Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    1/17

    http://cus.sagepub.com/Cultural Sociology

    http://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83The online version of this article can be found at:

    DOI: 10.1177/1749975510389728

    2011 5: 83 originally published online 31 January 2011Cultural SociologySergio Sismondo

    Bourdieu's Rationalist Science of Science: Some Promises and Limitations

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    On behalf of:

    British Sociological Association

    can be found at:Cultural SociologyAdditional services and information for

    http://cus.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://cus.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    http://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83.refs.htmlCitations:

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83http://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83http://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83http://www.sagepublications.com/http://www.britsoc.co.uk/http://cus.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://cus.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://cus.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://cus.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83.refs.htmlhttp://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83.refs.htmlhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://cus.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://cus.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.britsoc.co.uk/http://www.sagepublications.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    2/17

    What is This?

    - Jan 31, 2011OnlineFirst Version of Record

    - Mar 23, 2011Version of Record>>

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://cus.sagepub.com/content/early/2011/01/27/1749975510389728.full.pdfhttp://cus.sagepub.com/content/early/2011/01/27/1749975510389728.full.pdfhttp://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83.full.pdfhttp://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83.full.pdfhttp://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtmlhttp://cus.sagepub.com/content/early/2011/01/27/1749975510389728.full.pdfhttp://cus.sagepub.com/content/5/1/83.full.pdf
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    3/17

    Bourdieus Rationalist Scienceof Science: Some Promisesand Limitations

    Sergio SismondoQueens University, Canada

    AbstractAt several points over his career, Pierre Bourdieu articulated a framework for a sociology

    of science, derived mostly from a priori reasoning about scientific actors in competition for

    capital. This article offers a brief overview of Bourdieus framework, placing it in the context of

    dominant trends in Science and Technology Studies. Bourdieu provides an excellent justification

    for the project of the sociology of science, and some starting points for analysis. However,

    his framework suffers from his commitment to a vague evolutionary epistemology, and from

    his correlative and surprising neglect of sciences habituses, with their particular practices,boundaries, and political economies. To be productive, Bourdieus sociology of science would

    have to abandon its narrow rationalism and embrace the material complexity of the sciences.

    KeywordsBourdieu, evolutionary epistemology, political economies of knowledge, Science and Technology

    Studies, sociology of science

    Introduction

    Pierre Bourdieus last course of lectures at the Collge de France, published in English

    as Science of Science and Reflexivity (2004), returned him to the sociology of science.

    This is a topic he had addressed most prominently and directly in a substantial theoretical

    paper, The Specificity of the Scientific Field and the Social Conditions of the Progress

    of Reason, published in both French and English in 1975. Sociology of science is also

    in the background of many of Bourdieus works on knowledge and forms of capital,

    works such asDistinction (1984), andHomo Academicus (1988); or perhaps more accu-

    rately, we can see Bourdieus sociology of science as closely related to his sociology of

    education, which was already well developed by the early 1970s (e.g. Bourdieu, 1971;

    Bourdieu and Passeron, 1973). But Science of Science is a direct reprise of Specificity,

    Article

    Corresponding author:

    Sergio Sismondo, Department of Philosophy, Queens University, Kingston, K7L 3N6, Canada.

    Email: [email protected]

    Cultural Sociology

    5(1) 8397

    The Author(s) 2011Reprints and permission: sagepub.

    co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav

    DOI: 10.1177/1749975510389728cus.sagepub.com

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    4/17

    84 Cultural Sociology 5(1)

    both in the theoretical framework it provides and the themes it explores. Bourdieus

    sociology of science remained remarkably consistent over 30 years.

    What Bourdieu offers by way of a framework for a sociological approach to science

    is useful, I argue, but limited. Its central idea, which is also one of his central sociological

    ideas, provides an excellent justification for the project of the sociology of science, andalso provides a starting point for an analysis of some phenomena in science. However,

    it does not achieve the marriage of naturalistic sociology and a normative account of

    sciences objectivity that Bourdieu believes it does, nor is it nearly as broad as we should

    want a sociological account of science to be.

    A Rationalist Sociology of Science

    Bourdieus work in the area contains some anecdotes and a few observations, but nobody of empirical data. As such his statements neatly lay out some of his central social

    theoretical ideas, as well as his sociology of science, which is almost entirely driven by

    them. In fact, Bourdieus early (1975) foray into sociology of science could serve as an

    introduction to his social theory more generally, as it is (relatively) concise, and not

    worked out in a deeply empirical context, unlike those later works that also articulate his

    developed social theory, like Homo Academicus (1988) orDistinction (1984). This

    explains the constancy of his thinking on science between Specificity and Science of

    Science, given the constancy of his social theory over this period (Jenkins, 2002).

    Running parallel with his accounts of other domains (e.g. Bourdieu, 1981), Bourdieu

    argues that we can understand scientific achievements as resulting from the interplay

    of researchers on a field. Actors come to a field with less or more cultural, social,

    symbolic, and economiccapital and we could usefully subdivide the categories fur-

    ther. In the context of the sociology of science, Bourdieu generally lumps all of these

    together asscientific capital, to some extent downplaying insights that the systematic

    articulation of their differences allows: capital can be converted from one form to

    another, and the accumulation of capital depends upon the conversion not being

    transparent (e.g. Bourdieu, 1991).

