35
Archived Content Information identified as archived on the Web is for reference, research or record-keeping purposes. It has not been altered or updated after the date of archiving. Web pages that are archived on the Web are not subject to the Government of Canada Web Standards. As per the Communications Policy of the Government of Canada , you can request alternate formats on the "Contact Us " page. Information archivée dans le Web Information archivée dans le Web à des fins de consultation, de recherche ou de tenue de documents. Cette dernière n’a aucunement été modifiée ni mise à jour depuis sa date de mise en archive. Les pages archivées dans le Web ne sont pas assujetties aux normes qui s’appliquent aux sites Web du gouvernement du Canada. Conformément à la Politique de communication du gouvernement du Canada , vous pouvez demander de recevoir cette information dans tout autre format de rechange à la page « Contactez-nous ».

Archived Content - Canadian Forces College alternate formats on the "Contact Us" page. Information archivée dans le Web Information archivée dans le Web à des fins de consultation,

  • Upload
    halien

  • View
    216

  • Download
    3

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Archived Content

Information identified as archived on the Web is for reference, research or record-keeping purposes. It has not been altered or updated after the date of archiving. Web pages that are archived on the Web are not subject to the Government of Canada Web Standards.

As per the Communications Policy of the Government of Canada, you can request alternate formats on the "Contact Us" page.

Information archivée dans le Web

Information archivée dans le Web à des fins de consultation, de recherche ou de tenue de documents. Cette dernière n’a aucunement été modifiée ni mise à jour depuis sa date de mise en archive. Les pages archivées dans le Web ne sont pas assujetties aux normes qui s’appliquent aux sites Web du gouvernement du Canada.

Conformément à la Politique de communication du gouvernement du Canada, vous pouvez demander de recevoir cette information dans tout autre format de rechange à la page « Contactez-nous ».

CANADIAN FORCES COLLEGE /COLLÈGE DES FORCES CANADIENNES

NATIONAL SECURITY STUDIES COURSE 3

16 April 2001

STRATEGIC LEVEL ETHICS: From theory to practice.

By/par

Colonel Daniel St Amour

This paper was written by a student attending the Canadian Forces College in fulfillment of one of the communication skills requirements of the Course of

Studies. The paper is a scholastic document, and thus contains facts and opinions which the author alone

considered appropriate and correct for the subject. It does not necessarily reflect the policy or the opinion of any agency, including the Government of Canada and the Canadian Department of National Defence. This paper may not be released, quoted or copied

except with the express permission of the Canadian Department of National Defence.

La présente étude a été rédigée par un stagiaire du Collège des Forces canadiennes pour satisfaire à l’une des exigences du cours. L’étude est un document qui se rapporte au cours et contient donc des faits et des opinions que seul l’auteur considère appropriés et

convenables au sujet. Elle ne reflète pas nécessairement la politique ou l’opinion d’un

organisme quelconque, y compris le gouvernement du Canada et le ministère de la Défense nationale du Canada. Il est défendu de diffuser, de citer ou de

reproduire cette étude sans la permission expresse du ministère de la Défense nationale.

ABSTRACT

This paper deals with the issue of what can be done to prevent or at least minimize

the risk of international paralysis when the world reckons with such a cataclysmic

humanitarian crisis as Rwanda. Although just war theory and the body of international

law address the question of just intervention (Jus Ad Bellum) and good conduct (Jus In

Bello) of military forces, the theory addresses the just termination (Jus Post Bellum) of

military operation in a very limited fashion. The paper attempts to address an area in the

just war theory that, other than Articles 32 to 41 of the Hague Convention IV, has been

mostly ignored: there is no ethical or legal constructs developed in meaningful way to

address the Jus Post Bellum phase of a humanitarian intervention. The aim of this paper,

therefore, is to find out what conditions must be present when a state decides to engage in

the humanitarian intervention of the future. To accomplish the aim, the paper will look at

two key dimensions of the decision making-process involved in deciding to commit to a

humanitarian intervention, i.e., legal and political dimensions. The paper will also

demonstrate that three pillars must support these two dimensions in order to provide the

right conditions for the UN Member States to engage in a humanitarian crisis. Three

pillars are grounded in the theory of war ethics, i.e., the Jus Ad Bellum (JAD), the Jus In

Bello (JIB) principles, and the Jus Post Bellum (JPB). The genocide in Rwanda illustrates

the importance of having all three pillars in place. The Rwanda experience suggests,

although the JAD and JIB pillars are well grounded, the JPB pillar is not, and without it,

humanitarian intervention will remain problematic. Finally, the paper points out that the

United Nations’ (UN) Charters gives the Security Council a key role in the legitimisation

of a humanitarian intervention. It suggests that the Security Council could be the change

agent and take the lead towards amending the Law of Armed Conflict (LAOC) to reflect

JPB principles.

