16
This article was downloaded by: [Colorado College] On: 30 October 2014, At: 17:17 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Sport, Ethics and Philosophy Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rsep20 Disability or Extraordinary Talent—Francesco Lentini (Three Legs) Versus Oscar Pistorius (No Legs) Ivo van Hilvoorde & Laurens Landeweerd Published online: 18 Jul 2008. To cite this article: Ivo van Hilvoorde & Laurens Landeweerd (2008) Disability or Extraordinary Talent—Francesco Lentini (Three Legs) Versus Oscar Pistorius (No Legs), Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, 2:2, 97-111, DOI: 10.1080/17511320802221778 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17511320802221778 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions

Disability or Extraordinary Talent—Francesco Lentini (Three Legs) Versus Oscar Pistorius (No Legs)

  • Upload
    laurens

  • View
    215

  • Download
    2

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

This article was downloaded by: [Colorado College]On: 30 October 2014, At: 17:17Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

Sport, Ethics and PhilosophyPublication details, including instructions for authors andsubscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rsep20

Disability or ExtraordinaryTalent—Francesco Lentini (Three Legs)Versus Oscar Pistorius (No Legs)Ivo van Hilvoorde & Laurens LandeweerdPublished online: 18 Jul 2008.

To cite this article: Ivo van Hilvoorde & Laurens Landeweerd (2008) Disability or ExtraordinaryTalent—Francesco Lentini (Three Legs) Versus Oscar Pistorius (No Legs), Sport, Ethics andPhilosophy, 2:2, 97-111, DOI: 10.1080/17511320802221778

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17511320802221778

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the“Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis,our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as tothe accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinionsand views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Contentshould not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sourcesof information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims,proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever orhowsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arisingout of the use of the Content.

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms &Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT—

FRANCESCO LENTINI (THREE LEGS) VERSUS

OSCAR PISTORIUS (NO LEGS)

Ivo van Hilvoorde and Laurens Landeweerd

It seems fairly straightforward to describe what should and should not count as a disability into

two separate and opposing categories. In this paper we will challenge this assumption and

critically reflect on the narrow relations between the concepts of ‘talent’ and ‘disability’. We further

relate such matters of terminology and classification to issues of justice in what is conceived of as

disability sport. Do current systems of classification do justice to the performances of disabled

athletes? Is the organisation of a just and fair competition similar for abled as it is for disabled

sport? Two cases (of Francesco Lentini and Oscar Pistorius) will be explored to further illustrate the

complexities of these questions, in particular when related to notions of normality and

extraordinary performances.

Resumen

Parece un asunto bastante simple el describir lo que deberıa y no deberıa contar como discapacidad

en dos categorıas distintas y opuestas. En este artıculo desafiaremos esta suposicion y reflejaremos

crıticamente sobre las estrechas relaciones que hay entre los conceptos de ‘talento’ y ‘incapacidad.’

Ademas conectamos tales asuntos de terminologıa y clasificacion con asuntos de justicia en lo que se

entiende como deporte discapacitado. ¿Hacen justicia estas maneras actuales de clasificacion a las

actuaciones de los atletas minusvalidos? ¿Es la organizacion de una competicion justa parecida para

el deporte con y sin discapacidad? Dos casos (el de Francesco Lentini y el de Oscar Pistorius) seran

explorados para ilustrar mejor las complejidades de estas cuestiones, en particular cuando se las

relaciona con nociones de normalidad y actuaciones extraordinarias.

Zusammenfassung

Die Unterteilung von Behinderung und Nicht-Behinderung in zwei getrennte gegensatzliche

Kategorien erscheint etwas zu vereinfachend zu sein. In unserem Artikel wollen wir diese

Unterteilung infrage stellen und kritische Reflexionen zur engen Verbindung der Begriffe ,Talent’

und ,Behinderung’ anbringen. Des Weiteren wollen wir derartige terminologische Aspekte sowie

Probleme der Klassifikation mit Fragen nach Gerechtigkeit im sogenannten Behindertensport in

Verbindung bringen. Ist die gegenwartige Leitungsklassen-Einteilung behinderter Athleten

gerecht? Ist die Organisation gerechter und fairer Wettkampfe Nicht-Behinderter mit derjenigen

Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, Vol. 2, No. 2, August 2008

ISSN 1751-1321 print/1751-133X online/08/020097–15

ª 2008 Taylor & Francis

DOI: 10.1080/17511320802221778

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

fur Behinderte vergleichbar? Zur Veranschaulichung der Komplexitat dieser Fragen werden zwei

Fallbeispiele (Francesco Lentini und Oscar Pistorius) herangezogen, insbesondere in Bezug auf

Begriffe wie Normalitat und besondere Leistung.

KEYWORDS disability; super-ability; definition and ethics of (disability) sports; naturalness;

artificiality; enhancement; prostheses; Lentini; Pistorius

Introduction

The highly talented and the disabled person seem, at first sight, to be living in

completely different worlds. Gifted persons will be celebrated because of their culturally

valued talents and may enjoy a lifetime of social advantages as a result. But instead of

being praised for their deviation, a disabled person may need to adapt to a world that is

primarily built around standards of normality and even experience a lifetime characterised

by stigmatising and discrimination. Therefore, there seems to be a sharp contrast between

the athlete as a cultural hero and icon and the disabled person that needs extra attention

or care; the one incorporating the peak of normality, human functioning at its best, the

other often representing the opposite. The concepts of ‘talent’ and ‘handicap’, however,

bear certain family resemblances. Both concepts of dis-ability and super-ability are based

upon deviations from standards of normality.

