Conscience and Spirit in Id St

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    1/18

    2005.Idealistic Studies,Volume 35, Issues 23. ISSN 0046-8541. pp. 119136

    CONSCIENCE, RECOGNITION, AND THEIRREDUCIBILITY OF DIFFERENCE IN

    HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    Nathan Andersen

    Abstract: Hegels conception of Spirit does not subordinate difference to same-

    ness, in a way that would make it unusable for a genuinely intersubjective idealism

    directed to a comprehensive account of the contemporary world. A close analysis

    of the logic of recognition and the dialectic of conscience in the Phenomenology

    of Spirit demonstrates that the unity of Spirit emerges in and through conflict,

    and is forged in the process whereby particular encounters between differently

    situated individuals reveal and establish the emerging character and significance

    of the stances they uniquely occupy.

    It is a familiar problem in recent philosophy1that to the extent my experience of another

    person can be assimilated to ready-made experiential categories, I have not really gotten

    beyond myself. Rather, in the experience of the apparentother, I have merely reconfirmed

    or reconnected with a prior sense of self-identity. If Hegels conception of Spirit, whose

    substance and existence is described in the Phenomenology of Spiritas pure self-recogni-

    tion in absolute otherness (reine Selbsterkennen im absoluten Anderssein),2is no more than

    the identity achieved when the self discovers that what appearedto be other is really just

    an integral moment in an expanded conception of itself, then it would appear that absolute

    otherness in no way refers to a genuineother. Even if such an experience were to reveal

    that my individual sense of self, along with my familiar categories, is grounded in a more

    primordial identification with others in a shared world, that would only serve to expand my

    self-awareness. It may be that I then come to identify with a universal self as opposed to

    the merely individual self that finds itself opposed to and related to others in the world,

    but what would remain unchallenged in this experience is the priority of self and of self-

    identity over disruption and alterity. An expanded sense of the subject, in other words, does

    not amount to a rigorous account of a diversely constituted, intersubjective world.

    This essay will aim to demonstrate that Hegels conception of Spirit does notleave

    unchallenged the priority of self-identity over difference, and does not on that account

    fail to do justice to the claims of intersubjectivity. At the same time, it is a conception

    that recognizes genuine differences to form a point of contact, whereby is constituted an

    emerging unity that gives significance to difference at the same time as it is shaped bythese differences. I will argue that what Hegel means by Spirit, particularly in the Phe-

    nomenology, is best conceived in relation to the phenomenon of conscientious conflict

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    2/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES120

    and reconciliation, the analysis of which concludes his chapter entitled Spirit. The

    universality of Spirit, on this conception, is not one that subsumes differences between

    individuals; rather, it is a universality that is forged through the process whereby particular

    encounters with others who are differently situated not only reveal but also establish theemergingcharacter and significance of the stances they uniquely occupy.

    I will begin with an examination of Hegels concept of recognition, that will show

    the genuine universality of recognition to be an achievement, that cannot therefore serve

    as an a priori ground for the individuals who engage in the process of recognition. This

    should not, however, be taken to imply that the individuals who engage in this process

    are settled in themselvesprior to the formation of community. If this were the case, then

    the conception of Spirit that emerges when the process of recognition is taken as central

    would appear incompatible with Hegels repeated assertions of the foundational character

    of unity and community. The distinctness of the individuals who communally constitutecommunity is, on Hegels account, at one and the same time formed by and formative of

    the act of recognition.

    Following a brief account of recognition, I will turn to a more detailed analysis of

    Hegels discussion of conscience, and will conclude by showing what Spirit looks like

    when conceived on the model of conscientious conflict and reconciliation. Conscientious

    conflict in fact demonstrates both universality and individuality to emerge out of the

    determinateparticularityof contact and conflict, which is to say that unityand compre-

    hensionis just as much fragmentationand difference. For the reconciliation that takes

    place between conscientious selves who find themselves compelled to differ is not onethat overcomes that difference, but is rather the discovery of a kind of unity that emerges

    in and through conflict. This conception of Geist, then, is best characterized as Hegel

    does in fact characterize Spirit, at the beginning of his Spirit chapter: as bothunshaken

    righteous self-identity (die unwankende gerechte Sichselbstgleichheit) andfragmented

    being, self-sacrificing and benevolent, in which each accomplishes his own work, rends

    asunder the universal being and takes from it his own share (das aufgelste, das sich

    aufopfernde gtige Wesen, an dem Jeder sein eignes Werk vollbringt, das allgemeine Sein

    zerreit und sich seinen Teil davon nimmt).3

    I. Universal and Individual as Achievements

    The most extensive characterization of recognition in the Phenomenology of Spiritcomes

    in Hegels chapter on self-consciousness.4Hegel argues that a stable self-consciousness

    cannot be achieved in isolation from others. To secure the satisfaction of knowing ones

    own independence, one must have this independence affirmed by another who is like

    oneself.That means, however, that one cannot be simply self-conscious. One cannot be

    aware of oneself alone, but must at the same time be aware of another upon whom ones

    own identity as distinctive depends. The moment of self-consciousness coincides, accord-ing to Hegel, with the consciousness of the other.

    In a very helpful commentary on this passage, John Burbidge notes that the features

    which characterize his [that is, the consciousness whose identity is here at stake] own

    intrinsic nature are presented to him as something external. He thus learns that he is simply

    an instance of a more general universal.5This is the first stage in the process of recognition,

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    3/18

    121HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    the stage of universality, that shows the discovery of oneself asa self to coincide with the

    discovery of other selves. This discovery is, therefore, just as much a loss of self, insofar

    as it involves the recognition of oneself as not unique but like others. To secure a sense of

    itself in distinction from others the recognizing consciousness must engage at some level ina struggle to deny or overcome the appearance of a likeness with the other. In denying its

    similarity with the other, however, the recognizing consciousness at the same time affirms

    that the other is distinct from itself. This is the stage ofparticularity. To be a particular is

    to be among others, from which one is distinguished. That to affirm itself as itself, it must

    affirm its difference from the other, reveals that, contrary to its assumption of complete

    and utter independence, the identity of the other asdistinct mattersto the identity of the

    first. The first can recognize itself in particular only insofar as it recognizes the other to

    be specifically distinct from itself. The final stage of recognition, that of individuality,

    makes this result explicit. An awareness of difference alonedoes not individuate, for theawareness of themselves as different fromeach other establishes the two selves just as

    much for themselves in relationto one another. According to Burbidge, the individual

