Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    1/21

    http://ept.sagepub.com

    TheoryEuropean Journal of Political

    DOI: 10.1177/14748851080969612009; 8; 76European Journal of Political Theory

    Maeve CookeBeyond Dignity and Difference: Revisiting the Politics of Recognition

    http://ept.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/8/1/76The online version of this article can be found at:

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    can be found at:European Journal of Political TheoryAdditional services and information for

    http://ept.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://ept.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://ept.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://ept.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://ept.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://ept.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navhttp://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://ept.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://ept.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    2/21

    Beyond Dignity and DifferenceRevisiting the Politics of Recognition

    Maeve Cooke University College Dublin, Ireland

    AB S T R AC T : Revisiting Taylors 1992 account of the politics of recognition, I argue thathe is right to discern a strand in contemporary politics that goes beyond the demand for

    recognition of dignity. Against Taylor I contend that this is best understood as a concernnot for recognition of difference but for the value of something that is not universally

    shared, such as a particular ethical conception, cultural tradition or religious belief andpractice. Using the examples of three social movements I show the relevance of this forcontemporary politics. My empirically based argument is supported normatively by a

    discussion of Hegels critique of morality as conscience in hisPhenomenology. Referringto Axel Honneths theory of recognition I highlight the lack of attention to this kind ofconcern for recognition in contemporary political and social theory. I conclude byspecifying the key features of the concept of recognition most appropriate for

    responding to it publicly under conditions of value-pluralism.

    K E Y W O R D S : difference, Hegel, Honneth, politics of recognition, Taylor

    What is the point of the politics of recognition? What does the concept of recog-

    nition add to our thinking about justice or freedom or any other normative aim of

    political association and action? This question is not easy to answer. Certainly,

    Charles Taylors seminal essay The Politics of Recognition seemed to capture

    the mood of the times when it first appeared in 1992.1 His essay sparked off a

    variety of theoretical attempts to conceptualize demands for political justice as

    demands for recognition and may well have contributed towards the new idiom of

    recognition in political claims-making that emerged in the 1990s. However, from

    the beginning it was subjected to vigorous criticism and, rereading it some 15

    years later, it is hard to see why the essay was quite so influential. Nonetheless, I

    will suggest in the following that Taylors discussion is guided by an important

    intuition that has continued relevance for political theory and practice. In my

    view, he is right to suggest that there is a strand in contemporary politics that goes

    beyond the demand for recognition of universal capacities or qualities; moreover,

    that this should be seen as a demand for recognition of the worth of something

    76

    article

    Contact address: Professor Maeve Cooke, School of Philosophy, University CollegeDublin, Belfield, Dublin 4, Ireland.Email: [email protected]

    EJPTEuropean Journal

    of Political Theory SAGE Publications Ltd,

    Los Angeles, London, New Delhi

    and Singapore

    issn 1474-8851, 8(1) 7695

    [DOI: 10.1177/1474885108096961]

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    3/21

    that is not universally shared. However, Taylors efforts to address this kind of

    concern for recognition are hindered by his interpretation of specificity as differ-

    ence and, in particular, his correlation of the politics of difference with the norm

    of authenticity. In order to understand what is at stake and to respond to it appro-

    priately, therefore, we shall have to move beyond the framework of Taylors

    politics of recognition. Three contemporary social movements will be used to

    illustrate my point and to provide empirical support for my thesis that this kind

    of concern for recognition calls for an appropriate public response. In the follow-

    ing section, drawing on Hegels critique of morality as conscience in his

    Phenomenology of Spirit, I reinforce this empirically based argument with a norma-

    tive one. Then, focusing on the work of Axel Honneth, I discuss the lack of

    attention paid to this kind of concern for recognition by contemporary political

    and social theorists. In conclusion, I identify the key features of the concept of

    recognition most appropriate for responding to this kind of concern.

    Revisiting Taylor

    Taylor famously distinguishes between two meanings of the politics of recogni-

    tion. The first is what he calls the politics of equal dignity. This focuses on what

    all human beings have in common and is governed by the norm of autonomy. The

    second is what he calls the politics of difference. This focuses on each groups or

    each persons distinctness from all others and is governed by the norm of authen-

    ticity. Taylor connects these two versions of the politics of recognition with two

    types of social movements. The politics of equal dignity is held to correspond to

    a type of social movement in which a concern for legal issues is paramount: exam-

    ples might be current campaigns for human rights in the detention centre in

    Guntanamo Bay or for religious freedom in Tibet. By contrast, the politics of

    difference is connected with social movements in which the principal issues are

    identity-related: examples might be campaigns to protect and celebrate the dis-

    tinct ethnic identity of the Roma or Taylors own example of the Qubcois. He

    suggests, furthermore, that these two types of social movement form a historicalsequence: the politics of equal dignity is presented as historically prior to the

    politics of difference which is not to dispute its persistence in contemporary

    politics and, accordingly, the shift to a politics of difference is seen as something

    historically new. On his account, the politics of difference grows organically out

    of the politics of universal dignity through one of those shifts whereby a new

    understanding of the human social condition imparts a radically new meaning to

    an old principle.2

    Taylors account of the politics of recognition has been subjected to various

    criticisms. One objection is that he postulates a sequence of types of social move-

    ment that is historically inaccurate and misleading. Some critics argue that

    Taylors account obscures the ways in which, historically, issues of legal rights and

    issues of identity and, correspondingly, the politics of equal dignity and the poli-

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    77

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    4/21

    tics of difference, have always been intermeshed; moreover, that presenting the

    politics of difference as a historically new development disregards the ways in

    which identity-related issues were central to the resistance movements of the 19th

    and early 20th centuries, such as womens campaigns for the right to vote or the

    black revolt against slavery.3A second objection is that his account of the politics of

    difference is tied to an interpretation of difference as authenticity that seems to

    preclude the kind of discriminating recognition this kind of politics demands. This

    was one of the objections I raised against Taylor in a critical discussion of his essay

    some years ago.4 I argued that the politics of difference runs up against serious

    problems when it calls for recognition of authenticity, understood by Taylor as

    inwardly generated uniqueness. The main problem is one of critical evaluation.