Disabilities are seen as a dysfunctional deviations from normality. The division

between the dysfunctional and the healthy is often built from a bio-statistical notion of

normal functioning. Though a dysfunction can also be the result of an accident, these

deviations are in many cases the result of genetic inheritance and mutations. In the

literature there is an extended discussion on how to distinguish between impairment,

disability and handicap, a classical categorisation (cf. Sherill 2004a; Ustun 2004). The

semantic jungle that followed from this discussion still obstructs clear debates on disability

rights and public duties. We will try to avoid touching upon this jungle by merely using

the term disability as a generic term.

Athletes with a disability are classified within the following disability categories (cf.

Tweedy 2002; IPC 2006; Kioumourtzoglou and Politis 2004; Klenck and Gebke 2007;

DePauw and Gavron 2005):

. Wheelchair athletes;

. Athletes with cerebral palsy;

98 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

. Amputees;

. Athletes with total or partial loss of sight;

. Athletes with intellectual disability and learning difficulties; and

. ‘Les autres’ disabilities (a complex ‘all the rest category’)

Both the concept of ‘sport’ and ‘disability’ have their own specific distinctions and internal

differentiations, such that a combination of both gives rise to all sorts of complexities and

new issues, in particular regarding definition and fairness. The distinction between

different disabilities listed above is only relevant for disability sports. There is no medical

categorisation of disabilities that fits smoothly and logically into the context of sport. What

is considered a disability in ‘regular life’ may even become an advantage in the context of

elite sports. In basketball, extreme height is considered to be an advantage rather than a

disability, while possibly posing a disability, albeit slight, in daily life. A huge sumo wrestler

may have problems travelling on a bus, but at the same time be celebrated as a Japanese

sport hero. A genetic mutation that corresponds to extreme muscle growth can be

classified in one case as a high-risk potential for disablement and in another as a

precondition of being exceptionally talented. It appears that in many ways the scales on

which one ranks human traits are not value-neutral, or are at least established from a very

specific (albeit hidden) perspective. This poses the question whether one can neutrally or

objectively define what should count as a disability (or impairment), what as a trait within

a normal variance and what as a super-ability.

Several authors have shed light on the philosophical dimensions of classification,

categorisation, merit and justice related to disability sports (cf. Bowen 2002; Wheeler 2004;

Pickering 2005; Jones and Howe 2005). Categorisation and classification are ongoing

processes and discussions need to be continued, not least because our views on disabilities

change and evolve, as does the technology to compensate for certain disabilities. From an

egalitarian perspective one can strive for the neutralisation of luck and reward specific

talents (cf. Bailey 2007). On the other hand, specific distinctions between (severity of)

disabilities can be drawn in such a way that extreme efforts are awarded in order to

compensate for a lack of talent. Categorisations within disability sports appear to be the site

of an ‘ongoing struggle’ to find the right balance between a good competition based on

differences in talent on the one hand and the demonstration of excellence within a group

with relevant similar skills on the other. We will try to show that this tension eventually also

bears relevance for the distinction between elite sports and disability sports.

Defining Disability: Normative or Neutral

The concept of disease and disability was heavily debated in the 1970s and 1980s by

Christopher Boorse (1975, 1976, 1977) and H. Tristam Engelhardt and S.F. Spicker (1974).

Boorse looked upon the difference between health and diseases as a natural given, basing

his stance on a statistically derived definition of normal and abnormal function. Health was

therefore defined as ‘the ability to perform all typical physiological functions with at least

typical efficiency level’ (Boorse 1977, 542). Correspondingly, disease is any state that

interferes with this normal functioning. In Boorse’s words:

An organism is healthy at any moment in proportion as it is not diseased; and a disease is

a type of internal state of the organism which (i) interferes with the performance of some

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? 99

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

natural function—i.e., some species-typical contribution to survival and reproduction—

characteristic of the organism’s age; and (ii) is not simply in the nature of the species, i.e.,

is either atypical of the species or, if typical, mainly due to environmental causes. (Boorse

1976, 62)

This means that Boorse’s account of the concepts of health and disease is heavily

dependent of an objective image of ‘nature’, ‘natural’ or ‘normal functioning’.

Among others, Tristam Engelhardt criticises this naturalist approach to the

conceptualisation of diseases. In his opinion, one cannot analyse concepts of health and

disease solely on the basis of the biological nature of the organism and its functioning. The

social context needs to be taken into account as well. In this normative approach diseases

are normative constructions with a specific socio-cultural background, rather than natural

givens within a bio-statistical framework. In the words of Toulmin, supporting Engelhardt’s

view,

The nature of health is, at one and the same time, a matter for empirical discovery and a

matter of evaluative decision. We refine our sense of how the human body ought to

work, and ought to be helped to work, in the course of and in the light of our empirical

studies of how it does in fact work. (Toulmin 1975, 51)

So, according to the normativists, what counts as a disability and what not is as much

dependent on socio-cultural values and decisions as on medical standards. Essentially, within

this perspective, the latter are even to be seen as a subcategory of the former. The discussion

between the bio-statistical and the normative or contextual definition of diseases and

disabilities has continued up to now. As has been put forward by Moser (2006, 374), ‘Being

disabled is not something one is by definition, but something one becomes in relation to

specific environments. Disability is enacted and ordered in situated and quite specific ways.’

