) > HVH( HC ) + LVL( LC ) > HVH( HC ) + LVL(CL*), so that individuals are better off

Page 34: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

33  

  

under the duty to disclose. In Case B, the fact that LC offers full coverage while CL* offers

partial coverage implies that individuals are better off under the duty to disclose.

Table A2. Comparison of Duty to Disclose and Ban

Case Duty to Disclose Ban Policy

A I1 < 0, I4 = 0 VU( UC ) VH( HC ),VL(CL*) Duty to Disclose

B I1 > 0, I4 = 0 VH( HC ),VL( LC ) VH( HC ),VL(CL*) Duty to Disclose

Table A3 compares the code of conduct and the consent law. In Case A, I2 < 0 implies that VU(

UC ) > HVH( HC ) + LVL(CL*) and I3 > 0 implies that HVH( HC ) + LVL( LC ) > VU(CU*).

However, it cannot be determined whether VU( UC ) or HVH( HC ) + LVL( LC ) is larger.

Which policy is preferred depends on the underlying parameters. In Case B, VL( LC ) > VL(CL*)

implies that the Consent law is preferred. The code of conduct and the consent law are Pareto

non-comparable.

Table A3. Comparison of Code of Conduct and Consent Law

Case Code of Conduct Consent Law Policy

A I2 < 0, I3 > 0 VU( UC ) VH( HC ),VL( LC ) Indeterminate

B I2 > 0, I3 > 0 VH( HC ),VL(CL*) VH( HC ),VL( LC ) Consent Law

Table A4 compares the code of conduct and the ban. In Case A, the fact that I2 < 0 implies VU(

UC ) > HVH( HC ) + LVL( LC ) > HVH( HC ) + LVL(CL**), so that individuals are better off under

the duty to disclose. In Case B, individuals are not worse off under the code of conduct than

the ban.

Table A4. Comparison Code of Conduct and Ban

Page 35: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

34  

  

Case Code of Conduct Ban Policy

A I2 < 0, I4 = 0 VU( UC ) VH( HC ),VL(CL*) Code of Conduct

B I2 > 0, I4 = 0 VH( HC ),VL(CL*) VH( HC ),VL(CL*) Code of Conduct

Table A5 compares the consent law and the ban. In the only case, the fact that LC provides

full coverage while CL** provides partial coverage implies the consent law is preferred.

Table A5. Comparison of Consent Law and Ban

Case Consent Law Ban Policy

A I3 > 0, I4 = 0 VH( HC ),VL( LC ) VH( HC ),VL(CL*) Consent Law

Taken together, the results from the text and the analyses of Tables A1 and A2 imply the

duty to disclose is Pareto superior to the other policy regimes. The results in the text and the

analyses of Tables A3 and A4 imply that the other policies are Pareto superior to the ban on the

use of information.

The equilibria under the consent law and under the ban depend on the assumption that

individuals become informed if the cost of information is zero. We now consider the

outcome when there are small information costs. This implies that, under the consent law,

there is a second equilibrium where individuals remain uninformed. Under the ban the

unique equilibium is for individuals to remain uninformed. In both cases, individuals receive

expected utility VU( UC ).

First, consider the comparison of the consent law with the duty to disclose. If I1 < 0,

then the consent law and duty to disclose yield the same expected utlity. If I1 > 0, individuals

receive either VH( HC ) or VL( LC ). Then I1 > 0 implies HVH( HC ) + LVL( LC ) > VU( UC ), and

the duty to disclose is preferred. Now consider the comparison of the consent law with the

code of conduct. If I2 < 0, then the code of conduct and the consent law both yield expected

Page 36: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

35  

  

utility VU( UC )> If I2 > 0 individuals receive either VH( HC ) orVL(CL*). Again, I2 > 0 imples

HVH( HC ) + LVL(CL*) > VU( UC ) and the code of conduct is preferred. The comparison of the

duty to disclose and the code of conduct with the ban yields the same results, both are

preferred to the ban. The welfare analysis is not sensitive to the assumption that individuals

become informed if the value of information is non-negative.

Page 37: Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and … · Endogenous Information, Adverse Selection, and Prevention: ... Adverse Selection, and Prevention: Implications ... a reasonable

36  

  

Acknowledgment

We would like to thank Shinichi Kamiya, Jana Mühlnickel and Jörg Schiller for their

helpful comments on earlier versions of this article. We also thank participants at the Research

Seminar of Riskcenter at the University of Barcelona, the Hamburg-München-Hohenheimer

Insurance Economics Colloquium 2012, the American Risk and Insurance Association Annual

Meeting 2012, the Jahrestagung des Vereins für Socialpolitik 2012, the 39th Seminar of the

European Group of Risk and Insurance Economists, the 3rd CEQURA Conference on

Advances in Financial and Insurance Risk Management, the Western Risk and Insurance

Association Annual Meeting 2013, the Allied Social Science Associations Annual Meeting

2013, the Annual Meeting of the Deutscher Verein für Versicherungswissenschaft 2013 and

the 2013 Risk Theory Society Annual Meeting for valuable comments, which led to significant

improvements. Any remaining errors are, of course, our own.