    becomes aware of himself as similar to the other even in the difference, and because he

    becomes aware of the other as different even in the similarity, he becomes conscious of

    the uniqueness of the other, and hence grants him freedom.6

    Burbidges analysis of recognition, that highlights the roles of universality, particularity

    and individuality within that process, is valuable for emphasizing that genuine universal-

    ity isforgedthrough a process of differentiation between particular selves. Community

    and communication generally are achieved only through the process whereby individualscome to discover the character of their own individual identity by positing this identity in

    contrast to that of others. His analysis makes clear, at the same time, that the individuals

    for whom this community is generated do not themselves exist as these individuals prior

    to the process of recognition. He points out that for Hegel the three stages of this mu-

    tual recognition cannot be interpreted sequentially, but only as moments in an integrated

    activity.7Since to be a self requires at least the practical recognition of oneself as such,

    and recognition of oneself comes by way of a recognition of another, that would imply

    that neither the individual nor the community are original in the sense of preceding one

    another. Burbidges analysis of communication, in particular, highlights the fact that not

    only does the individual discoverherself as an individual in relation to others through

    the process of recognition, but that her identity as individual is itself a resultthat comes

    with the achievement of community.

    Neither the universality of community nor the singularity of the individual are prior

    on Hegels conception of Spirit. Rather, these are mutually implicating moments in a

    process whereby the illuminative contrasts between individuals in fact contribute to the

    formation of each in their differences and thereby bring them into significant connection.

    Since the community that emerges in this process does not erase, but in fact reconfirmsand establishes the absolute character of differences, Spirit is best conceived not merely

    as universal and individual, but always at once as particular. Spirit makes itself manifest,

    or brings itself to self-consciousnessand hence comes into beingonly in and through

    the particularities of the concrete processes whereby situated individuals come to know

    themselves through encounters with others.

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    4/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES122

    II. The Community of Conscience: Reconciliation In and Through Conflict

    This is demonstrated perhaps most powerfully by Hegels analysis of conscientious ac-

    tion, action that proceeds according to the principle that an agent can only be responsible

    to the moral demands of a particular situation insofar as she experiences those demands.Since one can never have more than a partial understanding of the total situation wherein

    one acts, the principle of conscience takes this partially illuminated situation to bethe

    genuinesituation of action, in relationship to which alone the conscientious action can

    legitimately be evaluated. The conscientious agent insists therefore, that all action be

    judged according to the particular demands of the conscience of the agent alone. This

    insistence, however, calls upon her the judgment that she has violated her own criterion,

    insofar as she expects others to act in accordance with a general principle. She expects

    others to judge her actions, not according to theirunique perspective on these actions,

    but solely in accordance with herclaim to have acted conscientiously. This conflict, aswe will see, motivates a resolution that does not so much dissolve the conflict as reveal,

    in an exemplary fashion, the productive dimension of contrasting self-definitions. The

    conscientious agent comes to recognize that the truth of the situation in which she has

    an individual obligation to act is not comprised merely of the circumstances of action as

    they appear to herself all at once. Rather, the truth of her situation is what dynamically

    unfolds as she risks action on the basis of a limited perspective and finds herself obliged

    to reformulate that perspective as a result of discovering the compelling character of the

    judgments of others that this action calls down upon itself.

    A. Conscience as Extreme Individuality:

    The Place of Conscience in the Philosophy of Right

    There is a difficulty posed for an interpretation of Hegelian Spirit that takes the dialectic of

    conscience as its model. For Hegel appears to claim the need to get beyond conscience. The

    problem with the ideal of conscience is that it appears to sanction an extreme subjectivism

    as a grounds for action, and Hegel criticizes it on just these grounds in the Philosophy of

    Right. If in the last analysis all we can appeal to is ourselves, and our subjective knowl-

    edge of our own situations, this would appear to render mutual recognition impossible.Jay Bernstein has articulated the basic problem very well:

    As modern agents the ultimate barrier to our self-recognition in absolute otherness

    is formed by our understanding of ourselves as autonomous moral beings. If we are

    autonomous, then nothing on heaven and earth can tell us what is right other than

    our conscience; but myconscience cannot be an absolute touchstone of rightness

    if yours is too. If I uphold the dictates of my conscience, then I cannot recognize

    myself in your conscientious claims. Conversely, if I surrender my conscience

    to the dictates of yours then I surrender my pure self-recognition; I become your

    moral beast or slave.8

    It is for this reason that a number of commentators (though notBernstein) have considered that

    conscience is a stance that will ultimately need to be left behind in the progress of Spirit.9

    To make more clear the objection, I will turn briefly to Hegels analysis of conscience

    in the Philosophy of Right, where Hegel himself identifies forcefully the problems with

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    5/18

    123HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    asserting the primacy of conscience as justification for action.10In the Philosophy of Right,

    Hegels discussion of conscience forms the culminating moment in his analysis of moral

    rights, rights as they apply in the sphere of self-determininghuman activity. Ones moral

    right is to recognize oneself, and to be recognized by others, as responsible for onesown activity. The developments that Hegel traces within the sphere of morality, and that

    culminate in a position advocating the primacy of conscience, can in fact be illustrated

    in terms of a basic ambiguity in the notion of responsibility.11One can, basically, be

    responsible for something both in the sense that one has causedit and in the sense that

    one is to be held accountablefor it. So, to begin with, the moral self is responsible for

    its activity in the (first) sense that it recognizes its own contributions to the world asits

    own, and has the rightto be regarded as their originator. To act is to carry out ones own

    purposesin the world, and one is therefore responsible(in the second sense) for ones

    own action and its consequences.12With freedom comes accountability.Yet no one can reasonably be held accountable for those consequences of action that

    she was unable to anticipate, which implies that as a moral agent one has the right to be

    responsible solely for ones intentions. Actions are to be evaluated, therefore, in light of

    what the agent was tryingto achieve, even if what she in fact achieves goes against what

    would abstractly be conceived as right. The moral agent has the right, in other words, to

    act for the sake of what she takes to be good, for herself and others.13It is an abstraction,

    moreover, to oppose a genuine and universal Good to the merely particular goods that

    individuals aim to achieve. For every achievement of what is taken to be Good universally

    is always the product of particular actions on the part of individuals aiming to achieveparticular goods. On the other hand, there can be no achievement of particular goods ex-

    cept where there is freedom for all to pursue particular aims,14which requires the mutual

    recognition of a Good that is not merely particular.