People can become disabled by the environment or by specific (lack of) technologies. A

person with an average intellectual ability may ‘become’ disabled in an environment with just

highly gifted people. An elite athlete who chooses not to use performance-enhancing

substances may become dis-abled in a context in which the use of doping is ‘normalised’. In

these cases (and in many similar cases) one can argue that one is free to choose the ‘right’

environment in which specific qualities can be shown and compared to ‘relevant others’. The

person that one wants to be cannot be detached from the financial rewards that are attached

to specific practices, as well as the status and meanings that are intrinsically related to the

community of superior athletic performances. The valuation of human performances cannot

be effected irrespective of a social-cultural hierarchy, ranking specific talents and making

differences between highly valued talents (e.g. the ability to throw a ball in a basket) and less

valued talents (e.g. running on prostheses).

New technologies such as prostheses apparently help to turn disabled people into

‘normal’ subjects. This may explain the urgent wish of Oscar Pistorius, an athlete who

usually competes in races for disabled athletes, to become part of the ‘normal Olympic

Games’. What may be considered ‘normalisation’ in the context of daily life is at least

ambivalent in the context of elite sport. Running on prostheses may be defined as crucial

for the specific talent that is tested in a competition against ‘relevant others’: athletes who

have the ability to show a similar talent. The wish of a disabled person to become part of

‘normal’ elite sport may be framed as a way of ‘inclusion’ or ‘integration’, but this at the

100 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

same time reproduces new inequalities and asymmetries between performances of able

and dis-abled bodied.

If one is to enhance the traits needed to function optimally in society, one takes that

society as a universal standard against which the functioning of people is measured, while

one could also say that within a just society people should not be made to follow the

dictations of a larger ideal. When one defines what counts as a disability in a normative

rather than a descriptive fashion the notion of a disability also becomes political. In

contemporary (Western) democracies, each citizen is presupposed to be self-reliant within

a competitive capitalist environment. Therefore, society is set up to deal primarily with an

idealised version of the ‘average person’ (Taylor and Mykitiuk 2001, 1). Anything that falls

below this picture of the ideal citizen is treated as abnormal. In many respects, however,

the ideal of the elite sportsman has all characteristics of abnormality as well. But in

contrast to the disabled, the elite sportsman is not considered a political and medical

burden. So on the one hand society invests quite willingly in the ‘abnormal’ super-abilities

of the elite sportsman, while on the other it does this only reluctantly, and from a ethics of

inclusion, with respect to the disabled. In the case of disabilities, one wants to eradicate

abnormalities by equalising on the basis of ‘sameness’ (Taylor and Mykitiuk 2001, 1), while

in the case of super-abilities we support abnormalities. This ‘selective investment in the

abnormal’ and the admiration for the ‘genetically superior’ could be seen as a token of a

society that cannot meet up with the criteria for justice (cf. Tannsjo 2000). On the other

hand, sport is a competitive practice, whose internal logic consists of the display of an

unequal distribution of abilities. These internal goods are considered worth striving for, for

their own sake (cf. MacIntyre 1985; Brown 1990; McNamee 1995). Sport consists of an

internal logic that may conflict with more societal ideals (for example concerning justice or

equality). These internal goods cannot be brought in agreement with the ideal, for

example, to create as many sport categories as possible with the aim of producing as

many sport stars as possible. It may be that everyone has certain abilities and disabilities;

we cannot however freely choose the practice in which our own specific abilities are

admired by people around the world.

Rawls and a Just Distribution of Disabilities

In the 1970s, Rawls, among others, gave rise to a revival of liberal political

philosophy. Next to his general influence on political and ethical philosophy, Rawls also

had an extensive influence on bioethics and sport ethics. Rawls most important

contribution to juridical and political philosophy was his publication in 1971 of a Theory

of Justice. In a Theory of Justice, John Rawls set out to find a more rational basis for the

contractualist tradition in political and ethical theory. He tried to find general principles of

justice that would function as basic rules for justice in society. These principles would, as is

typical for contractualism, be supported by a social agreement. However, Rawls combined

this with a stronger notion of justice which he derived from Kantian philosophy, and with

the utilitarian notion of costs and benefit calculus to find the best overall balance for

individual and collective well-being or happiness. Rational agreement was to be the basis

of this philosophical system. For Rawls, principles of justice

are the principles that free and rational persons concerned to further their own interests

would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the fundamental terms of their

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? 101

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

association. These principles are to regulate all further agreements; they specify the kinds

of social cooperation that can be entered into and the forms of government that can be

established. (Rawls 1971, 11)

So, in Rawlsian philosophy, the basic principles of justice should balance individual

liberty with an equal distribution of liberty. This should be combined with a provision

of the greatest benefit for the least advantaged. People should come to this

agreement through rational reflection, unaware of their specific individual place, talents

or background in society. This is what Rawls called ‘original position’. Rawls’s

conception of an ‘original position’ forms the rationale behind these basic principles

of justice. It stems from the contractarian tradition in political theory. The original

position was usually posed as the beginning position from which the social contract

was formulated, from within a ‘state of nature’. In Rawls’s work, this construction of an

original position should be regarded as a hypothetical position rather than a true

historical occurrence. It functions as a maxim rule; it is the basic position one

should take to come to the principles for a just society. In Rawls’s original position,

one is supposed to wear a ‘veil of ignorance’. With this construction, Rawls tried to

find a tool that can balance freedom or liberty and equality and leave out any

prejudices stemming from one’s class or one’s ethnic, linguistic, religious or cultural

background.