    Actors self-interestedly develop and deploy their capital to change their relative

    statuses within the field. Although Bourdieusfields often map roughly onto scientificfields, the former is not defined in disciplinary terms, but is rather a space of engage-

    ment, or a structure of relationships that bounds the practices relevant to somebody

    interested in contributing. The fields habitus is the set of dispositions that actors in it

    can or should have, defining a space of problems and possibilities, governing the accept-

    able moves an actor can make. The habitus itself is the result of previous actions in the

    social field. These concepts will be very familiar from all of Bourdieus other works.

    Scientific authority [is] a particular kind of capital, which can be accumulated, trans-

    mitted, and even reconverted into other kinds of capital under certain conditions

    (Bourdieu, 1975: 23). This symbolic capital enables an actor to make noticed achieve-ments. Symbolic capital thus can increase itself, as it enables claims and arguments to

    be recognized, and recognition is itself a key element of scientific capital. Meanwhile,

    sciences versions of cultural and economic capital provide the resources that enable

    people to make claims and arguments.

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    5/17

    Sismondo 85

    There is no escaping such a social structure and remaining within the sciences: The

    pure universe of even the purest science is a social field like any other, with its distri-

    bution of power and its monopolies, its struggles and strategies, interests and profits

    (Bourdieu, 1975: 19). Even the production of objective truth requires social conditions.

    Moreover, claims Bourdieu, action in a field is agonistic, a struggle for limited capitalamong its members: The structure of the scientific field at any given moment is defined

    by the state of the power distribution between the protagonists in the struggle (Bourdieu,

    1975: 27).

    All scientific moves of an actor are simultaneously moves on the field: Because all

    scientific practices are directed toward the acquisition of scientific authority . . . what

    is generally called interest in a particular scientific activity . . . is always two-sided

    (Bourdieu, 1975: 21). Every scientific intervention is also a move to increase capital,

    and vice versa: In the struggle in which every agent must engage in order to force

    recognition of the value of his products and his own authority as a legitimate producer,what is at stake is in fact the power to impose the definition of science (Bourdieu,

    1975: 23). It is, therefore, artificial to separate the pursuit of ideas from the social world.

    Bourdieu derives a number of insights from his simple starting points. Probably most

    interesting is his discussion of the conditions of entry into a field. The price of entry into

    a scientific field is scientific competence on the one hand, and a belief in the game, a

    libido scientifica (Bourdieu, 2004: 50), on the other. The participant needs both in

    order to succeed, and indeed, even to be a participant. Once playing the game of science,

    there are many different strategies for increasing capital.

    Depending on the position they occupy in the structure of the field . . . the new entrants may

    find themselves oriented either towards the risk-free investments of succession strategies . . . or

    towards subversion strategies, infinitely more costly and more hazardous investments which

    will not bring them the profits . . . unless they can achieve a complete redefinition of the

    principles legitimating domination. (Bourdieu, 1975: 30)

    Even established actors can adopt a wide variety of strategies and positions, given differ-

    ent levels and kinds of capital that they might possess. Bourdieus discussions on these

    issues nicely illustrate the possibilities (and in their narrowness also the limitations) of a

    rationalist sociology of science.Interest models have the immediate attraction of being grounded in objects, i.e. inter-

    ests, which are widely and pre-theoretically accepted to prompt and perhaps guide human

    action. But Bourdieus is a sophisticated interest model, accepting that actors interests

    and the dispositions they have to follow them depend on the habitus of the field in which

    they are acting. There can be no explanation of human actions without reference to the

    culture in which they occur. Thus Bourdieus framework demands work by anthropolo-

    gists and cultural historians to make sense of actual interplays of interests.

    Prior to that work of displaying particular cultures, though, the structural feature that

    distinguishes science from other, similar, activities, Bourdieu argues, is the fact that it isso closed (I will take issue with this claim in several different ways): The struggle for

    scientific authority, a particular kind of social capital, . . . owes its specificity to the fact

    that the producers tend to have no possible clients other than their competitors (Bourdieu,

    1975: 23). No external forces pull science in one direction or another. The scientific field

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    6/17

    86 Cultural Sociology 5(1)

    only has to deal with its own internal structure, its own distributions of scientific capital.

    But capital is distributed through recognition, which is given only by people who are

    themselves seeking recognition. As a result, every scientific intervention is scrutinized

    for its weaknesses, more than interventions in more open kinds of fields, fields that draw

    capital from outside.Thus Bourdieu thinks that he has a solution to the problem of finding ahistorical

    value in historical products, or getting non-relativized reason out of particular origins.

    If the scientific field is organized so as to isolate itself from its historical and social

    origins, then it can progress toward ahistorical reason. Severe competition achieves this,

    Bourdieu believes. This liberal solution (a version of evolutionary epistemologies seen

    in John Stuart Mill and Karl Popper, among others) to the problem is attractive, but as

    presented in both Specificity and Science of Science,it is too sketchy or simplistic to

    survive criticism. I will turn to this below.

    Science of Science Against STS

    In Science of Science, Bourdieu (2004) objects to postmodern rantings that threaten

    confidence in science, and threaten the walls that serve to insulate science from out-

    side pressures. As he announces early in the book, his concern is the problem of pro-

    tecting science from economic, political, and religious interests while recognizing

    sciences social and historical nature. The postmodern ranters against whom

    Bourdieu writes are mostly those researchers who staked out radical claims for the

    sociology of science in the 1970s: Barry Barnes, David Bloor, Harry Collins, NigelGilbert and Michael Mulkay, Karin Knorr-Cetina, and especially Bruno Latour and

    Steve Woolgar. Their work developed into the broader field of Science and Technology

    Studies (STS). Most of these sociologists and philosophers do not now look particu-

    larly postmodern.

