Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    1/29

    Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession:Explaining Government Responses to Autonomy Demands

    Tavishi [email protected]

    Department of Political ScienceEmory University

    Atlanta, GA 30322

    Amy H. [email protected]

    Department of Political ScienceEmory University

    Atlanta, GA 30322

    Abstract: What explains government responses to autonomy demands? Theexisting literature has focused on either the granting of cultural autonomy orcomplete secession from the state. In this paper, we incorporate a third possibleoption: Carvationthe creation of a subnational unit with its own legislature, fiscaljurisdiction, and representation in the national legislatureis a common institutional

    arrangement across various countries but has received little attention in the literature. We argue that studying these responses separately assumes each of these to bemutually independent of the others. We present an alternate scale of concessionsgranted: (a) no cultural autonomy; (b) some cultural autonomy, such as regionallanguage education; (c) the creation of a subnational unit with its own legislature,fiscal jurisdiction, and representation in the national legislature; and (d) completepolitical and economic independence from the national state. Employing a gametheoretic model, we demonstrate that the type of concessions granted depends on (a)the probability of the government winning in the event of a conflict and (b) the netbenefits for the government and the demander. We test our derived hypotheses onthree cases from India where the outcomes have all been different: Uttaranchal(carvation), Bodoland (cultural autonomy), and Telangana (no autonomy).

    Draft Prepared for the 2006 Midwest Political Science Association Annual Meeting, Chicago, ILApril 15, 2006

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    2/29

    2

    Acronyms

    ABSU All Bodo Students UnionBJP Bharatiya Janata PartyBLT Bodo Liberation Tigers

    MoU Memorandum of UnderstandingNDFB National Democratic Force of BodolandPTCA Plains Tribals Council of AssamTPS Telangana Praja SamitiTJS Telangana Janata PartyUKD Uttaranchal Kranti DalULFA United Liberation Front of AssamUP Uttar PradeshUPA United Progressive Alliance

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    3/29

    3

    I. Introduction

    As the 1917 Civil War drew to an end, the Finnish government was confronted with an escalating

    problem: the fate of the land Islands. On the one hand, the twenty-thousand-some separatist

    movement was gaining momentum. The landers were after all geographically remote and

    ethnically Swedish. With Swedens King Gustav Vs ambitions for territorial expansion, the

    residents of the Islands voiced a unanimous interest in joining Sweden. On the other hand, the

    land Islands were a part of Finland since 1809 when Sweden lost to Russia in the Swedish-Russian

    War and was of geostrategic importance. Theland Islands geostrategic importance cannot be

    understated: During the 1917 Finnish Civil War, the Islands were occupied by Russian, Red Finnish,

    White Finnish, Swedish, and German troops almost simultaneously (Jutikkala 1962).

    To resolve the fate of the land Islands, Finland and Sweden both turned to the League of

    Nations. The result was the 1921 Geneva Convention of the Demilitarization and Neutralization of

    the land Islands, which contained a preamble and ten articles. In addition to the demilitarization

    and neutralization of the Islands, the Convention officially recognized the land Islands as a part of

    Finland and obligated Finland to protect the Islands should it come under attack.

    The Finnish followed the demilitarization and neutralization by granting theland Islands

    the right to self-government as outlined in the Constitution. This self-government however was

    limited. When the League of Nations collapsed in the 1930s, the Finnish and Swedish governments

    held talks to fortify the Islands and the Finnish government planned to introduce military

    conscription on the Islands. The residents of the land Islands demonstrated in response. It was

    not until the Self-Government ofland Act of 1951 that the Islands saw a progression in the

    powers of the regional government. The 1951 Act guaranteed extensive protection concerning the

    preservation of the Swedish language, of the culture, and of the Swedish traditions. The inhabitants

    of the islands were also granted a special land citizenship, which exempted them from military

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    4/29

    4

    service and conscription altogether. Since 1954 the land Islands have had their own Nordic flag

    and separate postage stamps since 1984. The Provincial Parliament also has far-reaching taxing

    powers and its approval is necessary before Finland can ratify an international treaty that concerns

    matters which lie within the domain of the land government (Rotkirch 1986). The 1991 Act of

    Autonomy of theland Islands further granted the region more autonomy on matters that concern

    domestic issues, such as education, health care, labor, roads, social welfare, and some taxes; the

    national government is responsible for defense, ecclesiastical matters, foreign policy, and some taxes.

    Although slightly unusual because of the role of the League of Nations, this example of the

    land Islands serves two good heuristic purposes. First, it demonstrates how national governments

    respondto autonomydemands. Governments do not always respond to demands, and if they do, the

    demands are not always granted in full. Sometimes the demanding group is satisfied and the game

    ends, but in other times, as in the case of the land Islands, the bargaining continues: Whether the

    real preference was independence or reunification with Sweden, the landers demandedsecession.

    The Finnish government responded by constitutionally granting them cultural autonomy over

    linguistic affairs. However, with escalating discontent in the aftermath of World War II and the

    dawn of the Cold War, the Finnish government finally recognized the land Islands as a sub-

    national unit with its own legislative body, fiscal jurisdictions, and representation in the national

    legislature.