Page 2 of 34

Introduction

In 1994, while a genocide was brewing in Rwanda, the world remained in a state

of inertia. While the world stood still approximately 800,000 Rwandans were massacred.

Even with repeated calls for help from General Dallaire, the Commander of the United

Nations Assistance Mission In Rwanda (UNAMIR), the UN failed to intervene.1 The US,

a key player at the UN Security Council, maintained that because both Tutsis and Hutus

were getting murdered, it was not genocide. As far as the US was concerned, Rwanda

was in the midst of a civil war. Rwandans were fighting for their right of self-

determination. Thus, the US had no right to intervene in their domestic affairs.2 Why

was there no interest in intervening in Rwanda, and what can we do about it? Could it be

as simple as Samuel Huntington when he argues that it was “morally unjustifiable and

politically indefensible that members of the US armed Forces should be killed to prevent

Somalis from killing one another. 3” The issues must be more complex and raised the

question as to, what could be done to prevent or at least minimize the risk of international

paralysis when the world reckons with such a cataclysmic humanitarian crisis as

Rwanda?

Although just war theory and the body of international law address the question

of just intervention (Jus Ad Bellum) and good conduct (Jus In Bello) of military forces,

the theory addresses the just termination (Jus Post Bellum) of military operations in a

very limited fashion. Herein lies a significant problem: there is no moral or legal

constructs developed in any meaningful way to address the Jus Post Bellum phase of the

1 Gourevitch, P., (1998). [Excerpted from chapter 11]. We wish to inform you that tomorrow we will be killed with our families. Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1. http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/frontline/shows/evil/ 2 ibid.3 Huntington, Samuel, P., (1992, autumn). New contingencies, Old rules. Joint Forces Quaterly. 338.

Page 3 of 34

engagement. Walzer maintains that there” is an obligation to make sure the conditions

that require the intervention in the first place don’t simply resume once you leave”4, but

offers little advice on how military forces meet their obligations towards a military

intervention and not remain engaged indefinitely.

The aim of this paper is to find out what conditions must be present when a state

decides to engage in a humanitarian intervention in the future. To accomplish the aim,

the paper will look at two key dimensions of the foundation in a state decision making-

process, i.e., legal, and political dimensions. The paper will also demonstrate that three

pillars must support these two dimensions in order to provide the right condition for the

UN Member States to engage in a humanitarian crisis. Two pillars are grounded in the

theory of war ethics, i.e., the Jus Ad Bellum (JAD) and the Jus In Bello (JIB) principles.

The Jus Post Bellum (JPB) pillar is submitted as weak or non-existent, and therefore must

be further developed.

This paper is presented in four parts. The first part will examine the legal and

political dimensions focusing on the inter-dependence of each dimension in a human

intervention context. The second part will consist of a detailed analysis of the model three

pillars, (i.e., the JAD, JIB, and JPB) essential to provide the ethical justification required

to initiate, conduct, and terminate a humanitarian intervention. In the third part of the

paper, the genocide in Rwanda will illustrate the importance of having all three pillars in

place. The Rwanda experience suggests that the JAD and JIB pillars are well grounded,

but the JPB pillar is not, and without it humanitarian intervention will remain

4 Walzer, Micheal, (1995, Spring). The politics of rescue. Social research 62. 41.

Page 4 of 34

problematic. Finally, the last section looks at ways and means to guide decision-makers

in making the right decision regarding conflict engagement, conduct and termination.

The model at Figure1 provides a visual perspective of the humanitarian

intervention model. The base displays the dimensions that must be present before a state

is in a good posture to seriously consider engaging in a humanitarian intervention. When

the legal and political dimensions are satisfied, the state political body will be in better

position to debate the issue and, thereafter, decide if it is worthwhile to engage. Once the

decision is made to examine the issue then the political governance must ensure that the

conditions are favourable to achieve a positive outcome. Here lies the key: all three

ethical conditions of just war theory, as enonciated by Immanuel Kant in the 18th

century,5 must be met, i.e., the JAB, JIB, and JPB. Otherwise, its like having a structure

with a solid foundation, legal, and political dimensions, without all its supporting pillars

necessary to support the humanitarian intervention.