    At the same time that he denounces their postmodernity, Bourdieu complains in a

    somewhat contrary vein that these sociologists and philosophers were overly anxious to

    appear radical. Their strategies for achieving distinction were to emphasize their differ-

    ences from previous generations, and to emphasize the dramatic and surprising elements

    in their findings. For example, they were quick to announce the demise of the old soci-ology of science exemplified in the work of Robert Merton (e.g. 1973), demanding

    attention for the novel positions they were staking out, perhaps without appreciating the

    possibility of evolutionary, rather than revolutionary, movement in the field. Or, they

    took well-worn insights and perspectives and transformed them into philosophical

    scandals, in the form of claims that scientific facts are made rather than discovered. For

    the most part I think that Bourdieu is right in his observations: STS got off the ground

    by trumpeting its own radicality. It is not obvious, though, that these observations

    should underpin criticism of, rather than praise for, the field.

    Not all Bourdieus observations are right. He complains, for example, that there is

    little empirical data in STS, authors referring repeatedly to the same studies. A textbook

    of STS that I recently authored contains more than 500 references, the majority of them

    to empirical studies, and makes no claim to be more than a set of entry points to the field

    (Sismondo, 2010). In this, at least, Bourdieu is not a trustworthy guide to STS.

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    7/17

    Sismondo 87

    Perhaps the loudest of Bourdieus complaints is that STS did not pick up on

    Specificity and the concepts it offered. Indeed, his concepts of different capitals, the

    habitus, and the fieldhave had little impact on STS (Breslau, 2002). Despite the fact

    that Specificity has been very much cited, is widely taught, and is reprinted in the

    most prominent general anthology in the field (Biagioli, 1999), there is only a modestamount of explicitly Bourdieusian work in the field. Perhaps this is because Bourdieu

    himself never worked out his concepts in the context of sociology of science, and in

    particular never in the context of empirical case studies of the creation of scientific

    knowledge, which have generally been the vehicles of theoretical ideas in STS.

    Bourdieus contribution is isolated from other work in STS, and has been picked up

    and used by relatively few researchers.

    The member of the field who has most often used Bourdieusian concepts is probably

    the historian of physics Yves Gingras (e.g. Gingras and Trpanier, 2001). Arguably,

    though, Bourdieus theoretical framework is typically only a backdrop to Gingrassimpressive and diverse charting of the ways that historical actors develop and follow

    interests: for example, the historians finely tuned description of local disciplinary

    cultures becomes for Gingras a description of a habitus, but does not depend upon the

    definition ofhabitus.

    There are a few works that depend more directly on Bourdieus social theory. For

    example, Wei Hongs recent study, Domination in a Scientific Field (2008), describes

    competition within a Chinese isotope laboratory, where the struggle for authority is

    played out in terms of competition between two forms of scientific capital: theoretical

    capital and technological capital. The laboratory in question had become a researchlaboratory not too long before Hongs study, and in that time, those members with the

    most theoretical capital had become dominant over those with the most technological

    capital (just as theory tends to dominate empirical work across the sciences). Competition

    continued, however, because operation of difficult equipment was essential to the work-

    ing of the lab, and those people who were skilled with the equipment were constantly

    attempting to use their capital to subvert the hierarchy.

    Randall Collinss monumental TheSociology of Philosophies (1998) also deserves

    mention in this context. It is not, of course, a work directly on the sociology of science,

    but it has been recognized as a part of the field as a potential model for other work. Thebook also does not explicitly draw on Bourdieu other than to make cultural capital one

    of its key theoretical concepts. But regardless of the extent to which Collins draws on

    it, his internalist account of philosophical actors jockeying for prestige nicely mirrors

    the account of science that Bourdieu gives in Specificity. Actors can employ low- or

    high-risk strategies, either allying themselves with or placing themselves in opposition

    to established positions. Because of a limited attention space within the field, positions

    end up clustering, so that there are always between three and six recognized philosophi-

    cal schools within a community. On the basis of this framework, Collins provides

    explanations of episodes and extraordinary sweeps of the history of philosophy. (It is

    interesting to note that Collins describes a fully theoretical discipline, philosophy;

    Bourdieu appears to treat theoretical sociology as the exemplary science.)

    Despite the distance Bourdieu tries to put between himself and STS, the field model of

    science instantiates the tenets of the strong programme in the sociology of knowledge as

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    8/17

    88 Cultural Sociology 5(1)

    laid out by Barry Barnes (e.g. 1974) and David Bloor (e.g. 1976), a key methodological

    framework for STS. We can see Bourdieus agonistic theory of science as respecting the

    principles of the strong programme in an individualistic way, explaining the content of

    science as resulting from individual researchers actions. Bloor (1976) writes of sociology

    of scientific knowledge, as opposed to mere sociology of scientists, that

    1. It would be causal, that is, concerned with the conditions which bring about belief or states

    of knowledge . . .

    2. It would be impartial with respect to truth and falsity, rationality or irrationality, success or

    failure. Both sides of these dichotomies will require explanation.

    3. It would be symmetrical in its style of explanation. The same types of cause would explain,

    say, true and false beliefs.

    4. It would be reflexive. In principle its patterns of explanation would have to be applicable

    to sociology itself. (p. 5)

    The central structure of Bourdieus sociology of science is, or could easily be, all of

    these. The agonistic struggle for the accumulation of capital, the mechanism Bourdieu

    invokes for the production of knowledge, is eminently causal, impartial, and symmetric,

    and could be applied reflexively to the sociology of science. That there should be some

    consonance between Bourdieus work and the strong programme is to be expected, given

    the opening statement of Specificity: The sociology of science rests on the postulate

    that the objective truth of the product even in the case of that very particular product,

    scientific truth lies in a particular type of social condition of production (1975: 19).