    Second, the land Islands example illustrates how the possible outcomes from this

    bargaining exchange lie on a spectrum. As we demonstrate in the next section, the existing literature

    has focused on specific outcomesthe granting of cultural autonomy and complete secession from

    the national stateseparately. In this paper, we incorporate another possible outcome: Carvation

    the formation of a subnational unit with its own legislative body, fiscal jurisdiction, and

    representation in the national legislatureis a common institutional arrangement across various

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    5/29

    5

    countries but has received little attention in the literature. In this paper we argue all of these

    outcomes are available to governments when facing autonomy demands and thus, must be studied

    together. We present an alternate scale of concessions granted: (a) no cultural autonomy; (b) the

    authority over linguistic and/or religious affairs; (c) the formation of a subnational unit with its own

    legislative body, fiscal jurisdiction, and representation in the national legislature; and (d) complete

    political and economic independence from the national state.

    In Section III we employ a game theoretic model and argue that the type of concessions

    granted depends on (a) the probability of the government winning in the event of a conflict and (b)

    net benefits for the government and the demander. In Section IV, we test our hypotheses on a set

    of cases from India (Uttaranchal, Bodoland, and Talangana) that reflect the range of possible

    government responses. In the final section, we conclude and address future avenues for research.

    II. Explaining Demands

    The body of literature on demands for greater autonomy has concentrated on the occurrence and

    avoidance of ethnic conflict. The focus has been on explaining when ethnic conflict occurs, if the

    source of this conflict is primordial (Geertz 1994) or social engineering (Conner 1994; Hobsbawm

    1994), and how it can be avoided. The latter includes prescriptive institutions (Horowitz 1981, 1985,

    1996; Lijphart 1968, 1999) that encourage groups to cooperate and reduce the probability of conflict

    between these groups. However, there has been little scholarship devoted to understanding the

    demands made by these groups and the conditions explaining the success or failure of these groups

    to achieve these demands (Sorens 2005).

    The concentration on ethnic conflict and the demands made by ethnic groups also excludes

    demands for autonomy, not made on the basis of ethnicity. Demands for greater autonomy may

    certainly be made by groups that may share the same ethnicity as the larger group but the region

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    6/29

    6

    they reside in may have a different historical legacy from the larger region. In the Indian state of

    Andhra Pradesh, for example, the Telangana region which contains the oldest movement in India,

    demanding the carvationof a separate constitutional unit does not share the colonial past of the larger

    state and has experienced a different trajectory of economic development. The demand is spurred

    more by grievances regarding neglect and underdevelopment of the region (interview with V.

    Prakash1) than what are usually understood as ethnic differences.2 This paper studies demands for

    greater autonomy made on the basis of ethnicity as well as those on other factors such as a different

    historical legacy.

    In this study, the phrase autonomy demands has been used to refer to a whole range of

    demands made, including linguistic and/or religious demands (such as the Laplanders in Scandinavia

    and the Hakkas in Taiwan), the demand for a subnational unit with its own legislative body, fiscal

    jurisdiction, and representation in the national legislature (such as Puerto Rico in the United States

    and Jharkhand in India) and the demand for complete political and economic independence (such as

    the Basque country in Spain and East Timor in Indonesia). These demands are not mutually

    exclusive of each other. The Assam movement, for example, started with the demand for

    recognition of Assamese as the official language of the state and for education in the state to be

    carried out in Assamese (Baruah 1996). This movement consisted of social activists and local

    political and cultural leaders while the subsequent demand for complete secession from India was

    made by an armed militant group (ULFA). Yet, in spite of several examples where more than one of

    these demands has been made on behalf of the same region, scholarship in the area has studied

    them separately as language based demands for cultural autonomy (Fenwick 1981; Laitin 1988) and

    demands for secession (Islam 1985; Sorens 2005). Instead, we argue this bargaining exchange must

    1 Founder member, Telangana Rashtra Samiti (TRS) and long-time member of the Telangana movement2Walker Connors (1994) seminal work on ethnicity explains that ethnicity is used to encompass identificationbased on social realities as different as religion, language and national origin. He posits that ethnic groups may beself-defined or other defined.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    7/29

    7

    be studied along a continuum. We now turn to a review of the existing literature on linguistic

    autonomy demands and secessionist movements.

    II.1. Linguistic Autonomy Demands

    Demands for cultural autonomy can includeand often dothe freedom for groups to receive

    public education in their own language. The implications of language politics are several-fold: first,

    language standardization is an important mechanismalong with war, taxes, and marketsfor

    state-building. Second, it touches on the politics of regional autonomy: under what conditions does

    language repression fuel separatist tendencies? Third, it aids in our understanding of a nation.

    Nations are imagined communities (Anderson 1991) and such communities probably share a

    common language. Last, it addresses social mobility: The capacity of a minority to learn the majority

    language can affect the rate of social mobility (Laitin 1988, 2002).

    To the best of our knowledge, little theoretical work has been done on why certain groups

    demand language autonomy. However, there has been some scholarship explaining the motivation

    behind the choice of language-school made by households for their children. One explanation is the

    rational choice, economic-driven model: Regional groups are more likely to assimilate to the central

    group in order to improve their economic prospects in an environment that is increasingly favorable

    for the central group (see Fenwick 1981; Fierman 2006; Laitin 1988, 2002). Another explanation is a

    sociological hypothesis: The level of interethnic contact provides a powerful explanation for school

    choices. In an article on Russian identity in Latvia, Kronenfeld (2005) asks, not whether contact

    with Latvians make Russians likeLatvians, but whether contact with Latvians makes Russians act like

    Latvians (249).