    We can see this by recalling the point of Taylors distinction between the politics

    of equal dignity and the politics of difference. If the two are to be distinguished

    along the lines he suggests, the kind of recognition called for by the politics ofdifference cannot be an undiscriminating recognition of authenticity. A politics

    that recognizes everyone equally for their authenticity fits the model of the politics

    of equal dignity: it simply interprets the concept of human dignity in terms of

    uniqueness. Taylor is aware of the need to discriminate evaluatively between

    manifestations of authenticity, drawing attention to the distinction between

    regarding the creative activity of individuals or groups as worthwhile and declar-

    ing oneself on their side, even if their creations are not at all impressive.5As he sees

    it, failure to critically assess the validity of particular claims to authenticity leads

    easily to subjectivism, which, for him, is shot through with confusion.6 He con-

    cludes that we should make only apresumption of worth, which serves as a starting

    point for critical evaluation. However, critical evaluation runs up against two

    serious difficulties. First, in contexts in which there is a plurality of conceptions of

    ethical value and no generally acceptable overarching framework for

    distinguishing between them, ethical judgements will be contested. Second, in the

    case of claims to authenticity there is a further complication. Since this is an

    inwardly generated form of uniqueness, no external court of judgement is

    available: only the individuals and groups concerned can pass judgement on thevalidity of such claims. In the closing pages of his essay Taylor grapples with these

    difficulties but does not resolve them satisfactorily. In my critical discussion of the

    essay, my response was threefold. I first argued that he distinguishes too sharply

    between two versions of the politics of recognition and, furthermore, proposes a

    problematic correlation of the norm of autonomy with the politics of equal dignity

    and the norm of authenticity with the politics of difference. If we take autonomy

    to mean the capacity to form and develop an identity-specific conception of the

    good7 and, if as Taylor suggests, the deep concern of the politics of difference is

    singularity, then the norm of autonomy is also central to this version of the poli-

    tics of recognition. I then proposed a more differentiated account of the politics of

    difference. Whereas Taylor interprets the demand for recognition of difference

    solely as a demand for recognition of authenticity, I identified four other interpre-

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    78

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    5/21

    tations of this demand, one of which was a demand for recognition of autonomy,

    understood in the sense already mentioned. Arguing that some of the other inter-

    pretations, too, run up against the problem of critical evaluation encountered by

    Taylor, I concluded that only versions of the politics of difference that appeal to

    the norm of autonomy are able to avoid the subjectivism he deplores.

    At first glance this may seem merely to call for a more fluid boundary-line

    between Taylors two versions of the politics of recognition. Closer consideration

    reveals, however, that it undermines the very concept of a politics of difference as

    Taylor understands it. This is because the versions of the politics of recognition I

    ended up endorsing were ones that fit Taylors description of the politics of equal

    dignity: they focus on what all human beings have in common, in this case a capac-

    ity to form and develop identity-related conceptions of the good. Since, for

    Taylor, the politics of difference is the latest stage in a historical progression (we

    will recall his contention that it grows organically out of the politics of equal dig-nity as part of a shift in the western modern social imaginary), it also raises a ques-

    tion as to the contemporary relevance of the concept of the politics of recognition.

    In hindsight I think my conclusion was too hasty. I still hold that Taylors

    correlation of the politics of difference with the norm of authenticity is problem-

    atic. Moreover, I continue to be suspicious of the demand for recognition of any

    kind of difference. At the same time, I think Taylors account of the politics of

    recognition is guided by an important intuition. This is the intuition that con-

    temporary politics must take seriously a concern for recognition that goes beyond

    a demand for recognition of universal qualities or capacities; moreover, that it is a

    concern for recognition of the worth or value of things that are not universally

    shared.8To be sure, Taylors gaze is rather narrow: he focuses on the worth of

    particular cultural identities, specifically, the Francophone culture of Quebec.

    Since this is coupled with an interpretation of identity as difference, understood

    as authenticity in the sense of inwardly generated distinctiveness, it leads him into

    the difficulties I have outlined. It is easier to retain hold of Taylors intuition if we

    give up his focus on demands for recognition of particular cultural identities and

    expand his gaze to include claims for recognition of the value of particular sub-stantive conceptions of the good, cultural traditions and religious beliefs and

    practices. As the following examples show, Taylor is right to identify a concern for

    recognition that does not fit the category of the politics of equal dignity. But he is

    wrong to suggest that it is captured by the idea of a politics of difference. It is not

    a demand for recognition of authenticity, or indeed of difference in any sense, but

    a demand for recognition of a substantive value, be it the value of a concrete con-

    ception of the good, cultural tradition or religious belief and practice. I will argue

    that there are good reasons to take seriously this kind of concern for recognition.

    This calls on us to consider what it would mean to respond to it appropriately

    under contemporary conditions of value-pluralism.

    Let me start with three examples of contemporary social movements that are

    motivated, at least in part, by a concern for public recognition of the worth of

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    79

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    6/21

    something that is not a universal capacity or quality. Despite some significant

    differences between these movements, they all seek recognition for something

    that cannot be captured within the framework of the politics of equal dignity.

    The Slow Food MovementConstituted in 1989, its manifesto signed in Paris by delegates from 15 different

    countries, the international Slow Food movement is founded upon the concept of

    eco-gastronomy, which emphasizes the strong connections between plate and

    planet.9The movement describes itself as working to defend biodiversity in our

    food supply, spread taste education and connect producers of excellent foods with

    co-producers through events and initiatives. Its philosophy is that everyone has a

    fundamental right to pleasure and consequently the responsibility to protect the

    heritage of food, tradition and culture that make this pleasure possible. Let usassume as seems clear from its self-description that this movement seeks pub-

    lic recognition for its philosophy and mission. What kind of recognition does it

    seek? To describe it as a demand for recognition of what we share in common

    seems to miss the point. Despite the movements use of the term right to pleas-

    ure, it appears that its main purpose is not to unite all human beings through

    appeal to some universal human quality or capacity (for example, dignity or

    uniqueness or even pleasure) but to educate people to an appreciation of the ben-

    efits of biodiversity, of the value of local food traditions and of the importance of

    taking an interest in the food we eat, how it tastes, where it comes from and how it

    affects the rest of the world. Correspondingly, it seems less concerned to establish

    that right legally than to win public recognition for the value of eco-gastronomy.

    It might be objected that there is no difference in principle between the Slow

    Food movements campaign for eco-gastronomy and human rights movements

    since, like these, it seeks recognition for something that is held to be of universal

    value. The difference is merely that the good in question is not yet recognized as

    such by everyone. Nowadays, human rights movements can normally take for

    granted that the value of, for example, the dignity of the person is universallyrecognized and are concerned instead with inclusion: with expanding the category

    of those who count as persons. However, the dignity of the person was not always

    recognized as a universal value. The Slow Food movement, so the objection runs,

    can be described as a human rights movement in an early stage, when the princi-

    pal task is not inclusion, but to establish the universal value of the good in

    question.