J P B

J P

B

J

P

B

J U S I N

B E L L O

J U S

P O S T

B E L L U M

J U S

A D

BE L LU M

Figure 1 Figure 1 Political Dimension

Legal Dimension

Humanitarian Intervention

Page 5 of 34

The theory

The legal dimension

The first dimension is legal in nature. Canada as a member state of the UN and as

a signatory to the charter must work within this international law construct.

The key UN Charter articles most relevant to humanitarian intervention are

Articles 1(3) and 2 (4) in the UN Charter.6 Those establish the states sovereignty sanctity

and human rights. Article 1 (3) sets the stage by promoting and encouraging human

rights and fundamental freedoms for all by stating that one of the main purpose of the UN

is: “To achieve international co-operation in solving international problems of an

economic, social, cultural, or humanitarian character, and in promoting and

encouraging respect for human rights and for fundamental freedoms for all without

distinction as to race, sex, language, or religion.” 7 Note that Article 1(3) does not say

that the role of the UN is to police human rights. Rather, the charter speaks of

encouraging respect of human rights which is in line with the key principle of sovereign

sanctity as expressed in Article 2(4). Article 2 (4) discusses the use of force or threat

thereof against a sovereign state, “All members shall refrain in their international

relations from the threat or use of force against the territorial integrity or political

independence of any state, or in any other manner inconsistent with the purposes of the

United Nations”. 8

The legal precedent is fairly well established with regard to the territorial sanctity

of a sovereign territory. There are very few instances that warrant a humanitarian

5 Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1st ed. (New York: Routledge, 2000), 432. 6 United Nations (UN), (1945, June) UN Charter. New York, NY. http://www.un.org/aboutun/charter/index.html 7 Ibid. 8 Ibid.

Page 6 of 34

intervention without the legitimate governance’s consent. The exceptions form the basis

of the ethical interpretation of the Jus Ad Bellum principles which is the foundation of

LOAC.

The paper published by the Prime Minister’s Office titled “The Canadian Way in

the 21st Century” states how the Canadian Government sees Canada’s basic values within

an international legal context. In the paper, Jean Chretien, Canada’s Prime Minister (PM)

states that “Canada speak to the world through the values that can be traced to our

origins of ‘peace, order, good government’ [and] Canada’s foreign policy is the mirror

image of its domestic policy. 9” Canada does this by “capturing the traditions of

accommodation, peaceful resolution of conflict, the rule of law and democracy. Canada’s

legal framework”10.

The PM believes that by transmitting these values to the world, the probability of

maintaining world stability will improve.11 International law with its body of

conventions, protocols, treaties, declarations, and resolutions is certainly a key element in

the pursuit of “Peace, Order, and Good Government”.

The political dimension

The Political Dimension refers to the political imperatives that influence the

mission to engage in a humanitarian mission. It is also based on philosophical views that

range between pacifism and realism. Pacifists are basically against killing people even in

case of self-defence on the premise that less suffering will incur if we let others do with

9 Government of Canada (GC), (2001) The Canadian way in the 21st century. Ottawa, Ont: Prime Minister Office (PMO), 23. http://pm.gc.ca/default.asp?Language=E&Page=keyinitiatives&Sub=TheCanadianWayinthestCen.html 10 Ibid., 21 11 Ibid., 3.

Page 7 of 34

us as they please. 12 They are against the conduct of all forms of war.13 Realists hold the

view that states ought to be guided solely by a concern for national interest, such as

protection of citizens from external threat. 14 However, threat is a very subjective

element. A nation is threatened to the extent it feels threatened, and by the way the

nation defines its vital interest and, therefore, how secure a nation feels is subjective and

depends on factors that are not necessarily under our control.15

The PM describes Canada’s vision the international environment for the next

century as: “to secure economic prosperity for Canadians while not leaving citizens of

the globalized society behind.” 16 Prosperity will depend on economic growth, national

unity, and the highest quality of life for Canadians. In order to achieve this vision, Jean