In Rawls’s vision, those who are at the same level of talent and ability, and have

the same willingness to use them, should have the same prospects of success

regardless of their initial place in the social system. Social class, gender or any other

contingency should have no influence on the liberty individuals are to enjoy in the

pursuance of his or her goals in life. Moreover, social and economic inequalities

should be distributed in such a way that they can reasonably be expected to be

advantageous to all those who are the worst off in the first place. Rawls aimed

at a distributive justice to compensate for the differences in fortune that we come

across. Justice is seen as being independent of luck and favouring more equal

distribution.

This position, although dominant in our current theoretical framework of justice, is

on a par with the notions of both talent and disability. Our world is primarily designed

for the average human being. People with a disability cannot partake in it as fully as

they should according to the principles of distributive justice. By redesigning the world

around us, however, we can make this world more accessible for the disabled. The

question remains what obstacles can and should be taken away in order for the disabled

to become part of other spheres of life. Making a building accessible is not the same

thing as trying to become (a successful) part of one of the most competitive practices

on earth. Following Rawls, we should adjust the person rather than the environment.

Therefore, a defence of plurality is often not the outcome of a Rawlsian approach to

justice. Our dominant understanding of elite sport cannot be brought in agreement with

the right to become an elite athlete, similar to the right for example to receive good

education. It may be difficult to justify the difference in admiration for the elite athlete

and the disabled athlete just based upon concepts as ‘talent’ or ‘effort’. Some talents are

more valued in a society than others in spite of a (changing) terminology, one that

sometimes even seems to suggest that being disabled is the norm for each human

being.

102 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

Adaptation of terminology

The inclusion of people with disabilities within regular sport and physical education

has become daily practice in many countries (cf. Doll-Tepper et al. 2001; Vanlandewijck

and Chappel 1996; Block and Obrusnikova 2007). The aims of participation and inclusion

have also influenced debates about terminology and disability sports. This issue of

terminology and language is important when it comes to matters of categorisation, and

also with regard to the distinction between elite sport and disability sport. How does this

categorisation, between sport for the ‘normal’ and sport for the disabled, in itself

contribute to our understanding of what is and what should be considered ‘ab-normal’?

What equalities and what inequalities are considered justified in our society and in what

way does the internal logic of sports challenges the understanding of justice in relation to

matters of inclusion and exclusion? In able to deal with these questions we will have to go

back to some of the debates on terminology and classification.

In 1980, the World Health Organisation introduced the International Classification of

Impairments, Disabilities and Handicaps (ICIDH). It was followed by years of dispute about

the medical and social model of disabilities. This dispute finally resulted in the

presentation of the International Classification of Functioning, Disability and Health (ICF)

in 2001. Within this new model, disability is not regarded a characteristic (that is present all

the time) but a state that may be present in certain environments or resulting from specific

interactions with other people (cf. Ustun 2004). Following this new terminological

proposal all people possess a multitude of abilities and disabilities. Sherill (2004b, 9)

optimistically writes about this change of terminology: ‘The worldwide trend is on

appreciating, embracing and celebrating individual differences as opposed to glorifying

the norm, the normal, and normalisation as was done in the 1900s.’ Since everyone has

disabilities and abilities, there is no need to make a rigid distinction between abled and

dis-abled bodies. ‘Being disabled is the norm for humanity’ (Ustun 2004, 1). In this sense,

the Paralympics is understood as ‘parallel Olympics’, not special nor separate or inferior.

The change of terminology can not hide the huge difference in status attached to

winning a medal as an able-bodied or a disabled athlete. This difference very clearly

explains the ultimate wish for a disabled athlete to become part of the competition for

elite athletes. With two cases we ask if certain limits to normalisation and inclusion may

conflict with ‘a distribution of resources’. Having three legs or no legs does not, in and of

itself, necessarily entail being disabled. In relation to sport it does however raise questions

regarding which inequalities are ‘relevant inequalities’ based upon the internal logic of

sport. It also presents us with an example of the reproduction of normality through sports.

Although sport and the circus have very similar historical roots, elite sport in the twentieth

century has differentiated from the early ‘freak shows’. Nowadays it celebrates the

ultimate, but at the same time normalised, two-legged human abilities and performances.

Even in elite sport ‘more’ is not necessarily ‘better’, as can be illustrated by the story of

Franceso Lentini, the ‘three legged football player’.

Lentini: Super- or Dis-abled?

Francesco Lentini (1889–1966) was born in Sicily in Italy with three legs, and a

rudimentary foot growing on one of his legs. As a child he was brought to a home for

disabled children. Initially, Lentini experienced his impairment as a disability (mainly

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? 103

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

because his third leg was six inches shorter than the two other legs). After being brought

into this home of disabled children (with children who were deaf, blind or mute) he found

out for himself that he was not disabled at all. Lentini writes about his childhood

‘transformation’:

I could appreciate the fact that I was possessed of all my faculties and senses. I could

hear, talk, understand, appreciate and enjoy the beauties of life. I could read and they

couldn’t. I could talk to my friends, but some of them couldn’t because they were dumb. I

could hear and enjoy beautiful music, while some of them couldn’t because they were

deaf. I had my mental faculties and began to look forward to my education, and some of

them couldn’t because they were idiots. (Nickell 2005, 131–2)

Lentini learned to use his ‘disability’ as an advantage. He entered the circus in the USA as a

young child. One of his acts was playing soccer on a stage, which explains his show name:

the ‘Three-Legged Football Player’. How fair it would have been if Lentini would have

entered a regular soccer competition is purely hypothetical, since he was only acting in the

circus, and his third leg would have given him a disadvantage over his opponents rather

than an advantage. More interesting in this respect would be the case of swimming.