    It is true that the Slow Food movement has a universalizing impulse (I shall

    come back to this). Nonetheless, the objection is unconvincing. To categorize it

    as a human rights movement is to disregard a central difference between its aims

    and those of such movements. Since they are held to be universal, the qualities or

    capacities for which human rights movements seek recognition have to be con-

    strued sufficiently abstractly to accommodate the multiplicity of particular ends

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    80

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    7/21

    motivating human beings. In this sense, the recognition they seek is formal: it

    abstracts from the concrete content of particular conceptions of the good, tradi-

    tions, beliefs and practices. By contrast, the Slow Food movement is concerned to

    win recognition not for an abstract right to pleasure, but for a right to pleasure

    that has a determinate content: it seeks recognition for the value of a substantive

    end. Eco-gastronomy is a concrete good: it commits those who value it to specific

    beliefs and specific ways of life. It is the value of this concrete good that is at stake

    in its campaign. This is why it does not fit the category of the politics of equal

    dignity. It is also what connects it to my other examples.

    The Welsh-Language Initiatives: Mentrau Iaith

    These are local organizations in Wales that offer support to communities to

    increase and develop their use of the Welsh language.10

    Their self-professed aimsare to offer helpful information to parents seeking to raise their children bi-

    lingually and/or to educate them through the medium of Welsh; they also counsel

    public and voluntary organizations on how to increase their use of Welsh and

    advise businesses eager to offer a bilingual service to their customers. In addition

    they seek to provide social and leisure opportunities for children and young people

    to use Welsh, as well as opportunities for Welsh learners to use their Welsh out-

    side the classroom. In this case, too, there is an evident concern for public recog-

    nition. And, once again, describing this as a demand for recognition of what we

    share in common seems to miss the point. As I read the movements mission state-

    ment, its concern is less to unite human beings through appeal to some allegedly

    universal norm or quality than to bring to public attention the value of the Welsh

    language and the cultural traditions of which this is part. As in the case of the Slow

    Food movement, recognition is sought in the first instance not for an abstract

    right, but for the value of a concrete good. This is not to say that legal or public

    recognition of an abstract universal right for example, a right to linguistic self-

    determination is not also at stake: it is to suggest that this movements demand

    for recognition would not be fully satisfied by recognition of such a right.

    The Assembly for the Protection of Hijab

    This is a campaign to allow Muslim girls to wear the hijab in schools.11 Launched

    in London in 2004 by the Muslim Womens Group and the Muslim Association

    of Britain, this international movement describes itself as seeking the protection

    of Muslim womens right to wear the hijab in accordance with their beliefs and of

    every womans right to dress as modestly and as comfortably as she pleases. Its

    self-professed aims are to bring an end to the hijab ban wherever it has already

    been imposed and to prevent any further spreading of the ban. It seeks, in addi-

    tion, to provide a platform for Muslim women to express their views, to expose

    and discourage any false stereotypes that present Muslim women as being

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    81

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    8/21

    oppressed and to liberate Muslim women from any form of race, religious or sex

    discrimination. In this case, the appeal to universal rights is particularly striking.

    Those involved in the campaign appear to seek recognition for something all

    humans share in common, for example, a conception of dignity that is independ-

    ent of race, religion and sex or a capacity for self-determination that extends to

    matters of dress. Certainly, for many people actively involved in or sympathetic to

    the campaign, its purpose may best be captured in these terms. However, two

    comments are relevant here. First, despite the rhetoric of its mission statement,

    the Assembly clearly sees wearing the hijab as the public expression of a deeply

    held religious conviction. It does not consider it simply a matter of personal

    preference on a par with a penchant for bright-coloured clothing or the fashions

    of the 1950s. To express something publicly is to seek public recognition for the

    importance or value of what is expressed. Insofar as the Assembly is also con-

    cerned with public expression, therefore, it seeks public recognition not just for aconception of human dignity, or for the right to dress as one pleases, but for the

    importance of particular religious beliefs and practices. In this case too, therefore,

    recognition is sought for the value of a concrete good. Second, its employment of

    the language of universal rights could be due to its adoption of an assimilation

    model of social integration. Among contemporary sociologists it is generally

    accepted that assimilation is the first ideal-typical mode of incorporation of out-

    sider groups into the civil societies of western modernity.12 Incorporation as

    assimilation requires outsider groups Jews, blacks, women or, in this case,

    Muslims to shed their outsider identities completely upon entering the public

    domain. However, assimilative incorporation is usually considered normatively

    unsatisfactory. This is because a stigma remains attached to the cast-aside outsider

    qualities, infringing against the egalitarian requirements of justice. Some also

    consider it empirically unstable, since it is premised on the vilification and exclu-

    sion of the identities of those who belong to the formerly outsider groups.13 For

    these reasons, it can be expected to give way to a hyphenated mode of incorpora-

    tion: here, outsider groups partially give up their outsider identities in favour of a

    new form of identity that goes beyond all existing insider or outsider identities.However, some sociologists regard this mode of social integration, too, as nor-

    matively unsatisfactory. This is because outsider qualities are not redefined and

    there is no valuing of otherness; rather, the new identities adopted by outsider

    groups reflect the norms and values of the already dominant social groups. This

    suggests the need for a third mode of incorporation. Following this line of argu-

    ment, Jeffrey Alexander argues that only the multicultural mode of social

    integration leads to the requisite reconfiguration of outsider and insider qualities;

    on the multicultural model, outsider qualities are no longer seen as stigmatizing

    but as valuable in themselves.14 Following Alexander we could surmise that, on a

    multicultural model of incorporation, wearing the hijab would no longer be seen

    as irrelevant from the point of view, for example, of equal respect for the dignity

    of all women; rather it would be seen in a positive way as a public expression of a

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    82

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    9/21

    deeply held religious conviction on the part of a formerly outsider group.15To be

    sure, the empirical and normative arguments underpinning this sociological

    account are a matter of debate; nonetheless, insofar as they have some initial plau-

    sibility, they may help to explain the campaigns focus on what all human beings

    share in common and its use of the language of rights, despite its evident belief

    that wearing the hijab is not a normatively irrelevant aspect of personal identity

    for many human beings and that it is the public expression of an important con-

    viction.

    From Empirical to Normative Arguments

    One implication of the foregoing is that the formulation demandfor recognition

    may be misleading. What I have hitherto referred to as demands are sometimes

    better described as needs, desires or expectations of recognition, since those towhom such needs, desires or expectations are attributed may not be conscious of

    them, may not articulate them explicitly or may misconstrue the kind of recogni-

    tion that is required. This implies, in turn, that empirical arguments relating to

    actually formulated demands for recognition are insufficient to justify the politics

    of recognition: the reasons for responding politically to needs, desires or expecta-

    tions for recognition are always also normative in character.