    From this literature, we can identify two different mechanisms for why groups demand

    language autonomy. The first is an economic mechanism: It benefits the group to have its own

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    8/29

    8

    language-medium schools because of potential employment opportunities. For example, a

    moderately-developing economy in Russia combined with possible stagnation in Kazakhstan might

    make Russians in Kazakhstan demand Russian language autonomy. Contrast that to another

    example: A fast-paced growing economy in Estonia makes Russian language demand less important.

    The second mechanism is sociological: Groups demand language autonomy when they are

    geographically concentrated and have minimal contact with the majority ethnic group. We see this

    in the example of theland Islands and the demand for Swedish language schools.

    Having identified the mechanisms for why groups demand language autonomy, we can now

    seek to explain why governments grant this autonomy? We argue little work has been done to

    answer this question. To the best of our knowledge, the only systematic work is Laitin (1988). In

    his paper, he identifies six game theoretic models for representing different sources of language

    conflictsstate rationalization, nation building, regional reactivation, regional tipping, postcolonial,

    and competitive assimilation. In all six categories, the equilibrium is for the government to not grant

    linguistic autonomy. Although this theoretical framework is a valuable step for studying language

    based conflicts systematically, this literature still has yet to provide any empirical evidence that

    expands on these games.

    II.2. Secessionist Movements

    Prominent work explaining the conditions necessary for successful secessionist demands includes

    Islam (1985) and Sorens (2005). Islam (1985) compares the failures of Katanga and Biafra to the

    success of Bangladesh. His argument hinges on the physical distance between East and West

    Pakistanalso known as territorial anomalyas a major reason for the international community

    supporting Bangladeshs claim for independence; the majority claim for independence in Bangladesh

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    9/29

    9

    versus those in Biafra and Katanga that were led by minority groups; and whether these movements

    were democratic in nature.

    In addition to territorial noncontinguity, Sorens (2005) also highlights the lack of potential

    for irredentism- uniting with ethnic kin in a neighboring country (Saideman 2000), wealth in

    comparison to the rest of the country and the presence of a multiparty system as contributing

    factors. Sorens paper uses the percentage of votes received by secessionist parties in elections to

    the lower house of the national legislature as well as the provincial legislatures. He argues that the

    significance of secessionist parties in his analysis supports the claim that secessionist movements

    should be studied separately from other forms of autonomy movements. He posits that, in most

    cases these variables should have no impact on non-secessionist regional parties (319).

    What Sorens ignores in this analysis is the strategic interaction between these groups making

    demands for greater autonomy and the national government. There is an aspect of bargaining that

    takes place in these interactions. Groups also learn from previous interactions and those of other

    groups that have made demands with the state. It may be beneficial for a group that hopes to gain

    carvationa subnational unit with its own legislative body, fiscal jurisdiction, and representation in

    the national legislatureto ask for cultural autonomy initially, knowing well that the government is

    likely to grant such autonomy because the costs are low. At the same time, it may be a better

    bargaining strategy to begin with secession and agree to bargain down to a newly carved state, or an

    autonomous district as in the case of the Bodo movement in India.

    Sorens also argues that secessionist movements in democracies and autocracies need to be

    studied separately, as regime type may have a conditional effect on the determinants of

    secessionism (319). Although we concur with Sorens that different mechanisms may be at play

    between different regime types, we argue that his approach suffers from a selection bias empirically

    and theoretically. Empirically, there are large numbers of dropped negative cases in his universe (see

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    10/29

    10

    Mahoney and Goertz 2004). By looking only at countries where secessionist parties are allowed to

    run in elections, Sorens captures only those parties that have already had some degree of success as

    they are recognized as legal parties and allowed to contest elections. Theoretically, he also omits

    parties, that seek independence for regions much smaller than the province (316) without

    providing a theoretical justification for doing so.

    Another weakness in this approach is the underlying assumption that the revealed preference

    of the group is the sincerepreference of the group. For example, as illustrated by the Finnish example,

    and as we demonstrate in the model and in the Indian cases, the group may present a secessionist

    demand as an ideal situation in order to utilize it as a bargaining tool but may be willing to settle for

    less. For instance, their real preference may be for getting a constitutionally recognized subnational

    unit with its own legislative body and fiscal jurisdiction. How accurately the revealed preference

    reflects the sincere preference depends on a several factors. In the next section, we present the

    model to demonstrate our argument.