    By itself, however, the recognition of an obligation to the Good cannot specify how

    one must act in particular situations. It amounts to no more than the formal dictum: One

    should do what is right or one should strive after ones own welfare and the welfare of

    others.15In the end, the principle of dutyto the Good has no content of its own, and it is

    only what is experienced asobligating that counts as an actual duty. We doexperience

    obligation, and in particular obligation that constrains against the experience of what

    is merely inclination; yet it is only actual obligationto the extent that it doesconstrain,

    and finds expression in determinate action. Thisexperience of active obligation is what

    Hegel identifies as conscience(Gewissen):16the absolute inward certainty (Gewissheit)

    of himself, that which establishes the particular and is the determining and decisive ele-

    ment in him.17

    The principle of conscience recognizes rightly the universal necessity (and Good-

    ness) of individual determination in all action. There can be no duty, or good, that is not

    recognized as such and willed by the individual. The problem with conscience is that itappears to make the necessity and rightnessof individual determination for all action into

    an abstract principle. To operate on the principle of conscience is to anticipate that ones

    actions will be recognized and respected merely as the product of an unassailable individual

    sense of obligation or duty. It is, however, at the same time to respect the rights of others

    to carry out their own actions in their own particular circumstances in accordance with the

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    6/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES124

    dictates of their own conscience. That means that the conscientious agent cannot justly

    complain when her actions are not given the acceptance she anticipates; for the rejection

    of these actions is itself justified when it proceeds from the opposed convictions of oth-

    ers. As a merely formal principle, the conscientiousness of action cannot in fact sanctionany particular action or content. It acknowledges in general the power of the individual to

    determine the content of the good, but for that reason has nothing to say when the good

    is determined differently by different individuals.

    The true contentof conscientious action, however, is not merely thefactthat it is the

    product of individual determination. This individual determination acquires significance

    and status as an action only insofar as it makes a difference to the determinate situation

    that called it forth. The true conscience, that Hegel differentiates from the merely abstract

    formal conscience he discusses in the section on Morality in the Philosophy of Right,

    recognizes the authority of the state because it knows that whether what it considersordeclares to be goodis also actually good, can be recognized only from the contentof this

    supposed good,18and that the contentof the action is inseparable from its status within

    the instituted systems for interpersonal recognition that comprise the situation wherein

    the action takes place. Genuine conscience, in other words, discovers itself only as the

    individual commitment to carrying out the social institutions that give place toand yet

    for that reason are themselves transformed and defined byits conscientious actions.

    That is why I find it odd that Daniel Dahlstrom, who rightly notices that the true con-

    science plays an important role in the sphere of Ethics as well as in Morality, nevertheless

    points outin his otherwise compelling commentary on the role of morality and consciencein the Philosophy of Rightthat Hegel has, it bears noting, notoriously little to say about

    this genuine conscience as such in the third part of the Philosophy of Right.19As I take

    it, the third part of the Philosophy of Rightis allabout genuine conscience.20The division

    of the Philosophy of Rightthat deals with ethics can essentially be taken as an answer to

    the question: where, in the context of the objective reality of social life do we encoun-

    ter actualindividual conviction with a content, of a kind whose formalcharacteristics

    are proclaimed by conscience? On Hegels account, we find such conviction in ethical

    institutions: in mature stages of marriage and family life, for example, wherein the ques-

    tion whether one will or should take care of ones family, or discipline and educate ones

    child, never comes up as a real concern. It is something that one mustdo, as a matter of

    conscience. This particular example is a good one, because to be ethically committed to

    family life requires that one notfix onto the merely formal principle of conscience. It is

    the conscientious recognition of obligation, not to oneself, but to the particular demands

    of a determinate family lifethat teaches the individual family member in the first place

    the significance of his or her individual efforts to satisfy this obligation.

    The solution to problems Hegel identifies with the formal principle of conscience in

    the Philosophy of Rightis not to give up on the irreducible character of individual self-determination that it rightly proclaims. Rather, it is for the conscientious agent to come to

    recognize the demands and judgments on the part of others in response to its action to be

    themselves called forth by and definitive for the character of its immediately experienced

    conscientious obligation. The individual conscience has its reality and significance only

    in the reciprocal process whereby it discovers that reality and significance reflected back

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    7/18

    125HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    to itself through another. The principle of conscience is not, according to this analysis,

    opposed to the process of recognition, but in fact demands it. This result will become

    more clear in the next section, in the context of an analysis of Hegels discussion of con-

    science in the Phenomenology of Spirit. I will show how there, within Hegels account ofconscience itself, conscience comes to recognize the limits of its purely individual stance,

    and commits itself to the demands of intersubjective recognition.

    B. The Dialectic of Conscientious Recognition in the Phenomenology of Spirit

    The dialectic of conscientious recognition comes in the final section of Hegels chapter

    on Spirit in the Phenomenology. The chapter as a whole examines the dynamics of the

    relation between individuals and the communal institutions and activities in relation to

    which they define themselves, and out of which they are formed. The study of conscience

    follows an examination of two forms of communal life based on, first, the integration ofindividual into the community, and secondly, the formation of a community rooted in

    the importance of the individual. The problems that emerge within the first two forms of

    communal life can be traced to a failure, within the relationship between individual and

    community, to make explicit and live up to the demands of the three stages of recognition

    as I have outlined them above. The ethical substance, whose dialectical tensions Hegel

    illustrates in terms of the complex relation between family and state in ancient Greece,

    acknowledges particular differences between individuals, but treats these differences as

    having their sole significance in the demand that each individual carry out the role to

    which he or she is suited by virtue of the particular place he or she occupies within the

    pre-established community of the ethical substance. As John Russon puts it, this com-

    munity fails to recognize its dependence upon decisions made by singular agents on

    behalf of the community.21The world of culture, by contrast, takes individuality as its

    highest value. At the same time, however, it fails to recognize that individuals can define

    and express themselves only through engaging in particular actions that embed themselves

    within specific traditions, and that relate themselves to others in determinate ways. It is

    only in conscientious forgiveness, as the culmination of Hegels section on Morality, that

    we find the concrete living out within the relation between individuals and the community

    they share of the full dynamics of the three moments of universality, particularity and

    singularity that I have identified above with the process of recognition.

    Conscience is, basically, the moral stance that recognizes, in spite of its inevitably

    partial knowledge of its own situation and of the ultimate significance of its actions, that

    its dutyis to act as it, now, sees to be best. The conscientious agent acts as she knowsthat

    she must, on the basis of her apprehension of what is essential to the situation wherein she

    finds herself. Well aware that her knowledge of the situation is finite, she deems aspects

    of the situation of which she is unaware to be inessential to her duty as she now knows it.