    I have suggested that Taylor is correct to discern a concern for recognition that

    cannot be accommodated within the framework of the politics of equal dignity,

    which, as we have seen, focuses on qualities or capacities that are shared in com-

    mon. Using the examples of three contemporary social movements, I identified,

    respectively, a concern for recognition of the value of a specific substantive

    conception of the good, a specific linguistic and cultural tradition and a specific

    religious belief and practice. In each case, I perceived a concern for recognition of

    something that is not universally shared; indeed, in the case of the Welsh language

    and wearing the hijab, it is not clear that the movements in question even aim at

    universalization. But the examples also make clear that the issue is not recognition

    of difference. The Slow Food movement does not claim that eco-gastronomy isvaluable because it is different, but because it is the right approach to life for

    human beings. The Welsh-language initiatives do not claim that speaking Welsh

    is valuable because it is different, but because it is an intrinsic part of a cultural

    tradition that is conducive to human flourishing. The Assembly for the Protection

    of Hijab does not claim that wearing the hijab is valuable because it is different,

    but because it is the public expression of religious belief in the one true God.

    Evidently, therefore, in order to take account of this kind of concern for recogni-

    tion, we need to move beyond the two categories proposed by Taylor. However,before moving onwards, we should recall one further element of our discussion of

    his essay. This is the problem of critical evaluation that arises when recognition is

    required for something that is not universally shared. As we have seen, this gives

    rise to the following difficulty. On the one hand, there is a need for discriminat-

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    83

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    10/21

    ing recognition; if subjectivism is to be avoided, uncritical approbation of the

    value of a particular substantive conception of the good, cultural tradition or

    religious belief and practice is not an option. On the other hand, in contexts in

    which there is a plurality of conceptions of value and no generally acceptable over-

    arching framework for distinguishing between them, critical evaluation does not

    appear to be an option either. As we have also seen, in my earlier discussion of

    Taylor this problem of critical evaluation led me to reject the project of a politics

    of difference and to endorse only those versions of the politics of recognition that

    are guided by the norm of autonomy. I no longer consider the problem of critical

    evaluation quite so intractable; in the next sections, I propose a processual con-

    ception of ethical value and corresponding processual conception of recognition

    that are initial steps in response to it.16 But responding to the problem of critical

    evaluation presupposes that there are good normative arguments for doing so.

    For, even if, empirically, I am correct to identify a concern for recognition of thevalue of particular substantive conceptions of the good, cultural traditions and

    religious beliefs and practices, its empirical reality is not sufficient reason to take

    it seriously. Just as a normative theory of recognition cannot dispense with evalu-

    ative distinctions, a normative political theory has to distinguish evaluatively

    between the kinds of claims to recognition it deems worthy of response.

    Moreover, as indicated, the fact that a claim to recognition is articulated publicly

    is not sufficient reason for regarding it as such. Indeed, we should beware of taking

    as our point of orientation those normative claims that have already gained pub-

    lic notice in social movements. For one thing, as Axel Honneth points out, there

    is a danger here of reducing social suffering and moral discontent to just that part

    of it that has already been made visible in the political public sphere by publicity-

    savvy organizations.17 For another, in every society there are structural and

    political reasons why some groups are more visible than others. Drawing atten-

    tion to everyday, embryonic forms of social misery and moral injustice that are no

    less pressing for not yet being in the public eye, Honneth makes the case for

    thematizing socially unjust states of affairs that so far have been deprived of public

    attention, and for speaking on behalf of those who suffer from them.18

    Honnethswords of caution are well-taken. Thus, if contemporary political theory is to

    respond to a need, expectation or demand for recognition of the kind I have

    attributed to the Slow Food movement, Welsh-language initiatives and Assembly

    for the Protection of Hijab, it should have good normative reasons for doing so.

    In the next section I provide one such reason.

    The Relevance of Hegel

    Why is public recognition of the value of particular substantive conceptions of the

    good, cultural traditions or religious beliefs and practices important from the

    point of view of normative political theory? One good reason is to avoid what we

    might call the privatization of ethical concerns.19 It is noteworthy that a trench-

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    84

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    11/21

    ant critique of ethical privatization can be found in Hegels Phenomenology of

    Spirit, to whose account of recognition Taylor is, of course, indebted.20Towards

    the end of that book, Hegel presents the Romantic understanding of morality as

    conscience as a step forward in the development of Spirit and, specifically, of the

    concept of moral freedom.21 In line with his dialectical view of history, he shows

    how morality as conscience overcomes some of the limitations of the Kantian

    interpretation of moral freedom as duty. At the same time, he shows how it has

    weaknesses of its own that give rise to new problems.

    Hegel regards the Romantic view of morality as conscience as overcoming the

    incoherence and duplicity of the Kantian conception of moral freedom. One

    of Hegels criticisms of Kant is that he locates moral dignity in a capacity for self-

    determination, while at the same time conceiving of self-determination as subjec-

    tion to a moral law whose authority derives from a source external to the self. The

    objection, if I understand it correctly, is that we cannot at one and the same timetake seriously the component ofself-prescription in the idea of moral freedom and

    attribute to some otherconsciousness the authority of the moral law the individual

    prescribes to herself. For Hegel, the Romantic view of morality as conscience

    addresses this objection by moving moral authority inwards. Rather than appeal-

    ing to an external moral authority (for example, the Kantian moral law), the

    Romantic self determines from its own self what is true or right: In the strength of

    its own self-assurance it possesses the majesty of absolute autarky.22 By seeing its

    own inner voice its conscience as the sole moral authority, it is able to do justice

    to the idea of moral freedom as moral self-determination and overcomes the

    shortcomings of the Kantian conception. However, its strength in this regard is

    also its weakness. As we have seen, the Romantic self possesses absolute autarky.