Lentini talks about this advantage:

No, my limb does not bother me in the least. I can get about just as well and with the

same ease as any normal person—walk, run, jump; ride a bicycle, horse; ice and roller

skate; and drive my own car. I can swim—one advantage I have over the other fellow

when I swim is that I use the extra limb as a rudder.1

There is a clear difference between a performance in the circus and elite sport, and

between the performances of able (two-legged) and disabled (three-legged) athletes. This

difference can however not be inferred from a definition of ‘the normal’. Modern elite

sport celebrates abnormalities in many shapes and appearances, varying from extreme-

sized sumo wrestlers to extremely undersized gymnasts. What is considered a sport

performance or a circus performance has to be primarily understood from the historical

and cultural context. Yet comparing them does raise some interesting issues regarding the

definition of being disabled, the ‘boundaries of normality’ and the manner in which

modern, competitive sports may challenge some of the accepted categories and

definitions. Having three legs may become a disability in a world where two legs presents

the dominant norm, similar to Lentini’s observation: ‘If you lived in a world where

everyone had one arm, how would you cope with two?’

In the case of Lentini, uniqueness is not a reason for admiration, just because of the

deviation from the standard (as is the case in elite sport). Admiration and heroism is

afforded on the basis of a multitude of factors including training, discipline, showing and

mastering certain skills. Differences between elite sport as a global entertainment industry

and the circus are related to conceptual differences between ‘admiration’ and

‘amazement’. One can be amazed by looking at ‘physical abnormalities’, but this

amazement may turn into admiration when an ‘extraordinary feature’ is mastered and

turns out to be an extraordinary sport talent.

Without the prospect for the kind of heroism that is attached to modern elite sport,

large deviations from the standards of being ‘normal’ may still end up in a circus. It is

104 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

interesting to see that, although many acts in the circus are the result of years of hard and

vigorous training, these performances are still very much associated with the historical

roots of the freak show, or any other public place for the ‘unlucky mutants’ exposing or

trading upon their abnormalities. Elite sport and the circus have similar roots, based upon

the celebration of extraordinary talent. European countries share a similar history in the

knowledge and popularisation of physical culture, thanks to the circuses, the acrobats, the

pioneering bodybuilders and other body artists who travelled through Europe. In the late

eighteenth century, people already watched strongmen and other athletes performing at

fairs, festivals and in all kinds of theatres. Long before the idea of training and building

muscle mass became a ‘normalised’ kind of behaviour, people saw extraordinarily strong

men (and children) primarily as ‘miracles of nature’. Until around 1850, it is hard to draw

clear distinctions between sport, acrobatics and circus-like activities.

Thanks to the globalisation of modern sport, many ‘mutants’ are nowadays cheered

for their achievements. They set a norm for human performance and virtuosity to be

strived for also by elite athletes in disability sports. The classical distinction between elite

sports and the disabled athlete is blurring, as well as the distinction between the athlete as

hero, excelling on the basis of what counts as ‘normal’, and a (former) ‘patient combating

his limitations’, falling outside this normal variance. In this respect, modern disability sports

have made much progress in terms of admiration and respect. Nowadays, some so-called

‘disabled’ performances sometimes even come close to those of elite athletes. It raises the

question of what counts as normal in order to become part of the competition for able-

bodied athletes. How much of a disablement can and should be compensated for in order

to be (re)defined as a ‘normal athlete’?

Oscar Pistorius: Super- or Disabled?

South African Oscar Pistorius is known as ‘the fastest man on no legs’. He runs with

artificial limbs and is world record holder in the 100, 200 and 400 metres. He runs that fast

thanks partly to his carbon-fibre legs. He can even compete with elite athletes on ‘natural

legs’. In fact, he did so in July 2007, when he ran a 400-metre race at the British Grand Prix.

His participation in a regular competition is, however, surrounded by controversy. His

artificial limbs (also called ‘cheetahs’) may give him extra advantages which, as some

argue, makes the running competition unfair.

Pistorius is not the first disabled person competing in an able-bodied event. In most

historical cases there was no reason for concern about the justification of the participation

of disabled athletes. In the 1904 St Louis Olympics, George Eyser won three gold medals in

gymnastics while competing on a wooden leg. Neroli Fairhall, a paraplegic, competed in

archery in the 1984 Olympics, and in 2000 blind runner Marla Runyan raced against able-

bodied runners in the 1,500 metres athletics competition. Ajibola Adeoye (Nigeria) is an

arm amputee who holds the Paralympic record in the men’s 100 metres (10.72 seconds). If

his time would allow it, there is little reason why he couldn’t compete in the regular

Olympics. The loss of one of his arms does affect his ability to run, but not in such a way

that it causes concern about the fairness of the competition. These examples illustrate that

unless their disadvantage is a certain disability people can still compete in regular

competition. In these cases, no use is made of any prosthetic that influences the athletic

performance, at least not in such a way that it raises concern about the fairness of the

competition.