    Scientific knowledge can be explained socially. Or, more helpfully, Bourdieus attentionto different forms of capital makes clear that scientific work is always simultaneously

    intellectual and social: every intellectual gambit is also a move on the social field, and

    vice versa. Thus one of the strengths of Bourdieus framework is that it immediately

    justifies the project of the sociology of science.

    Evolutionary Epistemology and Its Problems

    The statement quoted in the last paragraph, with its focus on objective truth, also sug-

    gests a point of difference with STS. Overlaid onto Bourdieus symmetric rationalistmodel is a simple evolutionary epistemology that is less symmetric. Some social con-

    ditions, Bourdieu claims, allow true ideas to be stronger than false ones:

    the scientific field always includes a measure of social arbitrariness, inasmuch as it serves the

    interests of those who are in a position, inside or outside the field, to gather in the profits; but

    this does not prevent the inherent logic of the field, and in particular, the struggle between the

    dominant and the new entrants, with the resultant cross-control, from bringing about, under

    certain conditions, a systematic diversion of ends whereby the pursuit of private scientific

    interests . . . continuously operates to the advantage of the progress of science. (1975: 32)

    Just as natural selection produces well-adapted organisms, the intense selection of the

    scientific field produces well-adapted beliefs. On Bourdieus thinking, in the long run

    these well-adapted ideas will be true when there are no outside interests to systematically

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    9/17

    Sismondo 89

    skew them or the environments in which they must survive. Essentially the same point is

    made in Science of Science; insulating science from outside interests is central to

    Bourdieus project in both of his major forays into the sociology of science, despite the

    30 years separating them. Again, one of his complaints about the field of STS is that it

    fails to appreciate this solution to the problem of objectivity.There are a number of standard problems for evolutionary epistemology.

    Evolutionary epistemology, like natural selection, is capable of explaining truth and

    beauty, but also like natural selection it is capable of explaining falsity and ugliness. It

    can explain, for example, a scientific communitys circling in on supposed esoteric

    truths of astrophysics, but it can also explain the popular acceptance of the esoteric

    claims of astrology.

    A version of this difficulty affects Bourdieus use of evolutionary epistemology,

    which we can see in the observation that competing with the obvious argument for the

    insulation of the sciences is an equally obvious argument for their non-insulation. Purelyacademic science is ivory tower science. Without the check of practical application,

    without the intrusion of material interests, science can find itself un-tethered to the

    material world, and investigating unreal objects. To decide which one of these norma-

    tive arguments is right, and in what circumstances, requires attention to actual cases and

    empirical data. Evolutionary epistemology tends to be most attractive at a structural

    level, relatively distanced from empirical data. To explain particular ideas, though, we

    look to their actual histories. These may be consonant with the broad patterns that

    evolutionary epistemology predicts, but that is unimportant, because causal histories

    provide the more satisfying explanations. Bourdieu needs to turn to actual habituses toexplore whether subjectivity can produce objectivity.

    More philosophically troubling for evolutionary epistemology is the difficulty of

    defining truth as fully distinct from all forms of adaptedness. When Bourdieu says that

    objective truth and the progress of science require specific social configurations, he

    appears to be assuming that the truth can be specifiable completely independent of the

    social world. Bourdieu adopts a Gods-eye notion of truth, a correspondence notion of

    truth where correspondence is a relation that stands on its own. While I have some

    sympathies with the correspondence notion of truth, there are strong reasons to believe

    that it cannot be sufficient as a theory of scientific truth (Sismondo and Chrisman,2001). Let me set out two sets of concerns.

    First, scientific knowledge most directly describes situations that are distinctly non-

    natural, standing apart from nature in their purity and artificiality. Nature is systemati-

    cally excluded from the laboratory (Knorr Cetina, 1981), and therefore, scientific

    knowledge that depends upon experimentation is not true in the sense of straightfor-

    wardly corresponding to nature, following the contours of nature (Latour and Woolgar,

    1986). Just as importantly, the world of theory also tends to be several steps removed

    from nature, crucially depending on abstractions, idealizations, generalizations, and/or

    counter-factual situations. Explanatory and conceptual success for a theory demands a

    certain amount of abstraction away from the particularities of the real world. Even for

    theories that have a good claim to truth, close correspondence to ordinary empirical

    facts is only one virtue among many. In a strict sense then, scientists rarely study nature.

    Thus in some contexts we should adopt a kind of constructivism, a view that

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    10/17

    90 Cultural Sociology 5(1)

    emphasizes the contribution we make to knowledge and presents problems for the

    Gods-eye notion of truth. While truth may still be a correspondence to the facts, the facts

    are to some extent human products. And to the extent that the facts are independent, what

    counts as correspondence will cease to be; what can be considered an acceptable abstrac-

    tion or idealization is a human decision.As a second way to see such difficulties with the correspondence theory of truth, let

    us take a candidate scientific sentence like scientific authority is . . . a particular kind of

    capital, which can be accumulated, transmitted, and even reconverted into other kinds of

    capital under certain conditions (Bourdieu, 1975: 25) after all, Bourdieu is clear that

    sociology is a science, and that the sociology of science should apply to itself reflexively.

    If this sentence is true, is it true because it corresponds to some independent fact? Can

    that fact be specified independently of the interests that guide the sociology of science?