    Since it itself is the sole arbiter of the validity of its judgements and actions, no

    other self can judge their morality. Given that the self is always an empirical self,

    with a particular physical and psychic constitution, and particular experiences

    gained in real historical situations, this means, concretely, that we have no way of

    distinguishing between judgements and actions that meet the demands of objec-

    tive moral authority judgements and actions in conformity with the morallybinding law and the caprice of the individual and the contingency of her natural

    impulses and inclinations. As Hegel puts it: Conscience . . . in the majesty of its

    elevation above specific law and every content of duty, puts whatever content it

    pleases into its knowing and willing. It is the moral genius which knows the inner

    voice of what it immediately knows to be a divine voice . . .23

    There is a second reason why Hegel regards the Romantic view as a step for-

    ward in the development of the concept of moral freedom. Unlike the Kantian

    conception, in which the validity of the moral law is given prior to all experience

    and in which, as a consequence, moral freedom is essentially independent of

    recognition by others, the Romantic view ties the freedom of the individual to the

    recognition by others of the moral validity of her judgements and actions. But

    here, too, the weakness of the Romantic position is apparent. Since conscience is

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    85

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    12/21

    the sole arbiter of moral validity, recognition of the morally judging and acting

    individual is purely formal. The Romantic self declares itself to be the truth,24 and

    in so doing, recognizes every other self as a self who, in acting from conscience,

    always speaks the truth; in turn, it is acknowledged by every other self as such a

    self.25What is recognized, however, is not the moral quality of the selfs actions,

    but its formal capacity for self-determination. Since conscience possesses absolute

    autarky, no one individual can judge the moral quality of anothers judgements

    and actions; they can merely acknowledge them from the outside, as it were, as the

    expression of a self-contained source of moral validity. Using Taylors termin-

    ology we might say that this is the politics (or ethics) of equal dignity: Romantic

    selves focus on what we share in common, recognizing the universal human

    capacity for radical and absolute moral self-determination. However, Hegel holds

    purely formal recognition to have at least two unwelcome consequences. He sees

    it as leading, first, to feelings of emptiness and a pathological inability to act and,second, to social relations of mistrust and hostility.

    One unwelcome consequence of purely formal recognition is that it produces a

    hollow self that suffers from feelings of emptiness and incapacity for action;

    accordingly, for Hegel, the Romantic self is yet another form of unhappy con-

    sciousness.26 Since no external recognition of its substance is available, the self

    becomes a hollow object filled with a sense of emptiness. Moreover, in order to

    preserve the purity of its heart, it flees from contact with the actual world; thus,

    its self is reduced to extreme abstraction.27 It becomes disordered to the point of

    madness, wastes itself in yearning and pines away in consumption.28As Hegel puts

    it: In this transparent purity of its moments, an unhappy, so-called beautiful soul,

    its light dies away within it, and it vanishes like a shapeless vapour that dissolves

    into thin air.29

    Another unwelcome consequence of purely formal recognition is that it leads

    to relations of mistrust and hostility towards others that seriously threaten social

    and political cohesion. As we have seen, the Romantic self exists within purely

    formal relations of intersubjective recognition, in which each self is recognized as

    its own source of moral authority; since there can be no external acknowledge-ment of the value or worth of its moral judgements and actions, these become a

    purely private matter. As Hegel points out, since only each self can assess the

    moral validity of its judgements and action, each self can regard only its judge-

    ments and actions as morally good. The implication of this is that each self must

    regard the judgements and actions of others as evil. As he puts it: Others . . . do

    not know whether this conscience is morally good or evil, or rather they not only

    cannot know, but they must also take it to be evil.30 His point seems to be that, in

    the moral domain, everything that is not judged to be good is judged to be not

    good and what is morally not good is evil. At first glance this looks like an implau-

    sibly strong claim. On closer examination, however, it is hard to dispute. I take

    Hegel to mean that we cannot in the long run abstain from passing judgement on

    actions and beliefs we regard as morally relevant. If we do pass judgement on such

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    86

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    13/21

    actions and beliefs, our options are simple: they must either be judged to be

    morally good or morally not good (evil). If each self regards the others actions

    and judgments as evil, because only its own can be judged to be morally good, the

    inevitable result is reciprocal feelings of mistrust and hostility, radically under-

    mining the possibility of social and political cohesion.

    If Hegels argument is convincing, we have good reasons to seek to establish

    forms of social and political association that avoid ethical privatization. Moreover,

    it suggests that avoiding such privatization is a matter of establishing the right

    kind of relations of intersubjective recognition. In this regard Hegels critique of

    morality as conscience enhances Taylors account of the politics of recognition in

    at least two respects. First, whereas Taylor could be read as simply charting two

    steps in the movement of the western modern social imaginary, neither which is

    normatively better or worse than the other,31 Hegels approach is unequivocally

    normative: he not only insists that purely formal recognition is insufficient forthe purposes of realizing human freedom; he leaves no doubt that it hinders its

    realization.32 Second, Hegel suggests a way forward for the politics of recognition

    that is blocked by Taylors interpretation of particularity as difference, and dif-

    ference as inwardly generated uniqueness. As we have seen, Taylors account

    of the politics of difference ends in an impasse: he presents the politics of differ-

    ence as the historical successor to the politics of equal dignity, but interprets

    difference in a way that prevents the discriminating recognition the politics of

    difference requires in order to be coherent. By contrast Hegel indicates a solution

    to the problem he identifies. We have seen the problem to be the Romantic selfs

    absolute autarky in the domain of moral judgement; in other words, its claim to

    exclusive ownership of its ethical judgements and actions. In the final pages of the

    relevant section of thePhenomenology, Hegel offers an account of Spirits progres-

    sion beyond morality as conscience, which can be read as the eventual resolution

    of the problem.

    Although his account of the progression is not well developed, it contains some

    useful pointers. In this account, morality as conscience undergoes a number of

    unstable transitions before finally reaching a mode of consciousness in which theprevious tensions between self and others are reconciled.33 For our present pur-

    poses, the most significant feature of this progression is that Hegel describes it as

    a movement outwards.34 Instead of keeping its knowledge of itself to itself,35 refus-

    ing to let its own inner being come forth into the outer existence of speech,36 the

    self now brings its formerly completely inner being into outer existence.37 He

    refers to a reconciling Yea in which each self lets go of its formerly antithetical

    relation to the other, expanding its existence as a self-contained I into an inter-

    subjective one.38

    What I take from Hegels story is the claim that each self, if it is to progress

    towards the realization of moral freedom, must give up its claims to own its ethi-

    cal judgements and actions and release them into the public domain, where they

    will face the criticisms and challenges of other selves. In other words, if it is to

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    87

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    14/21

    progress towards the realization of moral freedom, the individual self may no

    longer see itself as the sole authority determining the value of its ethical judge-

    ments and actions; rather, the value of ethical judgements and actions becomes

    something to be worked out cooperatively by a plurality of selves in processes of

    public challenge and response. On such a view, ethical value is not something

    fixed and given, but rather a property that emerges processually by way of public

    contestation. I see this as a valuable intuition. In my concluding remarks I contend

    that a processual model of recognition fits best with a processual conception of

    ethical value.