    III. Autonomy Demands, Government Responses, and Outcomes

    [Figure I] presents the structure of the game. The demander D moves first and demands some

    division of control aD where aD~ [0, 1]. For example, a demand ofaD= 1 means the demander

    wants fully autonomysecession; aD = 0.67 translates into significant autonomy but short of

    secessioncarvation; aD = 0.33 suggests some basic cultural autonomysuch as linguistic or

    religious freedoms; and aD= 0 indicates the government assumes full control. The demander and

    the government G have diametric preferences for the division of control, whose values we

    normalize to one. We do not make any assumption about the status quothe initial distribution of

    control.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    11/29

    11

    Figure I: The Game Form

    The government G can accept or reject this division of autonomy. If the government

    accepts, the demander gets aD and the government is left with the remainder of the pie: 1 - aD. If the

    government rejects, the government then counteroffers with some division of control to the

    demander aGwhere aG~ [0, aD] and aG < aD. We make an assumption here that the government will

    always present a counteroffer that is smaller than the initial demand.

    The demander can then decide to accept or reject this new counteroffer. If the demander

    accepts, the demander gets aG and the governments receives 1 aG. If the demander rejects, the two

    sides fight. Because war is politically and economically costly, both the demander and the

    government assume costs for fightingcwhere c~ [0, 1]. Under such conditions, the utility for the

    demander is equal to the probability of it winning the war 1-p minus the cost of the war: 1 p cD.

    Similarly, the utility for the government for fighting is the probability of it winning the war p minus

    the cost of war: p cG. These utilities hold under the assumption that conflict yields one of two

    results: (a) victory for the government which means no autonomy whatsoever for the demander; or

    (b) victory for the demander which means secession. Also, because the government makes the

    counteroffer, we assume what it proposes to keep for itself will always be larger than what it expects

    from fighting 1 aG > 1 p cD..

    D G G D A

    R

    A

    R

    [aD; 1 - aD]

    [1-p-cD; p-cG]

    aG ~ [0, aDaD ~ [0, 1]

    [aG; 1-aG]

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    12/29

    12

    III.1. Preferences

    Thus far we have only stated that the demander and the government have strictly opposing

    preferences. In other words, for the demander, anylevel of autonomy is strongly preferred to no

    autonomy; and conversely for the government, anylevel of division is strongly less preferred to no

    autonomy. Yet, the outcome of war can be inefficient (Fearon 2004). What this means for our

    model is that after fighting, although one actor may receive its most preferred outcome, the costs of

    war may render both the demander and the governments utility less preferable than peacefully

    accepting some division of autonomy. For instance, let us consider a scenario where the cost of

    fighting for both the demander and the government is 1. If the demander wins the civil war, the

    payoffs for the two actors are [0; -1]; if the government wins, [-1; 0]. Regardless of who wins the

    war, in both conditions the demander and the government are no better off from fighting than from

    peacefully accepting.

    It is important to note that this inefficiency happens only under certain conditionswhen

    there are costs. One shortcoming in the secessionist movement literature is the common

    assumption of a threshold: secessionist movements happen only when the costs drop below some

    threshold. Sorens (2005), for example, argues people vote for secessionist parties only when they

    expect political and economic benefits from independence (309). We argue the same mechanism

    can be logically applied to carvation or cultural demands as well. As illustrated in [Table 1], the costs

    of warwhether it is low, moderately low, moderately high, or highcan change the linear

    preferences of both actors regardless of the level of autonomy demands.

    III.2. Equilibrium Results

    Having specified the model, we now turn to a discussion of the equilibrium results. Using

    backwards induction, we identify three equilibria:government accepting, demander accepting, andfighting.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    13/29

    13

    Table I: Preferences

    Cost Demander Government

    Low:[0.00, 0.32]

    secession [1.00] secession minus cost ofwar [0.68, 1.00] > carvation [0.67] carvation minus cost of war [0.35, 0.67] >cultural autonomy [0.33] culturalautonomy minus cost of war [0.01, 0.33] >no autonomy [0.00] no autonomy minuscost of war[-0.32, 0.00]

    no autonomy [1.00] no autonomy minuscost of war [0.68, 1.00] > culturalautonomy[0.67] cultural autonomy minuscost of war [0.35, 0.67] > carvation[0.33] carvation minus cost of war [0.01, 0.33]> secession [0.00] secession minus cost ofwar[-0.32, 0.00]

    Moderately

    Low:[0.33, 0.50]

    secession [1.00] > carvation [0.67]

    secession minus cost of war [0.50, 0.67] >cultural autonomy[0.33] carvation minuscost of war [0.17, 0.34] > no autonomy[0.00] cultural autonomy minus cost ofwar [-0.17, 0.00] > no autonomy minuscost of war[-0.50, -0.33]

    no autonomy [1.00] > cultural autonomy

    [0.67]

    no autonomy minus cost of war[0.50, 0.67] > carvation[0.33] culturalautonomy minus cost of war [0.17, 0.34] >secession [0.00] > secession minus cost ofwar[-0.33, -0.50]

    ModeratelyHigh:

    [0.51, 0.67]

    secession [1.00] > carvation [0.67] >secession minus cost of war [0.33, 0.49] cultural autonomy[0.33] > carvation minuscost of war [0.00, 0.16] no autonomy[0.00] > cultural autonomy minus cost ofwar [-0.34, -0.18] > no autonomy minuscost of war[-0.67, -0.51]

    no autonomy [1.00] > cultural autonomy[0.67] > no autonomy minus cost of war[0.33, 0.49] carvation[0.33] > culturalautonomy minus cost of war [0.00, 0.16] secession [0.00] > carvation minus cost ofwar[-0.34, -0.18] > secession minus cost ofwar[-0.67, -0.51]