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? 105

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

The case of Pistorius is rather special, because his disability may, with the help of his

prostheses, turn out to be an unfair advantage. This is why the IAAF amended its

competition rules in 2007, banning the use of ‘any technical device that incorporates

springs, wheels or any other element that provides a user with an advantage over another

athlete not using such a device’ (IAAF Rule 144.2). IAAF spokesman Nick Davies

commented after the British Grand Prix, ‘We all wish him [Pistorius] well. The point here is

what’s going to happen in ten years? What happens if it continues to evolve?’

In November 2007 the IAAF asked the Institute of Biomechanics and Orthopaedics

(German Sport University, Cologne) for an independent biomechanical and physiological

study. Early in 2008 the results were presented. Some of the main results, as presented on

the IAAF site2 were that:

. running with prosthetics needs less additional energy (up to 25 per cent) than running

with natural limbs;

. the amount of energy return of the prosthetic blade has never been reported for a

human muscle-driven ankle joint in sprint running;

. the returned energy from the prosthetic blade is close to three times higher than with

the human ankle joint in maximum sprinting.

Based on these findings, the study concluded that an athlete running with prosthetic

blades has a clear mechanical advantage (more than 30 per cent) when compared to

‘someone’ not using the blades. According to Pistorius, however, other experts

contradicted these findings. Not all of the relevant variables were taken into consideration.

Pistorius and his coach responded to some of these arguments by claiming that his

prosthetics confront him with other disadvantages, such as rain (which reduces his

traction), crosswinds (which can blow the device sideways), and that some of his energy is

more easily dispensed at the start of the race than the energy of other runners.

The discussion and main arguments in this case were primarily focused on the

empirical question of what is considered an athletic advantage. This debate cannot,

however, be detached from the more conceptual question on the definition of running,

and what could still be considered a norm for (human) running. The main question

preceding any empirical research is of course: with whom is Pistorius compared, and based

upon what arguments? Compared to the world record holder, any runner may be defined

as ‘disadvantaged’. The fact that running with prosthetics needs less additional energy (up

to 25 per cent) than running with natural limbs is in itself insufficient to keep Pistorius from

competing in the Olympics. Based on the same arguments, sport authorities could have

forbidden the introduction of klapskates in speed skating or the even the Fosbury flop in

high jumping (cf. van Hilvoorde et al. 2007). There seems to be a fear that running on

prosthetics might become faster that ‘normal’ running. It may conflict with our

understanding of elite sport. Does it show the conservatism of sport and the public

that wants to hold on to the familiar distinction between elite sport and disability sport?

Enhancement and ‘Boosting’ in Disabled Sport

In discussing the ethical issues that Paralympic sports are confronted with, Wheeler

(2004) states that most ethical issues may be classified as ‘boosting’. Well-known in

disability sports are physiological, pharmacological and intellectual boosting. In the

106 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

context of this paper the discussion on technical boosting is of great relevance. Similar to

sport in general, there is an ongoing discussion on unfairness as a result of inequalities in

(financing) new technology. Differences in the availability of new products (wheelchairs

that are made of lighter material for example) and increasing inequalities between

developing and industrialised countries highly affect the fairness of disability sports

worldwide. Wheeler also mentions ‘osseointegrated prostheses’, a new technology that

improves (enhances) the integration of the prostheses with the human part of the leg. This

is a positive development for people who are hindered by their current prostheses, but it

also creates new inequalities in the context of elite disabled sport.

Special concern is also raised by the issue of ‘classification boosting’, which is unique

to disability sports. Instances have been described where athletes misrepresent their

functional abilities during the process of classification (Wheeler 2004, 4). The matter of

defining dysfunctions is both complex and contentious, being susceptible to deceptive

manipulation and fraud. Think for example of the misrepresentation or misclassification of

persons with average or above average intellectual abilities as intellectually disabled. Not

much is known about this phenomenon, but it raises reasons for concern about the

(future) credibility of disability sports—not least because there do not seem to be easy

measures to prevent this type of athletic fraud. The ‘pre-game process’ of classification

influences possible outcomes of a contest to a considerable degree. Wheeler’s pledge for a

code of ethics for disability sport could be a first step, but needs to be followed by

measures of administrators to formalise observational criteria and investigate possibilities

of manipulation.

At the same time it raises the question of how objective the presentation of

functional abilities can be. Every boundary that is drawn between certain types of disability

creates some injustice (cf. Jones and Howe 2005). In every category there are the ‘lucky’ and

‘unlucky’ ones. In one category one could qualify as highly talented (Pistorius in the

Paralympics for example), in the other just as an average athlete (Pistorius in the regular

Olympics). This injustice is in many ways similar to the kind of injustice that is intrinsic to

sport in general (cf. Loland 2002). Sport intrinsically differentiates between (in some respect

arbitrary) differences in genetic makeup. Dysfunctions need to be recognised as similar/

dissimilar and, to an acceptable degree, responsible for the outcome of the sport. Athletic

competitions are ideally set up in such a way that obvious differences in biological makeup

do not determine the outcome at forehand. On the other hand, some people will always be

naturally faster or stronger in ways that no training regimen can correct for.