Chretien holds that Canada needs “to support policy coherence at the international level,

not only in the economic, but also the social, environmental, health, and cultural

consequences of globalization,” 17 He envisions the realization of policy coherence

through the advantages of our multi-cultural society. Canada’s citizens have roots in

every part of the world and, therefore, are well placed to promote Canada’s core values of

Peace, Order, and Good Government throughout the world. 18

The legal, and political dimensions are grounded in Canada’s perception of

“globalization as a mean to increase wealth, expanded opportunity and improved well-

12 Foltion, N., & Elfstrom, G. (1986). Military ethics: Guidelines for peace and war. Boston, London, and Henley: Ruthledge & Kegan. 7-8. 13 Coates, A. J., (1997). The ethics of war. Manchestor & New York: Manchestor University Press, 77. 14 Finnis, John, & Nardin, Terry (Ed.). The ethics of war & peace: Religious and secular perspectives. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 79. 15 Foltion N., & Elfstrom G. Military ethics: Guidelines for peace and war, 39. 16 GC PMO. The Canadian way in the 21st century, 21. 17 Ibid., 22. 18 Ibid., 21.

Page 8 of 34

being for Canadians and the citizens of other developed countries.” 19 For the citizens of

those states that are less fortunate, living in poverty, for example in less than secure

environments, Canada and beneficiaries of globalization “must help those that are

excluded to benefit.”20

Just War Theory

Analysis of the legal and political dimensions provides the basis to ground the

decision making process. Once the legal and political justifications to intervene have

been met, an ethical government must ensure that the conditions to meet the principles of

just-war theory are in place. The humanitarian intervention success depends very much

on a just intervention, a just conduct, and the ability to plan a just end to the crisis, in

other words the model’s three pillars, i.e., Jus ad bellum, Jus In Bello, and Jus Post

Bellum. Figure 3 shows how the three pillars of just-war theory inter relate.

19 Ibid., 22. 20 Ibid.

Page 9 of 34

Figure 3

Crisis

JPB delay

Jus Ad Bellum conditions

Commitment

Jus In Bello

Just Conduct

Jus Post Bellum Condition

NO

Just War TheoryJPB1

JPB yes

JPB3

JPB4 Just end

JPB5 JPB1

JPB2

JAB1

JAB2

Just intervention

JAB6

JAB3

Jus Ad Bellum (Just Intervention) JAB1: Just cause JAB2: Right intention JAB3: Proper authority, public declaration JAB4: No Precipitate Force JAB5: Probability of success JAB6: Proportionality Jus In Bello (Just Conduct) JIB: Just cause JIB2: Right intention JIB3: Proper authority, public declaration JIB4: Last Resort JIB5: Comparative justice JIB6: Consistency with ideal of perpetual peace Jus Post Bellum (Just End) JPB1: Just cause for termination JPB2: Right intention JPB3: Proper authority, public declaration JPB4: Discrimination JPB5: Proportionality.

JAB5

JAB4

The first pillar, Jus Ad Bellum, is based Grotius work “concerning the law of peace

and war”. Once a state governance believes that it ought to consider acting, JAB

provides the conceptual framework for deciding whether an intervention is justified or

not. An intervention is considered JAB when the intervention is for a just cause and a

Page 10 of 34

right intention; is publicly declared by a legitimate authority only once the avenues of

negotiation have been exhausted; and has reasonable chance of success with minimum

collateral damages.21 Each of these criteria is examined below.

A just cause and a right intent go hand in hand. To demonstrate right intent, a

government must be responding to an aggression to its own territory or in response to

threats to the lives and well being of citizens of other nations. David Luban “argues that

where a nation is in a grave danger from famine, flood, or other disaster even through its

own mismanagement, wherever large number of lives are at stake other nations are

obligated to help.22”23 The obligation needs to be weighted against national sovereignty

as stated in article 2(4) and article 1(3) of the UN Charter. Article 2(4) insists on

territorial integrity and political independence. If the intent is to help a country that has

been the victim of an aggression, intervention is justified unless its purpose is strictly for

self-interest, and all venues of negotiations have not been tried.24 Finally, war is

permissible if the intention is to set right perceived present or past wrong. 25

To satisfy JAB a state must also have the proper authority. The intervention

must be publicly declared, and domestic rights must be protected. Although, article