    High:[0.68, 1.00]

    secession [1.00] > carvation [0.67] >cultural autonomy [0.33] > secession minuscost of war [0.00, 0.32] no autonomy[0.00] > carvation minus cost of war [-0.33, -0.01]> cultural autonomy minus costof war[-0.67, -0.35] > no autonomy minus

    cost of war[-1.00, -0.68]

    no autonomy [1.00] > cultural autonomy[0.67] > carvation [0.33] > no autonomyminus cost of war [0.00, 0.32] secession[0.00] > cultural autonomy minus cost ofwar [-0.33, -0.01] > carvation minus costof war[-0.67, -0.35] > secession minus cost

    of war[-1.00, -0.68]

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    14/29

    14

    Proposition #1: When condition [1] below holds, the following strategy, let us call this the

    Government Accepting Equilibrium, forms a subgame perfect equilibrium: The government

    always accepts the initial offer proposed by the demander.

    Proposition #2:When conditions [1] fails to but [2] holds, the following strategy, let us call this

    the Demander Accepting Equilibrium, forms a subgame perfect equilibrium: The government

    always rejects the initial offer proposed by the demander, and the demander always accepts

    the governments counteroffer.

    Proposition #3:When both conditions [1] and [2] fail to hold, the following strategy, let us call

    this the Fighting Equilibrium, forms a subgame perfect equilibrium: The government always

    rejects the initial offer proposed by the demander, and the demander always rejects the

    governments counteroffer.

    The conditions are:

    )cp(*a GD 1 [1]

    GGD cp*acp +

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    15/29

    15

    demander and the probability of the governing winning the war are both very low at coordinate (0,

    0), the plane reaches z = 1 in the farthest back point of the figure. What this suggests is that under

    such conditions, we should expect the autonomy levels of the demander to be high; conversely,

    when the cost of fight for the demander and the governments probability of winning are high, such

    as at coordinate point (1, 1), we should expect the division of autonomy in favor of the government.

    Having specified our model, in the next section we turn to the empirical evidence. We first lay out

    our research design, which includes the ex ante predictions, the cases, and the operationalization of

    the dependent and independent variables.

    Figure II: Level of Autonomy Offered to Demander

    00.25

    0.5

    0.75

    1

    C

    0

    0.25

    0.5

    0.75

    1

    P-1-0.50

    0.51

    __AUTON

    00.25

    0.5

    0.75

    1

    C

    IV. Research Design and Evidence

    Ideally, we would be able to test the hypotheses generated from this study on all cases of demands

    made for greater autonomy. Currently, there is no dataset available which would allow such a test

    and we certainly encourage the collection of this data for future research in the area. As an

    alternative, we use three cases to test these hypotheses. What do we expect to gain from looking at

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    16/29

    16

    these cases? As we have employed a game theoretic model to understand the strategic interaction

    between governments and demanders, it is first essential to check if the assumptions we have made

    hold. To reiterate, we have made the following assumptions in the model. First, the demander

    makes the initial demand, and if the government rejects this demand, the government then

    counteroffers. Second, government counteroffers are never larger than the initial demands. Third,

    governments always prefer settling peacefully than going to war. If our assumptions hold in these

    cases, then we can test our argument that the demander and governments calculations are a

    function of the probability of winning a war and the cost of war.

    To test this argument, we need to operationalize the costs and benefits for the demanders

    and governments. One driving parameter in our model is the cost of war. One way to

    conceptualize cost is to think ofaudience cost(see Fearon 1994, 1997, Gaubatz 1996, Guisinger and

    Smith 2002). The intuition is that state leaders who escalate the conflict and then back down face

    the threat of being electorally removed by the population. The assumption is that the public always

    prefers its leader to stand firm (for an exception, see Chapman and Wolford nd). Another way to

    measure cost, which we employ here, is to think of it as the net benefit. Costs affect both the

    demander and the governments overall utility, and thus, it is not sufficient to consider payoffs just

    in terms of simple costs or benefits. Instead, we need to consider costs and benefits as an additive

    function. What this means is that the net benefit is high for a demander who has low costs; and

    conversely, the net benefit is low when the cost is high.

    [Table II] presents our ex ante indicators for the different levels of net benefits. On the

    demanders side, there are both economic and political net benefits from being granted additional

    autonomy. The region may have much to gain economically, as pointed out in an earlier discussion

    from being granted language autonomy. This could be seen in terms of acceptance of the regional

    language as official parlance which would open up jobs to people who speak the regional language.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    17/29

    17

    Also, carvation of a subnational unit implies both increased economic funding from the government

    for the region and increased control of its own finances. Political net benefits may include control

    of education and direct representation. Complete secession may have high economic net benefits

    for regions with great natural resources that have little net benefit from the resources under the SQ

    as well as political benefits from self-rule.