    Evaluations of the truth of this candidate sentence depend among other things on evalu-

    ations of the adequacy of the capitalmetaphor. Its adequacy, though, surely also dependson interests. We can make cases for and against such a sentence, making it more or less

    plausible, and ultimately its truth is tied at least to some degree to the cases that can be

    made for and against it.

    While it is straightforward to separate truth from some forms of adaptedness the features

    of astrology that make them so widely attractive it seems impossible to separate truth

    from all forms of adaptedness. What comes to count as truth, even in purely scientific

    contexts, must fit into disciplinary matrices, established material contexts, and the struc-

    tures that establish statements as plausible. Again, Bourdieus argument founders on his

    not paying sufficient attention to habitus.

    Another Approach to Legitimate and Illegitimate Interests: A

    Pharmaceutical Example

    Yet Bourdieu is right about the importance of the issue of the insulation of science, a

    point that can be illustrated by the current political economy of pharmaceutical knowl-

    edge. It should come as no surprise that pharmaceutical companies create and shape

    much of the medical knowledge about drugs. The industry funds 70 per cent or more of

    clinical trials. Most of this industry-sponsored clinical trial research is handled by con-tract research organizations, the data they produce is typically analyzed by pharmaceu-

    tical company statisticians, papers are written by hired medical writers, academics are

    given the opportunity to serve as authors of these papers, and professional publication

    planners submit the papers to medical journals (Sismondo, 2009). When a potentially

    major new drug is launched, its maker will flood the medical literature with articles on

    the drug and the conditions it might be used to treat. For example, Pfizers launch of the

    anti-depressant Zoloft (sertraline) was accompanied by one publication plan involv-

    ing 85 articles in major medical journals, and Mercks launch of the pain reliever Vioxx

    was accompanied by 96 articles (Healy and Cattell, 2003; Ross et al., 2008). These

    company-produced articles (and there may have been others) accounted for roughly

    40 per cent of the medical literature on those respective drugs in the years immediately

    following their launch. The pharmaceutical industry markets its products via core

    scientific media (Sismondo, 2009).

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    11/17

    Sismondo 91

    Pharmaceutical companies narrow set of interests has been demonstrated to shape the

    knowledge they produce. All science is laden with choices, of course, as has been shown

    by canonical studies in STS (e.g. Collins, 1991; Knorr Cetina, 1981; Pickering, 1984).

    Thus, the work of pharmaceutical companies to produce research and prominently place

    it in medical journals is not merely a corporate use of the patina of science. It is sciencedone in a new corporate mode, and to market products. Pharmaceutical company

    research, analysis, and writing is, though, different from other medical research, analy-

    sis, and writing in being driven by a very important and well-defined set of commercial

    interests. We can reasonably treat material interests in this arena as establishing some-

    thing akin to pervasive conflicts of interest.

    I would argue that the central issue here is not so much truth as control. Certainly the

    pharmaceutical industrys control over the medical literature produces some distortions

    (e.g. Melander et al., 2003; Turner et al., 2008). However, industry-produced manu-

    scripts fare very well in peer review at medical journals, and industry-sponsored manu-scripts tend to score better on standardized methodological tests than do independent

    trials (Lexchin et al., 2003). The industry produces at least some objective knowledge.

    Yet the pharmaceutical industrys control over so much clinical trial knowledge pro-

    foundly shapes that knowledge. It shapes the questions that are asked, and that its clinical

    trials answer. It shapes the kinds of answers that are valued, replacing, for example, clini-

    cal significance with statistical significance. And most obviously, the industry creates

    interest in certain conditions and products, as it affects centres of gravity. There are more

    than a thousand articles in medicines core clinical journals with the keyword omepra-

    zole, a proton-pump inhibitor for acid-related gastrointestinal problems; surely heartburnand its more serious but uncommon cousins would not merit such medical attention were

    they not immensely profitable to treat. One way of seeing the problem is that the phar-

    maceutical industrys control over clinical trial knowledge affects the habitus of clinical

    research to make knowledge serve corporate interests, rather than public ones.

    Pharmaceutical industry science may still be science, but it is profit-driven science.

    The effects of that should give the general public reason enough to object. Such a claim

    produces a very different reason for insulating science from interests than does Bourdieus

    evolutionary epistemology. A normative epistemology needs to understand much more

    about political economies of knowledge in order to deal with the complicated fields thatare sciences today, a point to which I return in my conclusion.

    Habitus and the Neglect of Material Sociality

    Bourdieus exemplary sciences are theoretical ones, and perhaps the prototype of them

    all is theoretical sociology, allowing reflexivity to be an easy consequence. Unfortunately,

    this allows him almost entirely to neglect the materiality of scientific work. Despite

    Bourdieus attention to the material dimensions of habituses in other contexts, his science

    is almost entirely ideal.

    The habitus of a field is its set of practices or dispositions, including dispositions of

    thought. STS, from its Wittgensteinian roots, also attends to sets of practices, and these

    can be roughly subsumed underhabitus. Moreover, since the work of Michael Polanyi

    (1958), STS has closely attended to the tacit dimensions of scientific knowledge and

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    12/17

    92 Cultural Sociology 5(1)

    practice, showing the unformalizable bases of what is taken to be formal (e.g. Collins,

    1991). Again in parallel to his work in other areas, Bourdieu accepts and incorporates

    this into his notion of the scientific habitus: science contains irreducible elements of

    connoisseurship, craft, and art (2004: 3840). But Bourdieus sociology is entirely

    human.STS has increasingly incorporated non-humans into its accounts of the social world,

    as a part of the social environment that must be taken into account before one can make

    sense of human actions, or even as full participants in scientific and technical work.