    Beyond Honneths Formal Conception of Sittlichkeit

    Hegels critique of ethical privatization shows the importance of public recogni-

    tion of the value of ethical conceptions. It can be expanded to include relatedforms of privatization, such as the privatization of cultural traditions and the

    privatization of religious beliefs and practices. Thus, his critique of privatization

    calls on us to respond to the kind of concern for public recognition I attributed to

    the Slow Food movement, the Welsh-language initiatives and the Assembly for

    the Protection of Hijab. It is striking, however, that there has been little attention

    to a concern of this kind among contemporary theorists of recognition. Our dis-

    cussion in the foregoing helps to explain why it slips from view in Taylors

    account. But why is it disregarded by the other major contributors to current

    debates? Even Honneths critical social theory, which offers one of the most

    developed and differentiated contemporary accounts of the relation between

    human flourishing and recognition, has no room for the kind of concern for

    recognition I have attributed to the social movements mentioned. In the case of

    some other theorists, this could be traced back to their understanding of substan-

    tive ethical conceptions, cultural traditions and religious beliefs and practices as

    inherently private or local. Jrgen Habermas holds this view. This leads him, in

    the case of conceptions of the good and cultural traditions, to confine public dis-

    cussion to hermeneutic explication39

    and, in the case of religious beliefs andpractices, to a salvaging operation in which the parties involved in discussion seek

    to rescue potentially valuable contents for the secular imagination by translating

    them into a secular vocabulary.40 Honneth rejects what he sees as Habermass

    overly deontological, Kantian approach. In his view, Kantian approaches make

    the mistake of splitting off questions of the selfs duties to others from questions

    relating to self-realization.41Against this, Honneth seeks to reintegrate the ques-

    tions What ought I to do? and What is the best life for me as a human being?

    At the same time, he is wary of communitarian approaches, which construe the

    good for human beings in terms of the substantive values that constitute the ethos

    of a particular community. Instead, he seeks to steer a middle path between

    Kantian and communitarian approaches by proposing a formal conception of

    ethical life (Sittlichkeit); this specifies only the conditions necessary for self-

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    88

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    15/21

    realization, leaving open the question of which substantive values are the right

    ones. Since Honneth sees recognition by others in a number of dimensions as a

    necessary condition of self-realization, this has consequences for his theory of

    recognition. It explains his endeavour to specify the relations of recognition

    required for self-realization in terms that make no commitment to substantive

    ethical values. Thus, the three principal relations of recognition he identifies are

    designed to be sufficiently abstract to avoid raising the suspicion that they reflect

    a particular vision of the good life. These are, first, recognition of the other as a

    particular object of love or affection; second, recognition of the other as the bearer

    of legal rights; and third, recognition of the other for her individual achievements

    or contributions to society (Leistung).42The kind of concern for recognition under

    discussion in the foregoing cannot be accommodated in this schema. It is obvi-

    ously not a form of recognition of the other as a particular object of love and

    affection and it is hard to see how it could be construed as a form of recognitionof individual achievements or contributions. The category into which it most

    easily fits is that of recognition of the other as a bearer of legal rights. However,

    as our examples of certain social movements showed, while recognition of rights

    is often also an issue, granting the rights in question would not fully satisfy their

    concern for recognition.43

    I have suggested that the inability of Honneths schema to accommodate recog-

    nition of the value of specific substantive ethical conceptions, cultural traditions

    and religious beliefs and practices is due to his concern to avoid making self-

    realization dependent on particular substantive values. This concern is laudable.

    Were his theory to specify in advance the ethical ingredients of a good life, it

    would undermine the individuals capacity to form and develop her own concep-

    tions of the good in other words, her autonomy. Nonetheless, Honneth seems

    to have missed the middle path he seeks and to have taken instead the Kantian

    turning. In his efforts to avoid the danger he associates with communitarianism,

    he adopts a Kantian position on ethical value: one that abstracts from the par-

    ticular ends of individual and groups. He needs to set his theory back onto the

    middle path. This requires him to find a way of recognizing the value of particu-lar substantive conceptions of the good, cultural traditions and religious beliefs

    and practices without pre-empting the question of which values are the right ones.

    In my discussion of Hegel, I hinted at a solution. As I read Hegels account of

    Spirits progression beyond morality as conscience, this is to be understood as a

    movement outwards, whereby moral authority is released from its confinement in

    inner being and discharged into processes of contestation in the public domain.

    This means that ethical value is no longer something each individual determines

    for herself by looking inwards, but a matter to be worked out with other indi-

    viduals in cooperative processes of challenge and response. Such a processual

    conception of ethical value has the advantage that it does not specify in advance

    which judgements and actions are the right ones; rather, it takes seriously indi-

    vidual autonomy by making it a task for the individuals concerned. Honneth could

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    89

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    16/21

    find the middle path he seeks by understanding ethical value in this way. To be

    sure, he would have to modify his theory of recognition accordingly and expand

    his schema of relations of recognition to include a concern for recognition of

    particular substantive ethical conceptions, cultural traditions and religious beliefs

    and practices. This is not a problem in principle. Since the schema in its present

    form depends on a combination of empirical and normative arguments, it can

    easily be expanded if there are good empirical and normative reasons for doing so.

    My discussion in the foregoing provides such reasons. In order to see this, a few

    words on the status of Honneths theory of recognition may be helpful.

    As indicated, Honneth justifies his schema of three relations of recognition by

    way of a combination of empirical and normative arguments. To begin with, his

    argument has a strong empirical component.44The three relations of recognition

    he identifies are held to be normative expectations that have emerged in the

    historical passage towards bourgeois modernity.45

    He claims that they build oncertain anthropologically rooted conditions of intact personality formation, but

    have taken on their specific shape as expectations of love or affection, of equal

    respect and of recognition of achievements or contributions only in the course of

    the last few hundred years. The claim that these are thesalient relations of recog-

    nition in contemporary capitalist societies relies on the support of convincing

    empirical arguments. However, on their own, empirical arguments are insuffi-

    cient. As we have seen, the actual articulation of a demand for recognition, or even

    the empirically verifiable existence of a need or desire for recognition, is not yet

    reason to satisfy it. This is why empirical arguments must go hand in hand with

    normative arguments, which are always guided by a particular vision of human

    flourishing.46 In Honneths case, the vision guiding his theory is one of human

    freedom in three dimensions corresponding to the three spheres of recognition

    mentioned.47 It is against the background of this idea of freedom that we can

    understand one of his central theses: the claim that failure to meet the specified

    expectations of recognition results in social pathologies.48

    Since Honneths schema of relations of recognition relies on a combination of

    empirical and normative arguments, it is open to challenge by convincing argu-ments of these kinds. My discussion in the foregoing has supplied such arguments.

    Empirically, it has identified in contemporary social reality a concern for recog-

    nition of the value of particular substantive ethical conceptions, cultural traditions

    and religious beliefs and practices, which cannot be accommodated within his

    schema as it stands. Normatively, it has suggested that lack of public recognition

    of the value of particular substantive ethical conceptions, cultural traditions and

    religious beliefs and practices may lead to social pathologies, specifically to feel-

    ings of emptiness and an incapacity for action and to mistrust of, and hostility

    towards, others.