    That is not to say that she considers what she does not know to be utterly irrelevant to hersituation; rather, she recognizes the situation of action to be constituted in and through

    these limitations, such that it is only by living up to the demands of thissituation that

    she has an opening in the first place to what lies outside of or beyond her own immediate

    conviction. What matters essentially for the conscientiousness of action is that the agent

    act solelyon the basis of conviction. If there is hesitation, if it is unclear how she must

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    8/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES126

    act, then her conscientious duty would be to resolve this confusion, to discover how she

    must act and thento act. But of course this deliberatehesitation is also a form of action,

    and is the form of action that in this case is dictated by conscience.22

    Conscience remains well aware that it does not possess that full acquaintance withall the attendant circumstances which is required, and that its pretense of conscientiously

    weighing all the circumstances is vain.23The conscientious agent, nevertheless, holds

    those aspects of the situation wherein she acts, with which she is not immediately ac-

    quainted, to have a moral significance only for others, or for herself in another situation,

    different from the one in which she, now, finds herself compelled to act. As Hegel puts

    it: this acquaintance with, and weighing of, all the circumstances are not altogether

    lacking; but they exist only as a moment, as something which is only for others. Oth-

    ers, differently situated, will experience different demands. For thisconscientious self,

    however, its incompleteknowledge is held . . . to be sufficient and complete, because itis its ownknowledge.24

    To engage in conscientious action is to posit the essentialparticularityof the situation

    wherein one acts, over and against the particular situations of others, and in opposition to

    the abstract universality of the duty that is posited by the stance of morality. The stance

    of conscience can thus be compared profitably to the second moment of the process of

    recognition, as it is interpreted by Burbidge. Morality, we might say, recognizes rightly

    the universalcharacter of duty, the first stage of recognition. To be moral is to act as

    anyone would find themselves compelled to act in a determinate situation; it is to rec-

    ognize oneself as bound by the same obligations that one might ascribe to others, andvice-versa. Against this conception of morality, however, the conscientious agent legiti-

    mately responds that the situation of others is never strictly likethat wherein she finds

    herself. For that reason she insists that herduty is distinctive, and can be revealed to her

    not through the universality of a rational judgment but by her conscience alone. All that

    others can expect of her, and her only obligation to these others, is an assurance that she

    is in fact acting as her conscience dictates. This assurance enables the particular agent

    to invoke the universality demanded by morality, in the sense that she anticipates that

    others will recognize and sanction this assurance, at the same time as it demands of the

    universal that it recognize particularity. As it turns out, however, this insistence upon an

    automaticacceptance of the agent in her particularity fails to recognize the particularity

    of the others. She will in fact only discover the distinctive character of her situation when

    she recognizes the differentiated response her actions solicit in others to establish in the

    first place the significance and validity of her action.

    The language of consciencewhose distinctive content is the assertion of the conscien-

    tious agent in the face of others that she is indeed acting as conscience demandsraises

    the particularity of conscientious action to a kind of universality, that appears to enable

    each conscientious agent to recognize the distinctively dutiful response invoked by theunique situation of others. Hegel writes that in calling itself conscience, [the individual

    agent] calls itself a universal knowing and willing which recognizes and acknowledges

    others, is the same as themfor they are just this pure self-knowing and willingand

    which for that reason is also recognized and acknowledged by them.25 Through the

    mutual recognition of the demand that agents give expression to the conscientiousness

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    9/18

    127HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    of action, a kind of community is formed, in which the differences invoked by the prin-

    ciple of conscience are embraced a priori. Yet what this community in fact embraces is

    merely difference in an abstract sense; it accepts a multiplicity of voices, but only to the

    extent that they are all saying essentially the same thing. It is the community composedof self-proclaimed conscientious agents, and built upon the mutual assurance of their

    conscientiousness, good intentions, the rejoicing over mutual purity, and the refreshing

    of themselves in the glory of knowing and uttering, of cherishing and fostering, such an

    excellent state of affairs.26

    On Hegels account, genuine universality, the true community of conscience, is not what

    is achieved in this mutual admiration society.27The genuinecommunity of conscience

    is forged only out of the situation wherein conscientious agents are unableto rejoice in

    the purity of one another, but find themselves engaged in a conscientiousconflict. It is

    this situation that forces a recognition of unity in and through difference, and a discoveryof the true character of their differences precisely in that unity.

    There is, Hegel points out, another aspect whereby the conscientious agent comes into

    contact with others than merely through the expression of its conscientious character. Con-

    science, Hegel insists, has to be considered as acting.28Even the mere proclamation that

    her action is conscientious must itself be considered as an action, that makes a difference

    to the situation wherein the conscientious agent stands. As a result of this activeside of

    the self-expression of conscience, Hegel writes, the antithesis of individuality to other

    individuals, and to the universal, inevitably comes on the scene.29The self-expression

    of the conscientious agent does not enable her to isolate herself and her situation whollyfrom judgment, for in this very utterance the agent actively invokes the judgment of others

    by explicitly differentiating herself from them, positing her action before them ascom-

    pelling in its uniqueness.30In the very action of proclaiming herself to be conscientious,

    the conscientious agent solicits over and against herself a conscientious judgment, that

    is to determine whether in fact this action lives up to the standard she proclaims. As it

    turns out, however, there is an ambiguity in the utterance that enables it to be taken up in

    a sense quite differently from the one in which it is intended by the conscientious agent.

    This ambiguity in the utterance of conscience is at the heart of the conflict out of which

    the true situation of conscience comes to light.

    The problem with the utterance of conscience, as Hegel puts it, is that the two mo-

    ments constituting this consciousness, the self and the in-itself, are held to be unequal

    in value within it, a disparity in which they are so determined that the certainty of itself

    is the essential being in the face of the in-itself or the universal, which counts only as a

    moment.31To proclaim the conscientiousness of ones actions is to know oneself as a

    singular being whose actions carry out a lived experience of necessity that may not be

    accepted by others, at the same time as it is to insist that these actions be respected by

    these others. What mattersfor the conscientious individual is the fact that her claim toconscientiousness be genuine and that she recognize herself in this claim; to the extent

    that she doesshe expects that others will recognize this as well. The aspect of universal-

    ity, or of universal acceptance, however, is taken for granted. The agent does not, in other

    words, take this judgement on the part of others to matterto the character of her action

    asconscientious. For the judging consciousness, by contrast, it is the judgement alone

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    10/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES128

    that matters when considering the utterance. Even when the judge takes for granted the

    feelingof conscientiousness that the agent proclaims in the utterance, there still remains to

    him the task of determining whether the utterance itself is a conscientious act. He knows

    the utterance to be conscientious only to the extent that he judges it to be such. Yet sincethe utterance of the agent poses this judgment as a foregone conclusion, as something

    that need not in fact take place, the judging consciousness must reject the utterance as a

    failure to live up to the demands of the principle of conscience.