    Table II: Expected Political and Economic Net Benefits

    Demander

    Net Benefits Political Economic

    Low No change from SQ Low Spending from Government &High Taxes to Government

    Moderately Low Slightly better political representationthan SQ

    Low Spending from Government &Low Taxes to Government

    Moderately High Moderately better politicalrepresentation than SQ

    High Spending from Government &High Taxes to Government

    High Much greater political representationthan SQ

    High Spending from Government &Low Taxes to Government

    Government

    Net Benefits Political Economic

    Low Electoral loss Low Revenues from SubnationalUnit & High Spending on

    Subnational Unit

    Moderately Low No change from SQ Low Revenues from SubnationalUnit & Low Spending on

    Subnational Unit

    Moderately High Small electoral gains High Revenues from SubnationalUnit & High Spending on

    Subnational Unit

    High Large electoral gains High Revenues from Subnational &Low Spending on Subnational Unit

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    18/29

    18

    For the government, the net political and economic benefits of is a function of holding on to

    the status quo (SQ) versus giving away some autonomy. The political net benefits are best

    understood as electoral gains as we have restricted ourselves to democratic cases. For example, in

    the case of Uttaranchal, political gains refer to the electoral gains the Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP)

    government hoped to make in the new state of Uttaranchal by granting the region carvation. The

    larger state, Uttar Pradesh (UP), from which Uttaranchal had been carved, was already ruled by a

    majority BJP government and they imagined that the granting of the state would make people

    associate their autonomy with the BJP and thus vote for them, thus, leading to the BJP gaining an

    additional state government that would be ruled by their party. Economic net benefits for the

    government include holding on to economic resources in the region that they may not be able to

    control if they grant a greater level of autonomy, whether carvation in the formation of a

    subnational unit ruled perhaps by a different party or secession where they lose control of the

    resources. Alternatively, if the region is extremely poor and has little to offer in terms of economic

    resources and involves more expenditure on the governments part, then the government may

    calculate a low net economic benefit from holding on to the region in its current position.

    The modern Indian state has had a varied number of demands for greater autonomy since its

    independence in 1947from cultural autonomy to carvation to secession. To test the empirical

    evidence, we employ a most similar systems design(Prezworski and Teune 1970), which allows us to

    concentrate on the variables of interest as the institutional context within which the demands are

    made and responded to remain the same for all cases. India provides us with a wide range of

    demands and outcomes within the same federal, institutional context. We choose three cases, all of

    which have seen the same demand being madecarvation, but has seen different outcomes, ranging

    from carvation (Uttaranchal), cultural autonomy (Bodoland), and no autonomy (Telangana).

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    19/29

    19

    In the next section, we discuss each case in further detail and its sequence of moves. We

    examine the (a) net benefits for the demander, (b) the net benefits for the government, and (c) the

    outcome. Uttaranchal was the northern hilly region part of the largely plains-dominated (both

    geographically as well as politically) state of Uttar Pradesh. Bodoland continues to be a part of the

    larger state of Assam; and the areas included in the demanded state of Telangana are the inland areas

    that fall within the larger coastal state of Andhra Pradesh.

    IV.1. Case #1 (Uttaranchal): Carvation Demand, Carvation Outcome

    The demand for a separate state for the hill districts of Uttar Pradesh was placed several times since

    the 1950s by political party leaders, local non profits and community groups from the region which

    was never accepted by the central government in New Delhi. The movement gained momentum

    since 1994, after the Mandal Commission controversy across the country (interview with Ranjit

    Singh Verma3) and even gained the support of national political parties such as the BJP. The state

    was finally granted in 2000 when the BJP government was in power at both the center as well as the

    state level in the larger state of Uttar Pradesh, which contained Uttaranchal. The original state

    demanded did not include the district of Haridwar which was included in the new state. The name

    was also changed to Uttaranchal from the original name of Uttarakhand used by the movement

    (interview with Kashi Singh Aeri4).

    Net Benefits for Demander:There were high political benefits and high economic benefits

    expected by the different factions within the larger movement for a separate Uttaranchal. The

    prominent regional party, the Uttaranchal Kranti Dal (UKD) had hoped to gain a political presence

    in the newly formed legislature within the state. The region would also be granted a separate

    legislature thus guaranteeing proper representation for these hill areas that had remained a political

    3Ranjit Singh Verma, independent member of the movement for a separate Uttaranchal

    4 Kashi Singh Aeri, President, Uttarakhand Kranti Dal, a political party that participated and led the movement

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    20/29

    20

    minority in the larger Uttar Pradesh assembly which had long been dominated by caste politics of

    the plains areas, bearing little relevance to the Uttarkhand regions which had a completely different

    demographic makeup.

    Net Benefits for Government:The central government saw high political benefits from granting

    greater autonomy as the ruling party at the center, the BJP itself had taken up the cause of a separate

    state in the preceding years. The BJP was in power at the state level in Uttar Pradesh which

    contained the region of Uttaranchal. The BJP, through its own admission (interview with Mr. I.D.

    Swamy5), expected to make great electoral gains in the new state once formed as it had been a part

    of the movement in the last years before the state was granted, had unanimously passed the

    resolution for a separate state when it was in majority at the state and granted a separate state at the

    national level. Thus it expected extremely high political benefits from the carvation of a new state.

    The expected economic benefits, on the other hand were low as the government expected to spend

    more after the formation of the new state in direct transfers to it, but expected low revenues from

    this less developed region of the country.