    Scientific and technical practices crucially involve tools and materials, and make no

    sense without them. Yet tools and materials are developed and chosen in the context of

    practices, and are made to accommodate existing structures and interests. In this way,

    scientific knowledge is partly materialized, and a scientific habitus cannot be thought

    of as a purely human object. Thus, almost all work in STS pays close attention to the

    materials or objects with which scientists and other technical workers interact.Actor-network theory (ANT) makes non-humans full participants in the social world

    of science and technology, which consists in the building of networks (Callon, 1986;

    Latour, 1987). The actors, and thus also the networks, of ANT include both human and

    non-human entities, with no methodologically significant distinction between them. Both

    humans and non-humans form associations, linking with other actors to form networks.

    Both humans and non-humans have interests (or dispositions that can usefully be thought

    of as interests) that cause them to act, that need to be accommodated, and that can be man-

    aged and used. We can chart networks by putting either particular humans or particular

    non-humans at their centers. ANT even reduces the social to the material, both insideand outside of science (Latour, 2005): science and technology work by translating mate-

    rial actions and forces from one form into another. Scientific representations are the result

    of material manipulations, and are solid precisely to the extent that they are mechanized.

    Theorists working outside the ANT tradition have developed similar views without

    assuming symmetry between humans and non-humans. For example, Karen Barad

    (2007) articulates a position she calls agential realism: human encounters with the

    world take the form of phenomena, which are ontologically basic. Material-discursive

    practices create intra-actions within these phenomena, parceling out features of the world

    and defining them as natural or human. Similarly, Andrew Pickerings pragmatic realism(1995) describes a mangle of practice in which humans encounter resistances to which

    they respond. Technologies and facts about nature result from a dialectic of resistance

    and accommodation.

    Material objects are interpreted by people, of course, and some in STS have argued

    that this can allow sociology to remain entirely within the human realm (e.g. Collins and

    Yearley, 1992). However, even on the most modest accounts of the agency of material

    objects, once interpreted they can be treated as having properties with which people inter-

    act. For example, interpretations can create technological frames (Bijker, 1995) or

    scripts (Akrich, 1992), the set of practices and the material and social infrastructure built

    up around an artifact or collection of similar artifacts. Sociality is a material sociality.

    An opportunity for Bourdieusian theorizing, then, is to articulate science as a set of

    material practices, and its habituses as simultaneously human and non-human domains.

    Particular non-humans are part of the habituses, and their shapes and dispositions have

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    13/17

    Sismondo 93

    been to some extent historically formed. This point, of course, applies to non-scientific

    domains as well, though it gets its initial importance from the impossibility of analyzing

    science without reference to scientists interactions with the material world.

    Boundaries of Knowledge Production

    Bourdieus neglect of the material world of science suggests further neglected elements:

    non-scientists. Bourdieus sociology of science, while it aims to explain scientific knowl-

    edge, is a sociology of scientists. It takes as given the boundaries between field and non-

    field, and between scientist contributors and non-scientist presumed non-contributors.

    But these are fascinating topics for a broader sociology of science.

    Boundary work is the work of developing, maintaining, and attacking a fields epis-

    temic authority, the potential to make respected claims (e.g. Gieryn, 1999). The study of

    boundary work is thus a localized, historical, or anti-foundational approach to under-standing authority. Boundary work occurs in the context of conflicts over claims,

    approaches, resources, or external issues. In particular, when broad disputes over epis-

    temic authority arise, people attempt to draw boundaries: for members of a discipline to

    have authority on any contentious issue requires that at least some other people do not

    have it, or have less of it. Maintenance of a currency of epistemic authority requires

    maintenance of a boundary inside of which other currencies have only limited value, or

    whose value depends on a conversion.

    Moreover, a challenge to the distribution of authority should be as important as a

    challenge to particular limits, if not more so. That is, holders of authority may havemore to lose from a threat to revalue their social capital, for example in a challenge to

    an important doctrine or method, than from another epistemic fields appropriation of

    subject matter. Thus we can expect boundary work to be one response to doctrinal dis-

    putes. This has been the case in much of the response of philosophy of science to STS

    (e.g. Brown, 2001; Kitcher, 2001). STS takes on the problem of understanding how

    scientific reasoning derives from particular and often local social and material contexts,

    and in so doing challenges philosophys claim that science is straightforwardly an

    exemplar of rationality.

    A slightly different version of boundary work establishes who can be a member of afield. As for almost all other fields, membership in scientific fields demands appropriate

    training and credentials, the clearing of key hurdles, and may even require personal

    characteristics that are more difficult to justify: through much of the history of science,

    it was very difficult for women to participate. To be a contributor to a science typically

    requires lengthy periods of student training in a discipline, successful participation in a

    research group, passing exams, particular types of high-level student achievements, a

    period of post-doctoral service, and more (Campbell, 2003; Delamont and Atkinson,

    2001). The subject matter does not dictate the specific contours of any of these require-

    ments. Thus it is useful to see the establishment of membership requirements as the

    result of boundary work.

    Membership in a scientific field is denied to various technicians, who may have as

    much knowledge and experimental ability as junior members of a field, and who on some

    criteria might look as though they are making contributions to knowledge (Doing, 2004;

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    14/17

    94 Cultural Sociology 5(1)

    Hong, 2008; Shapin, 1994). The difference in status between scientist and technician is

    one that has to be established and continually negotiated in the laboratory.