While recognising that Paralympics do not imply inferior performances, based upon

a static and absolute distinction between able and disabled bodies, one can expect that

these games are increasingly confronted with discussions about classification, credibility

and also about unfair methods of ‘enhancement’. The optimist could say that the increase

in sport-ethical concerns in the Paralympics (whether because of fraud or illegal

enhancement) is a good sign, because it shows that the Paralympics are taken more

and more seriously by both competitors and the audience. The more status is attached to

winning medals, the more attention there is for possible fraud (such as classification

boosting). This might, however, appear to be too optimistic. The struggle, for example,

within professional cycling as a result of doping scandals is grounded in the fear of losing

credibility within a sport that already enjoys a worldwide popularity. Disability sports start

with a lack of popularity (and credibility) and have, in this sense, not much to lose. The

Paralympics are not considered to be ‘truly’ interesting by the larger portion of the general

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? 107

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

public since disabled sportsmen (defined as an impaired deviance of normality) are not the

best athletes in the world from the perspective of ‘normal sports’. In this respect, the

urgent wish of Pistorius to compete within the 2008 Olympic Games paradoxically

underlines the differences and reproduces the current order and hierarchy between able

and disabled bodies. It would be as if Pistorius, being the best disabled runner, is

promoted from an inferior division to the premier league of international sport. For most

disabled athletes there is no reason (and no possibility) to aim for this kind of ranking and

‘promotion’. Pistorius’s ‘promotion’ may even contribute to a loss of credibility and

appreciation of the performances of disability athletes.

Some argue that athletic enhancement by means of an increase in the quality of

prosthetics is similar to the use of doping. In terms of enhancement there is, however, more

at stake within disability sport, more than just trying to become the best athlete within a

specific category. Disability sports are about showing performances within categories of

similar disabilities, without making those disabilities the central element of athletic

prowess. Elite sport is about excellence within the boundaries of ‘self-chosen’ limitations;

disability sports originated from limitations through fate. Elite sport symbolises the athlete

as hero; it reproduces elitist ideals about the body (‘athletic’ and ‘beautiful’), about good

sportsmanship and national pride. For many people in disability sport, the athlete is still a

‘patient combating their limitations’, instead of an elite athlete with specific talents or

virtuosity.

It is, however, a different matter if disabled elite athletes may in some cases be

eligible to compete with able athletes. Arguments against the inclusion of three legs or

prosthetic limbs may be focused too much and selective on visible differences between

athletes. Take for example Floyd Landis, who injured his hip in 2003 and received a hip

prosthesis in 2006. Why is Floyd Landis’s hip not regarded as an advantage or an (‘artificial

hip’) enhancement, while his usage of testosterone was? What’s the difference between

the internal prosthesis of Landis and the external ones of Pistorius? The advantages of a

prosthesis in this case bear upon the relevant inequalities of the sport. Some actually claim

this is also the case for running competitions between Ethiopians and Caucasians, and that

therefore they should compete in separate categories. The question is whether Pistorius is

playing the same game as his opponents. We argue that he is not because he is showing

another and extra skill, namely handling his prosthesis in an extremely talented way.

Prostheses may have a considerable influence on the outcome of the game. This, however

is not an argument in itself that this competition should be excluded from the regular

Olympic Games.

Conclusion

Problems with classification and categorisation in sport for the disabled confront us

with the intrinsic inequalities and unfairness of any competitive practice that depends

upon the classification of people based upon both equalities and (‘relevant’) inequalities. A

three legged swimmer or a sprinter with prostheses who might become faster than the

elite sprinters can be excluded from regular competition, not because of their inferiority

but instead because a disability may appear to be a superior advantage. It is easy to point

at the conservative elements within traditional sport, in order to explain the exclusion of

Pistorius from the Olympic Games. There is, however, more at stake, from the perspective

of the internal goods of the sport. In sport there is no purely rational logic in the definition

108 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

of rules, neither in classification nor categorisations, in order to make the competition as

‘fair’ as possible. Rules are always a combination and compromise of tradition and a sport-

ethical ideal of ‘equality’ (the ‘level playing field’). People with three legs would allow for a

separate competition when the third leg has a considerate influence on the outcome of

the game.

When discussing relations and remarkable differences in admiration between elite

sport and disability sport, the traditional sport world is confronted with matters of

inclusion and a fair distribution of resources and rewards for the achievements of all

athletes. As we have seen in the case of Rawls’s philosophy of justice, however, these

mechanisms of inclusion and fair distribution are often based upon a very narrow image of

the average person, therefore again excluding the possibility of a pluralistic society. Sport

is a social practice with an internal logic that does not always conform to these general

principles of justice, specifically as we have come to embrace them now. It therefore

proves to be a good case for further analyses of the distinction society draws between

normal and disabled, between natural and dysfunctional.

Sports are a well-defined form of cultivation of specific abnormalities, and what is

traditionally understood as professional sportsmanship has socio-cultural roots in history.

Abnormality is the common denominator for both. The direction of excellence can be

framed socio-culturally, and from that perspective, there is not that much of a difference

between Paralympics and Olympics. The genetically fortunate and unfortunate share the

exceptional position on the scale of normality. And sometimes they meet, at the circus or

in a sports arena. Many biological exceptions are the result of certain genetic mutations

that may result in either a talent or disability. Depending on the time and context in which

a ‘mutant’ is being nurtured, one could either end up in a freak show, at the circus or in a

modern sport arena.

NOTES

1. See http://www.sideshowworld.com/blowoff-RFlentini.html, accessed 10 March 2008.

2. Available at http://www.iaaf.org/news/Kind¼512/newsId¼42896.html, accessed 10 March

2008.

REFERENCES

BAILEY, R. 2007. Talent development and the luck problem. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 1 (3):

367–77.

BLOCK, M.E. and I. OBRUSNIKOVA. 2007. Inclusion in physical education: A review of the literature

from 1995–2005. Adapted Physical Activity Quarterly 24: 103–24.