    Outcome:Carvation. A separate state of Uttaranchal has been granted to the region within the

    federal framework of India. This is in keeping with our first equilibrium where the government

    always accepts if the expected gains from accepting the demanders demand are higher than the net

    benefits from a conflict. In this case, the BJP believed it had much to gain from granting the state

    peacefully as it wanted to be seen as the government that granted the state and hoped this would

    result in electoral gains which was a greater gain than what they would receive after a conflict with

    the region, where they would have lost their status as the government that had participated in the

    movement and then peacefully granted the state.

    5 Mr. I.D. Swamy, a former Indian Administrative Service officer, was State Minister of Home during the periodwhen three new subnational units with their own legislative bodies, fiscal jurisdictions, and representation in thenational legislatureChattisgarh, Jharkhand, and Uttaranchalwere created.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    21/29

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    22/29

    22

    government. At the same time, there were high political benefits and economic benefits from

    carvation as Bodo leaders only formed a very small portion of the Assam legislative assembly and

    the Bodo areas had seen little economic development in comparison with the rest of Assam.

    Net Benefits for Government: The granting of secession to Bodoland was a completely unviable

    solution and never considered (interview with Mr. Oscar Fernanes, the Indian National Congress in-

    charge for the North East) due to the total size of the Bodo areas and its location within Assam

    which is Indias connector to the North Eastern region. Also, the changing demographics of the

    Bodo areas and Assam more generally with increasing immigration from Bangladesh made the

    Bodos a much smaller majority in the region (Chadha 2005). Granting a state to the Bodos would

    also give spark discontent amongst the large number of other groups in the seven states of the

    Northeastern region of India, a heavy cost that the government was unwilling to pay. There were

    also costs related to the formation of a territorial council under the VI-th Schedule of the Indian

    constitution which included direct transfers from the Central government in Delhi but these were

    much lower than the costs associated with the ongoing violent conflict in the Assam. Thus political

    costs of secession were extremely high whereas economic costs of granting secession or greater

    autonomy were also high but somewhat lower than the political costs. Phrased in the language of net

    benefits, the political net benefits for keeping as much control as possible over the Bodo areas was

    high for the government whereas the economic net benefits were medium.

    Outcome: Cultural autonomy. This was awarded through the formation of the Bodo

    Territorial Council in 2000, to fulfill economic, educational and linguistic aspirations and the

    preservation of land-rights, socio-cultural and ethnic identity of the Bodos7. Here, both condition 1

    and 2, as specified in the model, failed to hold. The costs to the government for granting the state of

    Bodoland were too high, the counteroffer by the government was not acceptable to the movement

    7 Memorandum of Understanding on Bodoland Territorial Council, signed between the Government of India, theGovernment of Assam, and the Bodo Liberation Tigers on 10th February 2003 in New Delhi.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    23/29

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    24/29

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    25/29

    25

    unit with its own legislative body, fiscal jurisdiction, and representation in the national legislatureis

    a common institutional arrangement across various countries but has received little attention in the

    literature. We present an alternate scale of concessions granted: (a) no cultural autonomy; (b) the

    authority over linguistic and/or religious affairs; (c) the formation of a subnational unit with its own

    legislative body, fiscal jurisdiction, and representation in the national legislature; and (d) complete

    political independence from the larger national unit. We demonstrate formally that the type of

    concessions granted is a function of (a) the probability of the government winning a civil war and (b)

    the expected net benefits for both the demander and the government. The empirical evidence from

    several Indian regionsUttaranchal, Bodoland and Telanganareflects this strategic calculation.

    Future research on this topic can proceed most notably along two dimensions. Theoretically,

    in this paper we have modeled the interaction between the demander and the government as a one-

    period stationary game. However, in real lifeand as reflected in the Indian casesthe bargaining

    process often happens over several iterations. Intuitively, there is a difference between (a)

    demanding carvation in the first period and (b) demanding incrementally increasing autonomy and

    culminating in carvation in the n-th period. Governments are not as willing to make extreme

    concessions, and we see this difference reflected in the case of Bodoland.

    Empirically, we have thus far tested our theory on a set of Indian cases. This has allowed us

    to control for a host of variables and to get at the mechanisms of interest. However, we are aware

    that our cases in this paper reflect no variation in original demand. Ideally, we would like to include

    cases where the original demand was either cultural autonomy, as in the case of Assam, or secession,

    as in the case of Nagaland. Most certainly, focusing only on Indian cases raises the question of

    generalizability. We believe our theory is applicable to all democracies and unlike Sorens (2005),

    certain subset of dictatorships. There is institutional variation among dictatorships (see Bueno de

    Mesquita, Morrow, Siverson, and Smith 1999, 2002, 2003; Gandhi 2004; Geddes 1999; Lai and

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    26/29

    26

    Slater 2006; Linz and Stepan 1996; Slater 2003). Some have political institutions that resemble those

    found in democracies, such as competitive parties, elected legislatures, and decentralization. Thus,

    our theory should be extendable to include cases that are considered partly free by Freedom

    House. Examples of cases in these quasi-democracies include Abkhazia, Ajaria, and South Ossetia

    in Georgia, and Aceh, East Timor, and Yogyakarta in Indonesia.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    27/29

    27

    Bibliography

    Anderson, Benedict. 1991. Imagined Communities. London: Verso.