    Issues about boundaries become particularly interesting sociologically where science

    meets non-science. The standard model of expertise assumes that science trumps all

    other knowledge traditions, ignoring claims to knowledge that come out of non-sciencetraditions. Yet, for many problems of public import, non-scientists have relevant knowl-

    edge (Wynne, 1996; Yearley, 1999). For example, applied scientific knowledge contains

    implicit normative assumptions, or assumptions about the social world, which members

    of the public can recognize and with which they may disagree.

    When scientists find opposition to their claims, they tend to see that opposition as

    misinformed or even irrational. Moreover, controversies between experts and non-experts

    may not be resolved in the way that controversies among experts are: mechanisms of

    closure that are effective within scientific communities may not be effective outside

    of them. How societies manage the production and application of scientific knowledgecreates a set of questions, some of them normative questions, that a sociology of science

    should address.

    For example, Sheila Jasanoff (2005) describes civic epistemologies in Germany, the

    United Kingdom, and the United States that have shaped biotechnology, its institutional

    structures, its regulation, and public responses to it. Civic epistemologies contain a vari-

    ety of related components, including such things as: styles of knowledge making;

    approaches to and levels of trust; practices of demonstration; accepted foundations of

    expertise; and assumptions about the accessibility of experts. This approach demands

    and identifies only local solutions to the political issue of expertise. Each culture arrivesat its own civic epistemology, which becomes a locally legitimate response to the issue.

    That may involve deference to scientific and technical expertise, but it will be a politi-

    cally generated deference.

    Sociology of science thus needs to take account of the constructed boundaries of sci-

    ence, what lies outside of them, and interactions across those boundaries. Restricting

    attention to what recognized scientists say and do is to fail to understand the precondi-

    tions of what they say and do. Bourdieus sociology of science, with its exclusive focus

    on bounded fields, leaves little room to address these issues. Rather than seeing this as

    simply a failing, we might recognize an opportunity. A Bourdieusian sociology of scienceshould drop its commitment to strong boundaries of scientific fields, and understand

    ways in which forms of capital do and do not move across those boundaries, affecting the

    scientific knowledge that results.

    Conclusion

    Bourdieus contributions to the sociology of science contain many local insights, as one

    would expect of a work by someone as talented as he was. His later work is burdened,

    though, by his sense that STS took a wrong turn in the 1970s. This is a claim for which

    he does not mount a convincing and sustained argument, but rather a set of isolated

    complaints, only some of which are convincing. His later work is also burdened by his

    sense that his own work in the area was never valued as much as he thought it should

    have been. Bourdieu made an effort to re-articulate his perspective, but without properly

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    15/17

    Sismondo 95

    responding to and learning from STS, it resulted in a narrow view of what the science

    of science can be.

    Let me close by suggesting a further missed opportunity for a Bourdieusian contribu-

    tion to STS, that might be made to link my above concerns about material sociality and

    the boundaries of science. As I mentioned earlier, in the context of the sociology ofscience Bourdieu combines different forms of capital cultural, social, symbolic and

    economic and terms them scientific capital, which he sees as residing wholly within

    individual scientists. However, cultural capital is simply knowledge, which does not

    reside wholly within individual scientists: sometimes it can be embodied in technolo-

    gies, and sometimes it can be formalized and put in printed and electronic media.

    Bourdieus attention to knowledge as a kind of capital should lead us to thinking in

    terms ofpolitical economies of knowledge: the production, distribution and consump-

    tion of knowledge. This concept has an easy application to the new economies of knowl-

    edge of the 20th and 21st centuries, in which actors treat technical knowledge as aresource, and attempt to own or control it using mechanisms of intellectual property law.

    For this reason, business schools have created the discipline of knowledge management,

    studying how to shape the creation and flow of knowledge so that institutions can use it

    most efficiently and effectively.

    We might find value in exploring economies of knowledge, even when they are non-

    market ones, relying on gift exchanges or efforts aimed at communal goods. Because it

    does not separate epistemic and political processes, STS can genuinely study scientific

    and technological societies, rather than treating science and technology as externalities

    to political processes. I think, then, that Bourdieus work contains unused resources forthinking about science and technology, which can considerably broaden his narrow

    rationalism.

    References

    Akrich, M. (1992) The De-scription of Technical Objects, in W.E. Bijker and J. Law (eds) Shaping

    Technology/Building Society: Studies in Sociotechnical Change, pp. 20524. Cambridge, MA:

    MIT Press.

    Barad, K. (2007) Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of

    Matter and Meaning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Barnes, B.S. (1974) Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Biagioli, M. (ed.) (1999) The Science Studies Reader. New York: Routledge.

    Bijker, W.E. (1995) Of Bicycles, Bakelites, and Bulbs: Toward a Theory of Sociotechnical Change.

    Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Bloor, D. (1976)Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Bourdieu, P. (1971) Systems of Education and Systems of Thought, in M. Young (ed.)Knowledge

    and Control: New Directions for the Sociology of Education, pp. 189207. London: Macmillan.

    Bourdieu, P. (1975) The Specificity of the Scientific Field and the Social Conditions of the

    Progress of Reason, Social Science Information 14: 1947.

    Bourdieu, P. (1981) Men and Machines, in K. Knorr-Cetina and A.V. Cicourel (eds) Advances inSocial Theory and Methodology: Toward an Integration of Micro- and Macro-sociologies ,

    pp. 30417. Boston, MA: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Bourdieu, P. (1984) Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. Cambridge, MA:

    Harvard University Press.