BOORSE, C. 1975. On the distinction between disease and illness. Philosophy and Public Affairs 5:

49–68.

———. 1976. What a theory of mental health should be. Journal for the Theory of Social

Behaviour 6 (1).

———. 1977. Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science 44.

BOWEN, J. 2002. The Americans With Disabilities Act and its application to sport. Journal of The

Philosophy of Sport XXIX: 66–74.

BROWN, W.M. 1990. Practices and prudence. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport XVII: 71–84.

BUCHANAN, A.B., D.W. BROCK, N. DANIELS and D. WIKLER. 2000. From Chance to Choice. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? 109

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

DEPAUW, K.P. and S.J. GAVRON. 2005. Disability Sport, 2nd edn. Champaign, IL: Human

Kinetics.

DOLL-TEPPER, G., M. KRONER and W. SONNENSCHEIN. 2001. New Horizons in Sport for Athletes with a

Disability. Aachen: Meyer & Meyer Sport.

ENGELHARDT, H.T. and S.F. SPICKER, eds. 1974. Evaluation and Explanation in the Biomedical

Sciences. Dordrecht: Netherlands: Reidel Publishing Company.

IPC (2006) Athletics Classification Handbook.

JONES, C. and P.D. HOWE. 2005. The conceptual boundaries of sport for the disabled: Classification

and athletic performance. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 32: 133–46.

KIOUMOURTZOGLOU, E. and K. POLITIS, eds. 2004. Paralympic Games From 1960 to 2004. Athens:

Organising Committee for the Olympic Games.

KLENCK, C. and K. GEBKE. 2007. Practical management: Common medical problems in disabled

athletes. Clinical Journal of Sport Medicine 19 (1): 55–60.

LINDSTROM, L.L. 1992. Integration of sport for athletes with disabilities into sport programmes for

able-bodied athletes. Palaestra 8 (3): 25–59.

LOLAND, S. 2002. Fair Play in Sport: A Moral Norm System. London and New York: Routledge.

MACINTYRE, A. 1985. After Virtue. London: Duckworth.

MCNAMEE, M. 1995. Sporting practices, institutions, and virtues: A critique and a restatement.

Journal of the Philosophy of Sport XXII: 61–82.

MOSER, I. 2006. Disability and the promises of technology: Technology, subjectivity and

embodiment within an order of the normal. Information, Communication and Society 9

(3): 373–95.

NICKELL, J. 2005. Secrets of the Sideshows. Lexington, KY: University Press of Kentucky.

PICKERING, FRANCIS L. 2005. Competitive sports, disability, and problems of justice in sports.

Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 32: 127–32.

RAWLS, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

SHERILL, C. 2004a. Adapted Physical Activity, Recreation, and Sport. Crossdisciplinary and Lifespan,

6th edn. New York: McGraw-Hill.

———. 2004b. The changing terminology of ‘‘ability’’ and ‘‘disability’’ in the sport context. In

Paralympic Games From 1960 to 2004, edited by E. Kioumourtzoglou and K. Politis.

Athens: Organising Committee for the Olympic Games.

TANNSJO, T. 2000. Is our admiration for sports heroes fascistoid? In Values in Sport: Elitism,

Nationalism, Gender Equality, and the Scientific Manufacture of Winners, edited by

T. Tannsjo and C.M. Tamburrini. London and New York: E&FN Spon/Routledge.

TAYLOR, K. and R. MYKITIUK. 2001. Genetics, normalcy and disability. ISUMA: Canadian Journal of

Policy Research/Revue canadienne de recherche surles politiques 2 (3): 65–71.

TOULMIN, S. 1975. Concepts of function and mechanism in medicine and medical science. In

Evaluation and Explanation in the Biomedical Sciences, edited by H.T. Engelhardt and

S.F. Spicker. Dordrecht: Netherlands: Reidel Publishing Company.

TWEEDY, S.M. 2002. Taxonomic theory and the ICF: Foundation for the Unified Disability Athletics

Classification. Adapted Physical Activity Quarterly 19: 221–37.

USTUN, T.B. 2004. Celebrate individual differences. The ICF model of disability. In Paralympic

Games From 1960 to 2004, edited by E. Kioumourtzoglou and K. Politis. Athens:

Organising Committee for the Olympic Games.

VAN HILVOORDE, I., R. VOS and G. DE WERT. 2007. Flopping, klapping and gene doping:

Dichotomies between ‘natural’ and ‘artificial’ in elite sport. Social Studies of Science 37 (2):

173–200.

110 IVO VAN HILVOORDE AND LAURENS LANDEWEERD

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4

VANLANDEWIJCK, Y.C. and R. CHAPPEL. 1996. Integration and classification issues in competitive

sport for athletes with disabilities. Sport Science Review 5: 65–88.

WHEELER, G.D. 2004. Ethical aspects in sports participation. In Paralympic Games From 1960 to

2004, edited by E. Kioumourtzoglou and K. Politis. Athens: Organising Committee for the

Olympic Games.

Ivo van Hilvoorde, Faculty of Human Movement Science, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, The

Netherlands. E-mail: [email protected]

Laurens Landeweerd, Faculty of Health and Science, University of Maastricht, The

Netherlands. E-mail: [email protected]

DISABILITY OR EXTRAORDINARY TALENT? 111

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Col

orad

o C

olle

ge]

at 1

7:17

30

Oct

ober

201

4