    Barbora, Sanjay. 2005. Autonomy in the Northeast: The Frontiers of Centralized Politics. In The

    Politics of Autonomy. Indian Experiences, edited by Ranabir Samaddar. Sage Publications. NewDelhi.

    Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siverson, and Alastair Smith, 1999. "AnInstitutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace,"American Political Science Review93:791-807.

    Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siverson, and Alastair Smith. 2002."The Selectorate Model: A Theory of Political Institutions." In Contemporary SociologicalTheories, edited by J. Berger, Morris Zelditch. Boulder: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siverson, and Alastair Smith. 2003. TheLogic of Political Survival. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Chadha, Lt. Col. Vivek, 2005. Low Intensity Conflicts in India. Sage Publications. New Delhi.

    Chapman, Terrence L. and Scott Wolford. nd. "Organizational Bias and Crisis Bargaining: WhenCan IOs Help Prevent War".Manuscript.

    Connor, Walker. 1994. Ethnonationalism: Princeton University Press.

    Fearon, James D. 1994. Domestic Political Audiences and the Escalation of InternationalDisputes,American Political Science Review88(3): 577-592.

    Fearon, James D. 1997. Signaling Foreign Policy Interests: Tying Hands Versus Sinking Costs,Journal of Conflict Resolution41(1): 68-90.

    Fearon, James D. 2004. Why Do Some Civil Wars Last So Much Longer Than Others? Journal ofPeace Research41(3): 275-301.

    Fenwick, Rudy. 1981. Social Change and Ethnic Nationalism. Comparative Studies in Society andHistory23(2): 196-216.

    Fierman, William. 2006. Language and Education in Post-Soviet Kazakhstan: Kazakh-Medium

    Instruction in Urban Schools. The Russian Review65: 98-116.

    Gandhi, Jennifer. 2004. Political Institutions Under Dictatorship. Dissertation. New York: New YorkUniversity.

    Gaubatz, Kurt Taylor. 1996. Democratic States and Commitment in International Relations,International Organization50(1): 109-139.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    28/29

    28

    Geddes, Barbara. 1999. "What Do We Know about Democratization after Twenty Years?" AnnualReview of Political Science2: 115-144.

    Geertz, Clifford. 1994. Primordial and Civic Ties. In Nationalism, edited by J. H. a. A. D. Smith.Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Guisinger, Alexandra and Alastair Smith (2002), Honest Threats: The Interaction of Reputationsand Political Institutions in International Crises,Journal of Conflict Resolution46 (2): 175-200.

    Hobsbawm, Eric. 1994. The Nation as Invented Tradition. InNationalism, edited by J. Hutchinsonand A. D. Smith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Horowitz, Donald L. 1981. Patterns of Ethnic Separatism. Comparative Studies in Society and History23(2): 165-195.

    Horowitz, Donald L. 1985. Ethnic Groups in Conflict. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Horowitz, Donald L. 1996. Ethnic Conflict Management for Policymakers. In Conflict andPeacemaking in Multiethnic Societies, edited by J. Montville. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.

    Islam, M. Rafiqul. 1985. Secessionist Self-Determination: Some Lessons from Katanga, Baifra andBangladesh.Journal of Peace Research22(3): 211-221.

    Kornenfeld, Daniel A. 2005. The Effects of Interethnic Contact on Ethnic Identity: Evidence fromLatvia. Post-Soviet Affairs21(3): 247-277.

    Lai, Brian and Dan Slater. 2006. Institutions of the Offensive: Domestic Sources of DisputeInitiation in Authoritarian Regimes, 1950-1992,American Journal of Political Science50(1).

    Laitin, David D. 1988. Language Games. Comparative Politics20(3): 289-302.

    Laitin, David D. 2002. What Is a Language Community? American Journal of Political Science44(1):142-155.

    Lijphart, Arend. 1968. The Politics of Accommodation: Pluralism and Democracy in the Netherlands. LosAngeles: University of California Press.

    Lijphart, Arend. 1999. Patterns of Democracy. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Linz, Juan and Alfred Stepan. 1996. Problems of Democratic Transition and Consolidation.Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Mahoney, James and Gary Goertz. 2004. The Possibility Principle: Choosing Negative Cases inComparative Research.American Political Science Review98(4): 653-670.

    Przeworski, Adam and Henry Teune. 1970. The Logic of Comparative Social Inquiry. Malabar: Robert E.Krieger Publishing.

  • 8/9/2019 Cultural Autonomy, Carvation, and Secession

    29/29

    Rotkirch, Holger. 1986. The Demilitarization and Neutralization of the land Islands: A Regime inEuropean Interest Withstanding Changing Circumstances, Journal of Peace Research23(4):357-376.

    Saideman, Stephen M. and Ayres, William R. 2000. Determining the Causes of Irrdentism: Logit

    Analysis of Minorities at Risk Data from the 1980s and 1990s.The Journal of Politics

    62(4):1126-1144.

    Slater, Dan. 2003. Iron Cage in an Iron Fist: Authoritarian Institutions and the Personalization ofPower in Malaysia. Comparative Politics36(1): 81-101.

    Sorens, Jason. 2005. The Cross-Sectional Determinants of Secessionism in AdvancedDemocracies. Comparative Political Studies38(3): 304-326.