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    16/17

    96 Cultural Sociology 5(1)

    Bourdieu, P. (1988)Homo Academicus. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Bourdieu, P. (1991)Language and Symbolic Power. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Bourdieu, P. (2004) Science of Science and Reflexivity. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Bourdieu, P. and Passeron, J.-C. (1973) Cultural Reproduction and Social Reproduction, in

    R. Brown (ed.) Knowledge, Education, and Cultural Change: Papers in the Sociology ofEducation, pp. 71112. London: Tavistock.

    Breslau, D. (2002) Pierre Bourdieu (Obituary). Social Studies of Science 32: 6315.

    Brown, J.R. (2001) Who Rules in Science? An Opinionated Guide to the Wars. Cambridge, MA:

    Harvard University Press.

    Callon, M. (1986) Some Elements of a Sociology of Translation: Domestication of the Scallops

    and the Fishermen of St. Brieuc Bay, in J. Law (ed.)Power, Action and Belief, pp. 196233.

    London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Campbell, R.A. (2003) Preparing the Next Generation of Scientists: The Social Process of

    Managing Students, Social Studies of Science 33: 897927.

    Collins, H.M. (1991) Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. Chicago,IL: Chicago University Press.

    Collins, H.M. and Yearley, S. (1992) Epistemological Chicken, in A. Pickering (ed.) Science as

    Practice and Culture, pp. 30126. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Collins, R. (1998) The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change .

    Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Delamont, S. and Atkinson, P. (2001) Doctoring Uncertainty: Mastering Craft Knowledge, Social

    Studies of Science 31: 87107.

    Doing, P. (2004) Lab Hands and the Scarlet O: Epistemic Politics and (Scientific) Labor,

    Social Studies of Science 34: 299323.

    Gieryn, T. (1999) Cultural Boundaries of Science: Credibility on the Line. Chicago, IL: Universityof Chicago Press.

    Gingras, Y. and Trpanier, M. (2001) Constructing a Tokomak: Political, Economic and Technical

    Factors as Constraints and Resources, Social Studies of Science 23: 536.

    Healy, D. and Cattell, D. (2003) Interface between Authorship, Industry and Science in the Domain

    of Therapeutics,British Journal of Psychiatry 183: 227.

    Hong, W. (2008) Domination in a Scientific Field: Capital Struggle in a Chinese Isotope Lab,

    Social Studies of Science 38: 54370.

    Jasanoff, S. (2005)Designs on Nature: Science and Democracy in Europe and the United States.

    Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Jenkins, R. (2002)Pierre Bourdieu. London: Routledge.Kitcher, P. (2001) Science, Truth, and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Knorr Cetina, K. (1981) The Manufacture of Knowledge: An Essay on the Constructivist and

    Contextual Nature of Science. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Latour, B. (1987) Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society.

    Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Latour, B. (2005) Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford:

    Oxford University Press.

    Latour, B. and Woolgar, S. (1986)Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton,

    NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Lexchin J., Bero, L.A., Djulbegovic, B. and Clark, O. (2003) Pharmaceutical IndustrySponsorship and Research Outcome and Quality: Systematic Review, British Medical

    Journal326: 116770.

    Melander, H., Ahlqvist-Rastad, J., Meijer, G. and Beermann, B. (2003) Evidence B(i)ased Medicine:

    Selective Reporting from Studies Sponsored by Pharmaceutical Industry: Review of Studies in

    New Drug Applications,British Medical Journal326: 11713.

    at Flinders University on April 20, 2013cus.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/http://cus.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 Cultural Sociology 2011 Sismondo 83 97

    17/17

    Sismondo 97

    Merton, R.K. (1973) The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations.

    Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Pickering, A. (1984) Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. Chicago,

    IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Pickering, A. (1995) The Mangle of Practice: Time, Agency, and Science. Chicago, IL: Universityof Chicago Press.

    Polanyi, M. (1958) Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago, IL:

    University of Chicago Press.

    Ross, J.S., Hill, K.P., Egilman, D.S. and Krumholz, H.M. (2008) Guest Authorship and

    Ghostwriting in Publications Related to Rofecoxib: A Case Study of Industry Documents

    from Rofecoxib Litigation,Journal of the American Medical Association 299(15): 180012.

    Shapin, S. (1994)A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-century England.

    Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Sismondo, S. (2009) Ghosts in the Machine: Publication Planning in the Medical Sciences,

    Social Studies of Science 39: 17198.Sismondo, S. (2010) An Introduction to Science and Technology Studies. Malden, MA: Wiley-

    Blackwell.

    Sismondo, S. and Chrisman, N. (2001) Deflationary Metaphysics and the Natures of Maps,

    Philosophy of Science 68 (Proceedings): S38S49.

    Turner, E.H., Matthews, A.M., Linardatos, E., Tell, R.A. and Rosenthal, R. (2008) Selective

    Publication of Antidepressant Trials and Its Influence on Apparent Efficacy, New England

    Journal of Medicine 358(3): 25260.

    Wynne, B. (1996) May the Sheep Safely Graze? A Reflexive View of the Expert-Lay Knowledge

    Divide, in S. Lash, B. Szerszynski and B. Wynne (eds) Risk, Environment & Modernity,

    pp. 4483. London: Sage.Yearley, S. (1999) Computer Models and the Publics Understanding of Science: A Case-Study

    Analysis, Social Studies of Science 29: 84566.

    Sergio Sismondo is Professor of Philosophy and Sociology at Queens University, Kingston,

    Canada. His current research is on the political economy of pharmaceutical knowledge, focusing

    particularly on industry sponsorship of clinical trials. He is also the author ofAn Introduction to

    Science and Technology Studies (Wiley-Blackwell, 2010) and a number of other general and

    philosophical works in STS. See www.sismondo.ca