    The acting conscience is thus, as Bernstein puts it, the moral ironist who, having

    recognized that action always embeds itself in a context over which the actor does not

    have exclusive control, attempts to overcome responsibility for the consequences of action

    by appealing to the inevitable finitude of conscience.32The sacred, inviolable character of

    claims to conscience is, from the standpoint of the judging consciousness, taken lightly

    by the acting conscience. From the standpoint of the judge, who knows that he is notina position to judge whether or not the agent in fact operates on an undeniable conviction,

    the assertion that she doesappears as a contingent strategy for acceptance, one that indi-

    cates her not really to be in earnest about being accepted. She is, in that sense, according

    to the judge, a hypocrite.33

    On the other hand, from the perspective of the agent, the judge is insensitive to the par-

    ticularities of the situation in which she acts. His insistence upon respect for the principle

    of conscience, when seen in contrast with the feeling of what is right for her now, seems

    just as much to be arbitrary and one-sided as her approach. In general, the conscientious

    agent will consider the judgment that opposes it to be itself one-sided, and to rest upona particular and idiosyncratic way of taking up the principle of conscience in the same

    way that this judgment proclaims to be true of the action. The judge does violence to the

    expectations of the agent, just as much as he considers the agent to show disregard for

    the expectations of others.

    For this reason, however, it is precisely in her confrontation with the judge that the

    conscientious agent is able to see herself. The judge takes his own position to be just as

    obvious as the acting consciousness takes hers to be. Yet, on the one hand, the condem-

    nation by the judge makes the agent aware that her own way of taking up the principle

    of conscience is not universally acceptable, and, on the other hand, because she does not

    interpret the principle in the same way as does the judge, she knows also that neither is

    the claim of the judge. As a result of the conflict, she has found herself compelled to see

    the truthof the judges condemnation, and now knows that not only her activity but even

    her claimto be acting conscientiously is open to multiple interpretations. Likewise, and

    for that reason, she can no longer anticipate that others will automatically accept her

    claims to be conscientious. She recognizes the possibility of failure to communicate as

    inevitable, and characteristic of her shared situation with others.

    Having recognized this, however, she expects that the mutual acceptance of failurewill produce a reconciliation. While she cannot accept the particular character of the

    response of the judge, she nevertheless respects this response, as a singular expression of

    hisconscience. She anticipates, however, that whereas her expectation of an automatic and

    universal acceptance of her claim to conscience was frustrated, her confession that she is

    like the judge precisely in the one-sidedness of their approach will at least be acknowledged.

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    11/18

    129HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    But, of course, thisanticipation merely repeats her error at a higher level. Her confession

    merely indicates that she has so far continuedto interpret the judges position solely in

    light of her own, and on her own terms. From her perspective, as we saw, what matters

    is to act in accordance with the dictates of her conscience, and she expects that allwillrecognize and sanction such a course of action. Having recognized and acknowledged that

    the judge is also acting as he feels he must in light of his own best understanding of the

    situation they share, she expects that her confession will be automatically acknowledged

    and accepted by the judge, in the same way that she had previously expected her own

    claims to conscience to find an immediately accepting audience.

    Reconciliation, or forgiveness, can only come, on Hegels account, when both agent

    and judge come to acknowledge not merely that conscientious conflict is possibleso that

    the recognition of the validity of ones claims can never be automatically expectedbut

    that the very character of the claim to conscience calls forth such conflict. Each must cometo recognize, in the opposed claims of the other, the experience of necessity that animates

    his or her own claims. Moreover, each must come to recognize the essential bearing of

    opposed claims upon his or her own conscientious character. As Hegel puts it, just as the

    former [agent] has to surrender its one-sided, unacknowledged existence of its particular

    being-for-self, so too must this other set aside its one-sided, unacknowledged judgment.34

    The acting consciousness has recognized the demands of its own conscience to include

    respect for the demands of the other, and therefore no longer takes the recognitionof her

    claims to conscience by this other as inessential to her own identity as a conscientious

    agent. Likewise, the judge must come to recognize that what is essential is not the legiti-macy of his judgmentper se, but thatthe agent herself come to recognizethe legitimacy

    of his judgement, and thereby come to judge herself.

    Forgiveness, for Hegel, is not merely a matter of accepting and tolerating the finitude

    and partiality of the stances adopted by others, any more than confession was a matter

    of automatically giving up such a partial stance. Forgiveness does, however, come to

    recognize the futility of a merely externalcriticism. It involves the acceptance of the

    other in its uniqueness, as a self-determining being who is not in principle confined to the

    particular, finite stance it appears to adopt, but who will nevertheless accept and respond

    only to criticism that it can understand on its own terms. At the same time, the forgiving

    conscience comes to acknowledge that the criticism of others cannot itself be merely

    external, and recognizes the demand to come to comprehend as necessary the experience

    of ones own shared situation with others that called forth precisely this concern. Forgive-

    ness, in Hegels sense, is thus not something that one can decidewhether or not to extend

    to the other; to forgive involves, rather, the compulsion to respond to and acknowledge

    the other as genuinely conscientious, both in the sense that she responds to hers own

    situation as she knows best and in the sense that her own appraisal of a shared situation

    cannot be ignored or taken lightly.Conscientious forgiveness lives up to the demands of recognition insofar as it identifies

    as genuineuniversality only what is forged in the process whereby particular encounters

    with others, from whom the conscientious agent differentiates herself, in fact progres-

    sively reveal to her who she is herself as an individual in the first place. In Hegels words,

    conscientious forgiveness beholds the pure knowledge of itself qua universalessence, in