    Thus, my argument challenges Honneths schema in a productive manner by

    supplying good empirical and normative reasons for why he should expand it.

    Furthermore, the processual conception of value I have proposed fits well with his

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    90

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    17/21

    processual conception of recognition. For, as the word struggle in the title of his

    first major work on recognition makes clear,49 recognition for him is not a static

    concept, but a dynamic relation that is fought for in processes of social contesta-

    tion and, once obtained, always open to new challenges.

    Concluding Remarks

    This way of understanding the concept of recognition helps us to answer the ques-

    tion of what it would mean to respond to the concern for public recognition of the

    value of particular ethical conceptions, cultural traditions and religious beliefs and

    practices. Drawing together the strands of our discussion, we can now say that

    taking seriously this kind of concern for recognition calls for open-ended public

    processes of contestation in which individuals and groups seek to convince others

    of the value of particular substantive ethical conceptions, cultural traditions andreligious beliefs and practices.50 For reasons I have elaborated elsewhere, such

    public processes of contestation should always involve the exchange of powerful

    arguments and counter-arguments, although non-argumentative forms of public

    contestation may play a significant, if subsidiary, role.51 I have also argued that

    such public processes of contestation should take place at the formal level of politi-

    cal decision-making and law-making, as well as in the informal public sphere.52

    Four further observations are important here.

    First, in many cases, the projected goal is not general agreement that a particularsubstantive conception of the good, tradition, belief or practice should beembraced by everyone. For example, while the aim of the Slow Food movementdoes seem to be that everyone should adopt eco-gastronomy as a way of life, theother two movements mentioned do not share this universalizing aspiration. Theaim of the Welsh-language initiatives is not that everyone should speak the Welshlanguage, but that everyone should acknowledge that speaking the Welsh lan-guage is a vital element in maintaining a particular valuable cultural tradition.Similarly, the aim of the Assembly for the Protection of Hijab is not that every-

    one should wear the hijab, but that everyone should acknowledge that wearing thehijab is the expression of a particular deeply held, valuable religious belief. In suchcases, the projected general agreement does not universalize the value in question:it is not a matter of everyone agreeing that it is valuablefor everyone, but of every-

    one agreeing that it as a valuable way of life forsome individuals or groups.53To besure, in order to avoid subjectivism, the argument that something is valuablefor particular individuals and groups must attribute some degree of subject-independent value to the good in question. Thus, the argument would be, forexample, that speaking Welsh is valuable for particular individuals and groups

    because that language offers possibilities for expression that would not otherwisebe available; further, that expressivity is good. Or, that wearing the hijab isvaluable for particular individuals and groups because the power of God can beexperienced only by those who live their lives in certain ways and that wearing thehijab is one of these ways; further, that experiencing the power of God is good. In

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    91

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    18/21

    allowing for public discussion of the value of something particular, this position issimilar to Taylors presumption of worth: his view that the prerequisite for dia-logue is a presumption that a particular cultural identity is valuable. However,Taylor then blocks the path towards testing this presumption in dialogue byinterpreting particularity as difference and difference as inwardly generated

    uniqueness. I unblock the path by focusing, instead, on claims to recognitionraised on behalf of particular substantive conceptions of the good, cultural tradi-tions and religious beliefs and practices.

    Second, even in cases where the projected goal is general agreement that the

    value in question is valuable for everyone, this should not be understood as a deon-

    tological prescription. It should be understood, instead, as an invitation: the indi-

    viduals and groups who seek recognition that the value in question is valuable for

    everyone invite us to see the world in a new way. In such cases, accordingly, uni-

    versalization involves a change in perceptions. If autonomy is to be respected, suchchanges may not be imposed; they can only be encouraged by opening our eyes to

    new possibilities and perspectives. Typically, such processes of disclosure and

    cognitive transformation involve changes in behaviour as well as powerful argu-

    ments. Thus, the Slow Food movement does not insist that eco-gastronomy is

    mandatory for all human beings, but hopes that we will all come to recognize it as

    a way of life conducive to human flourishing by hearing the movements message

    of plate and planet and by taking steps to live our lives in a corresponding way.

    Third, the idea of general agreement whether it is agreement by everyone that

    something is valuable for some people or agreement by everyone that somethingis valuable for everyone is an imaginative projection. It conjures the idea of a

    harmonious condition of perfect understanding and insight. Such a condition is

    not an attainable goal of human action; nonetheless, its projection serves to ori-

    ent such action. In other words, general agreement is not an achievable state of

    affairs, but a regulative idea that orients practices of contestation.54

    Finally, as indicated, recognition in practice is a dynamic relation. Individuals

    and groups seek to win recognition from others in never-ending struggles for

    recognition (Honneth), for recognition, even if obtained and institutionalizedpolitically, is always subject to new contestation.

    Taken together these observations provide the basis for the account of recog-

    nition most appropriate for responding publicly to claims for the value of

    particular substantive ethical conceptions, cultural traditions and religious beliefs

    and practices under conditions of value-pluralism. In the spirit of Honneth, such

    an account of recognition allows for a public response to claims of this kind with-

    out pre-empting the question of which values are the right ones. In the spirit of

    Taylor, it allows for a politics that is hospitable to particularity though indiffer-

    ent to difference without endorsing it in an uncritical way.55

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    92

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    19/21

    Notes

    1. C. Taylor, The Politics of Recognition in A. Gutmann (ed.) (1994)Multiculturalism:Examining the Politics of Recognition, pp. 2572. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    2. Ibid. p. 39.3. See C. Calhoun (1995) Critical Social Theory: Culture, History, and the Challenge of

    Difference, pp. 21516. Oxford: Blackwell. Citing Calhoun approvingly, Axel Honneth,too, finds Taylors thesis of a shift from a concern with legal equality to a concern withcultural identity and difference historically misleading and accuses him, in addition, ofover-dramatizing the differences between the politics of equal dignity and the politics ofdifference. See A. Honneth, Redistribution as Recognition: A Response to Nancy

    Fraser, in N. Fraser and A. Honneth (2005)Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange, pp. 1224. London: Verso.

    4. M. Cooke (1997) Authenticity and Autonomy: Taylor, Habermas, and the Politics ofRecognition,Political Theory 25(2): 26090.

    5. Taylor (n. 1), p. 69.

    6. Ibid. p. 69.7. I propose a conception of autonomy along these lines in M. Cooke (2006)Re-Presenting

    the Good Society, pp. 133145. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    8. Taylor (n. 1), pp. 6373.9. http://www.slowfood.com

    10. http://www.mentrau-iaith.com11. http://www.prohijab.net12. See e.g. J. Alexander (2006) The Civil Sphere, pp. 42557. Oxford: Oxford University

    Press.13. Alexander (n. 12) holds this view.