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    12/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES130

    its opposite, in the pure knowledge of itself quaabsolutely self-contained and exclusive

    individualitya reciprocal recognition which is absoluteSpirit.35According to this re-

    sult there can be no genuine universality or community except that which emerges out of

    particular situations wherein individuals discover themselves and the character of the situ-ation they share with others only in and through their acknowledgement of the compelling

    character of the others affirmation of difference. The community that is achieved between

    them is not a community that exists prior to these opposed individuals, a shared identity

    that they come to realize they had already possessed. It is not even the community that

    comes by way of affirming differences in advance, and that for that reason overlooks the

    formative role of differences in establishing identity. It is, rather, the unity that emerges

    through the dynamic interaction and opposition of distinct individuals, who refuse to be

    assimilated by each other and yet because they recognize this refusal in the other as well,

    discover who and how they are by affirming and identifying with the other in their differ-ences. They discover the uniqueness of their own experienced demands precisely insofar

    as they open themselves up to a discovery and awareness of the demands that animate the

    actions of others. This self-discovery, moreover, is just as much a matter of self-formation

    or self-creation, insofar as it involves the active reformulation of the boundaries between

    each individual and her others, that takes place as each comes to comprehend ever more

    adequately the necessity that motivates the activities of these others to be a necessity ac-

    cording to which she herself bound.

    III. Spirit as an Emerging, Situated WholeIn an essay entitled Hegels Concept of Geist, Robert Williams points out the difficul-

    ties involved in interpreting what Hegel means by Spirit. He contrasts interpretations that

    consider Spirit to be largely a development of Kants transcendental ego with what he

    calls a social-intersubjective interpretation of Geist. When Spirit is interpreted along

    transcendental lines, he argues, it founders on the problem of intersubjectivity. Whether

    social encounters and developments are conceived as the immanent unfolding of the condi-

    tions of human subjectivity or as the self-othering of transcendent divinity, there appears

    to be no room in such an interpretation for an otherness that is not already conditioned by

    a prior unity or identity. According to Williams, it is Hegels concept of recognitionthat

    provides the key to a conception of Spirit that does justice to the ontological transcendence

    of the other. Spirit, he argues, is not a transcendental structure a priori, but rather a

    result, an intersubjective accomplishment.36He acknowledges, however, that it is not clear

    whether and how this interpretation of Spirit as social infinite can be reconciled with an

    idealist conception of Spirit as self-identical unity, a conception that does appear also to

    play an undeniably important role throughout Hegels writings. My concluding remarks

    will aim to show that Williams is right to insist upon the intersubjective and emergent

    character of Hegelian Spirit. At the same time, however, I will seek to demonstrate thatthe intersubjectively emerging Spirit is rightlydescribed just as much as a self-identical

    unity or totality from which differences emerge.37

    I have claimed that the universality of Hegelian Spirit, and its relation to otherness in

    general, is best conceived on the model of the phenomenon of conscientious reconciliation.

    This is not to say that, for Hegel, Spirit is ultimately to be found onlyin conscientious

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    13/18

    131HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    conflict and reconciliation. In that case, if Spirit is universal, it would appear that the logi-

    cal dynamic uncovered in thissituation is one that, strictly speaking, has no other. The

    universality of Spirit would be abstract, and Hegelian philosophy would amount to the

    attempt to applythe terms of the phenomenological dynamic we have discovered in ourstudy of conscience and forgiveness to a diverse range of phenomena. This universality

    would consist, like the abstract formalism of certain strands of idealism that Hegel criticizes

    in his Preface, of the shapeless repetition of one and the same formula, only externally

    applied to diverse materials, thereby obtaining merely a boring show of diversity.38I want

    to suggest, in conclusion, an alternative sense in which his account of conscience and

    forgiveness can be considered paradigmatic for Hegels conception of Spirit in general: the

    universality of the culminating dynamic of Hegels account of Spirit should be conceived

    precisely on the model of the universality that this dynamic itself reveals.

    The result of this culminating moment of conscience is that universality and communityis never pregiven. It is the result of situated selves coming to terms with one another in and

    through their discovery of differences. Community can only be created and established

    through exemplaryencounters, wherein opposed individuals reveal to themselves and

    to each other the nature and implications of their own expectations, precisely as these

    expectations call forth opposition or resistance from others who are differently situated.

    It is not, moreover, just that these opposed selves come better to understandthemselves

    by relating to their other. Rather, they becomethemselves only as each begins to acquire

    through the other a genuine sense for the sigularity of his or her own situation. For that

    reason, however, the process itself does not prioritize either the one or the other, because,as Hegel writes in the account of recognition discussed above, what is to happen can only

    be brought about by both.39What does happen is that, as a result of the dynamic interplay

    of their contrasting perspectives, a situatedunity is forged, that reveals and embraces the

    mutually implicating character of just these particular perspectives.

    The results of this process are always particular, in the sense that the result is always

    the formation of a determinate shape of community in which uniquely situated individu-

    als have to some degree come to terms with their differences. For that reason, what is

    learned in this result cannot be applied as a formal structure to other situations. The

    process itself makes manifest that universality can only emerge out of the particularity of

    contrast, wherein is established in the first place the singularity or uniqueness of opposed

    individual moments. What is indicated in this process, however, can illuminate experience

    generally according to the logic of this result. The result itself teaches us how we are to

    read this result in relation to other forms of experience that are not explicitly included in

    the analysis of conscientious conflict, or even how we are to read this result in relation

    to forms of conscientious conflict other than ones that rest on the specific grounds that I

    have identified above.

    Just as the conscientious agent invokes judgment in proclaiming herself to be con-scientious, so the claim that the situation of conscientious conflict and reconciliation is

    exemplary of Spirit calls upon itself a contrast with other forms of experience, whose dy-

    namics are unique to themselves. The identification of such forms of experience constitutes

    a judgement with respect to the alleged universality of the result we have developed. The

    judgement cannot be ignored, and to respond to it requires a serious investigation of this

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    14/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES132

    new form of experience that will both illuminate our grasp of the distinctive character of

    the experience Hegel has examined in his discussion of conscience, and will establish a

    linkage between these forms in their illuminative contrasts.

    What makes the situation of conscientious conflict exemplary of Spirit is that theuniversality achieved therein emerges precisely from the recognition on the part of both

    agent and judge that their claims are the expression of particular perspectives, that have

    their significance only in the dynamic interplay with the claims of others. The self-knowing

    that emerges in this situation is absolutein the sense that it is absolvedfrom a dependence

    upon an otherness of which it is completely unaware. Conscientious forgiveness knows

    that its comprehension of the situation wherein it acts is finite, and knows that the truth

    of its situation is only that revealed through the process whereby it takes the risk to act

    in spite of limitations, and is attentive to the responses this action invokes upon itself.

    The absoluteness of the Spirit that takes shape within this situation is not opposed to theessentially intersubjective process of recognition, for it is absoluteand unitary only by

    announcing the irreducibility of difference, through the recognition of itself aslimited

    in ways that are so far unanticipated.40As Hegel writes of the word of reconciliation

    wherein forgiveness is expressed, it is the objectively existent Spirit, which beholds the

    pure knowledge of itself qua universalessence, in its opposite, in the pure knowledge of

    itself qua absolutely self-contained and exclusive individualitya reciprocal recognition

    which is absoluteSpirit.41

    Eckerd College

    Notes

    1. Thematized powerfully in the work of Emmanuel Levinas, for example. Similar conclusions

    are reached in the work of a wide range of feminist philosophers and social theorists.

    2. References to HegelsPhenomenology of Spirit

    throughout this essay will be to the num-bered paragraphs in the translation by A. V. Miller, indicated by an M followed by the paragraph

    number. These references will be followed in each case by references to the German edition of the

    Phnomenologie des Geistes, hrsg. v. Hans-Friedrich Wessels und Heinrich Clairmont, indicated

    by W/C and then the page number. The current reference is to M26, W/C 19.

    3. M439, W/C 289; in chap. VI, entitled Spirit.

    4. M178185, W/C 127129.

    5. Language and Recognition, p. 89.

    6. Ibid., p. 90.

    7. Ibid., p. 89.

    8. Conscience and Transgression: The Exemplarity of Tragic Action, p. 79.

    9. Several commentators who interpret Hegel in this way are cited by Daniel Dahlstrom

    in The Dialectic of Conscience and the Necessity of Morality in Hegels Philosophy of Right.

    Bradleys famous essay My Station and Its Duties is an attempt to argue (along Hegelian lines)

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    15/18

    133HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    for a modern-day ethics that puts the Sittlichkeitof finding oneself situated within and obligated

    to ones larger community abovethe claims of conscience that insist on obedience only to what

    conscience recognizes as right. By contrast, Bernstein argues in Conscience and Transgression:

    The Exemplarity of Tragic Action, that the moment of self-conscious self-formation that is

    emphasized in claims to conscience cannot be subordinated communitarian demands. He writes:

    There is an assumption in the literature that Hegel is a communitarian and, more to the point, that

    all obligations are sittlichBradleyan my station and its duties. But if for Hegel we are free and

    self-determining, then not all obligations can be sittlichin character; to believe that would involve

    adding only a level of reflexivity to the sittlichobligations of the kind found in the Greekpolisand

    ignoring the formation of individuality and self-consciousness that is the medium of Spirits com-

    ing to self-consciousness, p. 80. Other commentators who maintain the priority of conscience in

    Hegels account of Spirit include H. S. Harris (inHegels Ladder) and John Russon (in The Self

    and its Body in Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit).

    10. Of course the Philosophy of Righthas a different aim than does the Phenomenology of Spirit,so we should not expect the account of conscience to be identical. Whereas the Phenomenology

    is explicitly an investigation of knowledge, the Philosophy of Rightis concerned primarily with

    freedom, and deals with knowledge only insofar as this has bearing upon the explicit formulation of

    the concept of right. In the case of conscience and morality, however, we should expect the results

    of these two books to converge, insofar as moral agents have the rightto be judged in accordance

    with their knowledge of the situation wherein they act. My aim in the present section will not be to

    make a conclusive case for the compatibility of the Philosophy of Rightand the Phenomenology

    on the issue of conscience (but see Dahlstroms The Dialectic of Conscience and the Necessity of

    Morality in Hegels Philosophy of Right, which could at least serve as the basis for demonstrating

    this compatibility). My aim is rather to indicate that there is no immediately compelling reasonto consider Hegels argument in the Philosophy of Rightthat conscience as it comes up in that

    context cannot serve as the basis for an adequate conception of rightas a refutation of the posi-

    tion of primacy that conscience appears to occupy in the Phenomenology of Spirit. In neither case

    is theformaldoctrine of conscience taken to be sufficient to the claims that are put forward in its

    behalf. Yet in both cases, as I will show, conscience continues to play an essential role even after

    its merely formal character is overcome.

    11. What follows is merely a sketch of the basic stages of Hegels argument. For a good general

    discussion of the argument of the Philosophy of Rightas a whole that has the merit of being concise,

    see Stephen Houlgates Freedom, Truth and History, chap. 3.

    12. The first section of Hegels analysis of Morality is thus entitled Purpose and Responsibility.

    13. The second section of Hegels analysis of Morality is entitled Intention and Welfare.

    14. Hegel writes: My particularity, however, like that of others, is only a right at all in so far

    as I amfree. It cannot therefore assert itself in contradiction to this substantial basis on which it

    rests, Philosophy of Right, 126.

    15. Compare Philosophy of Right, 134.

    16. The third and final section of Hegels analysis of Morality is entitled The Good and

    Conscience.

    17. Philosophy of Right, 136.

    18. Ibid., 137.

    19. The Dialectic of Conscience and the Necessity of Morality in Hegels Philosophy of Spirit,

    p. 185.

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    16/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES134

    20. Hegel himself appears to say as much in a remark appended to 137 in the Philosophy

    of Right: At the level of morality, distinguished as it is in this book from the level of ethics, it is

    only formal conscience that is to be found. True conscience has been mentioned only to indicate

    its distinction from the other and to obviate the possible misunderstanding that here [i.e., in the

    section on morality], where it is only formal conscience that is under consideration, the argument

    is about true conscience. The latter is part of the ethical disposition which comes before us for the

    first time in the following section [i.e., in the section on ethics].

    21. The Self and Its Body in Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit, p. 84. My account in this para-

    graph of the general dynamics of Hegels Spirit chapter, according to which the movement of the

    chapter turns on the progressive recognition that each form of community depends for its existence

    upon a moment of the process of recognition that this form of community works systematically to

    exclude, relies upon interpretations developed in this and other studies of the Phenomenology of

    Spiritby John Russon.

    22. InHegels Transcendental Induction, Peter Simpson describes the position of conscience,as it emerges out of the confusions of the moral world view, in similar terms: the conscientious self

    is the self that knows it must act to carry out its duty, no matter what. The conscientious self is

    the self that places the need to realize its duty above the complications that morality produces. . . .