    14. Ibid. pp. 4507.15. Alexander argues that in the multicultural mode of incorporation rigid distinctions

    between insider and outsider groups break down and difference and particularitybecome sources of cross-group identification. In his view, accordingly, multiculturalintegration not only reconfigures the categories of outsider and insider in moreuniversalistic and egalitarian ways; it also extends the range of imagined life-experiences

    for members of the insider group.16. I address the problem of critical evaluation in more detail in Cooke (n. 7), where I

    outline the key features of a model of practical reasoning appropriate for contexts ofvalue pluralism.

    17. Honneth (n. 3), p. 115.18. Ibid. pp. 11316.19. I use the term ethical in a loose sense to refer to conceptions of the good. What I say

    about ethical conceptions can, I suggest, be extended to religious beliefs and culturaltraditions.

    20. G. W. F. Hegel (1977) The Phenomenology of Spirit, tr. A. V. Miller. Oxford: ClarendonPress. Cf. Taylor (n. 1), p. 36.

    21. Following Hegel I use the terms ethical and moral interchangeably in the following.22. Hegel (n. 20), p. 393, 646.

    23. Ibid. p. 397, 655.

    24. Hegel underscores the linguistic component of this kind of recognition, seeing it ascrucial to its claim to universality. I cannot explore this further in the present context.

    25. Ibid. p. 397, 654.26. Ibid. pp. 399400, 658. It may be noted that Axel Honneth sees feelings of emptiness

    of the Hegelian kind as one of the pathologies of contemporary capitalism. See A.

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    93

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    20/21

    Honneth (2002) Organisierte Selbstverwirklichung: Paradoxien derSelbstverwirklichung, in A. Honneth (ed.) Befreiung aus der Mndigkeit: Paradoxien des

    gegenwrtigen Kapitalismus, pp. 1427 (here p. 146), Frankfurt and New York: Campus

    Verlag. See also A. Honneth (2001) Suffering from Indeterminacy. An Attempt at theReactualization of Hegels Philosophy of Right. Amsterdam: Spinoza Lectures.

    27. Hegel (n. 20), p. 400, 658.28. Ibid. p. 407, 668.29. Ibid. p. 400, 658.

    30. Ibid.31. Taylor does not argue explicitly that the historical progression from the politics of equal

    dignity to the politics of difference constitutes a normative gain.32. By contrast, it is not clear whether or not Taylor regards all versions of the politics of

    equal dignity as to some degree harmful; certainly, he holds the view that not all versionsare equally homogenizing: see Taylor (n. 1), pp. 5173.

    33. Hegel (n. 20), pp. 398409, 65770. The key transitions described by Hegel are frommorality as conscience to the beautiful soul and, from there, to the confessing,

    hardhearted and, ultimately, forgiving consciousness.34. Ibid, esp. pp. 4078, 66971.35. Ibid. p. 406, 668.36. Ibidp. 405, 667.37. Ibid. p. 408, 670.

    38. Ibid. p. 409, 671.39. J. Habermas (1996) Between Facts and Norms, tr. W. Rehg, pp. 15768. Cambridge, MA:

    MIT Press.40. J. Habermas (2008) Between Naturalism and Religion, tr. C. Cronin. Cambridge, MA: MIT

    Press.41. A. Honneth (1995) The Struggle for Recognition, tr. J. Anderson, pp. 1729. Cambridge:

    Polity Press.42. Ibid., esp. pp. 92130. In this book, Honneth described the third sphere of recognition as

    that of solidarity. In his more recent work, he no longer refers to it as such, speaking

    instead of recognition of achievements or contributions (Leistung): see e. g. Honneth(n. 3), pp. 14550.

    43. In his exchange with Nancy Fraser, Honneth does consider the possibility of theemergence of a fourth principle of recognition within the normative infrastructure of

    capitalist societies: a principle that calls for social recognition of members of a culturalgroup: see Honneth (n. 3), pp. 16170. Indeed, he even acknowledges that one of themultiple ways of interpreting this demand is as a demand to recognize the culture inquestion as valuable in itself. However, he sees no possibility of dealing with the problem

    of critical evaluation to which this gives rise. In the end, he remains sceptical as towhether this kind of demand represents a legitimate fourth principle of recognition.

    44. A. Honneth (2002) Grounding Recognition: A Rejoinder to Critical Questions,Inquiry45(4): 500.

    45. Honneth (n. 3), pp. 1367 and (n. 44), p. 501.

    46. See Cooke (n. 7).47. In his exchange with Nancy Fraser, Honneth presents his work as a recognitive theory of

    justice: see Honneth (n. 3). It is important to grasp, however, that in this context he usesthe term justice in a broad sense: as more or less equivalent to the normative goal of his

    critical social theory, which he variously describes as freedom or autonomy or self-realization. He makes this particularly clear in Honneth (n. 44), pp. 51617.

    48. A. Honneth (1994) The Social Dynamics of Disrespect: On the Location of CriticalTheory Today, Constellations1(2): 25569.

    European Journal of Political Theory8(1)

    94

    by E G on April 20, 2009http://ept.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/http://ept.sagepub.com/
  • 7/25/2019 Cooke, "Beyond dignity and difference"

    21/21

    49. Honneth (n. 41).50. My call for public deliberation concerning substantive values, esp. ones that are particular

    to certain individuals and groups, raises a number of epistemological issues, such as

    whether we must presuppose a common concern with a shared conception of truth. Idiscuss the issue of truth in M. Cooke (2008) Religion in the Democratic Public

    Sphere: Does Truth Matter? Paper delivered at Reset Dialogues on CivilizationIstanbul Seminars, 26 June.51. Cooke (n. 7), esp. ch. 6.

    52. See M. Cooke (2007) A Secular State for a Secular Society? Postmetaphysical PoliticalTheory and the Place of Religion, Constellations14(2): 22438.

    53. I make a distinction between (a) conceptions whose validity is accepted by everyone andare also deemed to be valid for everyone and (b) conceptions whose validity is merely

    accepted by everyone. See M. Cooke (1994) Recognizing the Post-Conventional Self,Philosophy and Social Criticism 20(12): 87101.

    54. I discuss ideas of the good society as imaginative projections and make a case for theplace of regulative ideas in critical social thinking in Cooke (n. 7), esp. chs 5 and 6.

    55. I am grateful to Jonathan Seglow for helpful comments.

    Cooke: Beyond Dignity and Difference

    95