    [C]onscience posits the necessity of action under the conditions of a limited or situated singularity

    as the universally recognized truth of experiencing, p. 94.

    23. M642, W/C 422.

    24. M642, W/C 422.

    25. M654, W/C 430.

    26. M656, W/C 431.

    27. As it is described by Shklar in Freedom and Independence, p. 191.

    28. M659, W/C 433.

    29. M659, W/C 433.

    30. It is just this character of individual action as compelling in its singularity that is focused upon

    by the genre of Romantic literature that proclaims the ideal of the Beautiful Soul. Hegel explicitly

    references the figure of the Beautiful Soul only at two significant dead ends in the argument of

    his text: the beautiful soul whose sole object is to express itself, by producing an image of itself as

    beautiful in its isolation from the world, and yet fails to discover itself in these very images (M658,W/C 432433); and the judging consciousness whose sole action is to condemn and renounce all

    action (M667668, W/C 438440). But see Jean Hyppolites commentary on this section in Genesis

    and Structure of Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit. Hyppolite traces in Hegels text five separate

    significations of the beautiful soul, all of which have a place in the literature of Romanticism. See

    also Benjamin Saxs article Active Individuality and the Language of Confession: The Figure of

    the Beautiful Soul in theLehrjahre and thePhnomenologie.

    31. M660, W/C 434.

    32. See Hegels Poetics of Action, p. 38; Bernstein borrows and extends the language of irony

    in relation to the position of conscience from Hegels own concluding remarks on conscience in thePhilosophy of Right(in a remark to 140, under heading f).

    33. According to the judge, as Hegel explains, one cannot even consider the agents employ-

    ment of the principle of conscience as a sign of respect for its sanctity, for the fact that [she] uses

    what is an essence as a being-for-anotherimplies rather [her] own contempt for that essence, and

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    17/18

    135HEGELS CONCEPTION OF SPIRIT

    the exposure to everyone of its own lack of any substantial being. For what lets itself be used as an

    external instrument shows itself to be a thing which possesses no importance of its own, M661.

    34. M669, W/C 440.

    35. M670, W/C 441.

    36. Hegels Concept of Geist, pp. 23. It should be noted that character of Spirit as an intersub-

    jective achievement is not lost on those who interpret Hegels concept of Spirit as a development and

    transformation of Kants transcendental ego. Merold Westphal, for example, who Williams identifies

    as one for whom Hegels philosophy is regarded as an instance of transcendental philosophy (p. 2),

    insists that spirit is a social reality, a unity of individual human selves, not a timeless metaphysical

    reality . . . something present, not a supersensible beyond. Yet he also argues that Hegelian Spirit

    must be conceived as absolute, a self-developing socialwhole.

    37. Williams attempts to show that his account can be reconciled with Hegels descriptions

    of Spirit as self-identical totality by pointing out that through the process of recognition a We isformed, to which the other is no longer alien (see Hegels Concept of Geist, pp. 1617). But if the

    We is merelya result, that makes it difficult to see how it can also be the groundof differences.

    38. M15, W/C 12.

    39. M182, W/C 121.

    40. Compare Burbidges account of the absolute in Hegel: The only thing that is genuinely

    absolute, that is without any condition and any restriction, is not an entity identified by a noun, but

    a living process in which each absolute realization of spirit is overturned in favour of another that

    is more truly absolute, in Hegels Absolutes, pp. 3334.

    41. M670, W/C 441.

    Bibliography

    Bernstein, Jay, Confession and Forgiveness: Hegels Poetics of Action, inBeyond Rep-

    resentation: Philosophy and Poetic Imagination, ed. Richard Eldredge (New

    York: Cambridge University Press, 1996).

    , Conscience and Transgression: The Exemplarity of Tragic Action, in

    Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit: A Reappraisal, ed. G. K. Browning (London:Kluwer, 1997), pp. 7997.

    Bradley, F. H., My Station and its Duties, inEthical Studies(Oxford: Clarendon Press,

    1927).

    Burbidge, John, Hegels Absolutes, The Owl of Minerva, vol. 29, no. 1 (Fall 1997),

    pp. 2337.

    , Language and Recognition, inMethod and Speculation in Hegels Phe-

    nomenology of Spirit, ed. Merold Westphal (Humanities Press, 1982).

    Dahlstrom, Daniel, The Dialectic of Conscience and the Necessity of Morality in Hegels

    Philosophy of Spirit, The Owl of Minerva, vol. 24, no. 2 (Spring 1993), pp.

    181189.

  • 7/23/2019 Conscience and Spirit in Id St

    18/18

    IDEALISTIC STUDIES136

    Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, Wilhelm Meister, vol. 1, Apprenticeship, trans. R. O.

    Moon (London: G. T. Foulis & Co., 1947).

    Harris, H. S., Hegels Ladder, vols. 1 and 2 (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.,

    1997).

    Hegel, G. W. F., Elements of the Philosophy of Right, trans. H. B. Nisbet (New York:

    Cambridge University Press, 1991).

    , Phnomenologie des Geistes, hrsg. von Hans-Friedrich Wessels u. Heinrich

    Clairmont (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag GmbH, 1988).

    , Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University

    Press, 1977).

    Houlgate, Stephen, Freedom, Truth and History: An Introduction to Hegels Philosophy

    (New York : Routledge, 1991).

    Hyppolite, Jean, Genesis and Structure of Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Samuel

    Cherniak and John Heckman (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press,

    1974).

    Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich,Allwill, in The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel

    Allwill, trans. by George di Giovanni (Montreal: McGill-Queens University

    Press, 1994).

    Levinas, Immanuel, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority(Pittsburgh : DuquesneUniversity Press, 1969).

    Russon, John, The Self and its Body in Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit (Toronto: Uni-

    versity of Toronto Press, 1997).

    Sax, Benjamin C., Active Individuality and the Language of Confession: The Figure of

    the Beautiful Soul inLehrjahreand the Phenomenologie,Journal of the History

    of Philosophy, vol. 21, no. 4 (1983), pp. 437466.

    Shklar, Judith, Freedom and Independence: A Study of the Political Ideas of Hegels Phe-

    nomenology of Mind(New York : Cambridge University Press, 1976).Simpson, Peter,Hegels Transcendental Induction(Albany: SUNY Press, 1998).

    Westphal, Merold,History and Truth in Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit (Atlantic High-

    lands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1978).

    Williams, Robert R., Hegels Concept of Geist, inHegels Philosophy of Spirit, ed. Peter

    G. Stillman (Albany: SUNY Press, 187).