2 (7) of the UN Charter re-enforced by resolution 36/103 passed at the 91st plenary

meeting held by the General Assembly prohibits the Security Council ‘s intervention in

the domestic affairs of a state by re-affirming that: “No state or group of states has the

right to intervene or interfere in any form or for any reason whatsoever in the internal

21 Orend Brian (2000), War and international justice: A Kantian Perpective.Waterloo, Ontario, Canada: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 205-211. 22 Luban, D, ‘Just war and human rights,’ Philosophy in public Affairs, Vol. 9, 1980, 150-81. 23 Foltion N., & Elfstrom G., 117. 24 Nuttal, J., & Rosenthal J. H. (Ed). (1993). Ethics and international affairs: Polity. (2nd ed.). Washington D.C.: George Town University Press, 162. 25 Ibid.

Page 11 of 34

and external affairs of any other state”26 Part III of the declaration presents a few

exceptions to the non-use of force. The first exception is found in Paragraph 2 III (c) and

expresses the right to self-defence by affirming that: “The right and duty of states fully to

support the right to self-determination, freedom and independence of peoples under

colonial domination, foreign occupation or racist regimes, as well as the right of these

peoples to wage both political and armed struggle to that end in accordance with the

purposes and principles of the Charter of the United Nations.”27 The declaration, as

indicated in Paragraph 4, also supports an intervention in response to threats to the lives

and well being of citizens of other nations and might legally justify the use force in a

sovereign territory. The declaration states that: “Nothing in this declaration shall

prejudice in any manner the right to self-determination, foreign occupation or racist

regimes, and the right to seek and receive support in accordance with the purposes and

principles of the Charter of the United Nations”. 28 Finally, Article 1 of the Convention

on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide which entered into force on

12 January 1951 recognises the obligation to act to prevent and punish in case of

“genocide (as defined in Article 2), whether committed in time of peace or in time of war,

is a crime under international law which they undertake to prevent and to punish”.29

On the principle of no precipitate force, Jeff McNamara says that one may pre-empt

a likely aggression if and only if a country can prove that their adversary was actually

26 UN General assembly. “36/103. Declaration on the Inadmissibility of Intervention and Interference in the Internal Affairs of States.” Resolution 36-103: 91st plenary meeting. 1981, December 9 http://www.un.org/documents/ga/res/36/a36r103.htm 27 Ibid. 28 Ibid. 29 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide. Approved and proposed for signature and ratification or accession by General Assembly resolution 260 A (III) of 9 December 1948 entry into force 12 January 1951, in accordance with article XIII. http://www.unhchr.ch/html/menu3/b/p_genoci.htm

Page 12 of 34

guilty of an offence that threatens its territorial integrity.30 A pre-emptive strike is not

permitted unless it is clear that there is compelling evidence that the threat will actually

occur, or that the obvious threat can move all too quickly toward an actual assault.31

Finally, to meet the conditions of a just intervention there must a reasonable

probability of success. There should also be proportionality considering the social and

economic wellbeing of all concerned. The probable good in pursuit of the just cause

must outweigh the probable evil.32 The calculation of proportionality must be made

compared to the probability of success. 33 In an international context, the potential

escalation, and ramifications of a possible war have at times been crucial to determine

how much coercion a nation and/or the international community are prepared to use to

resolve a dispute. For example, the Russian’s invasion of Hungary in 1956 was an

obvious infringement of the principle of non-aggression and a clear violation of

Hungarian Sovereignty and right to self-determination. Hungary’s request for help from

international community in 1956 was very similar to Kuwait’s except for a distinct

difference. An armed conflict with Russia had the potential of causing a nuclear

holocaust. 34 The human suffering that would result from helping Hungary in 1956 would

have been worse than not intervening. Thus, each case must be decided in terms of the

long-range effect of going to war. 35

The second pillar, Jus In Bello, refers to the criteria that justify moral conduct in

operations. Jus in bello principles have deontological roots. The legal framework that has

30 McMahan, & Nardin Terry (Ed.). (1996). The ethics of war & peace: Realism, Morality, and war. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 85. 31 Foltion N., & Elfstrom G., Military Ethics: Guidelines for Peace and War. 35-36. 32 O’Brien, W.V. (1981). The conduct of a just an limited war. New York: Praeger, 27-28. 33 Ibid.34 Coates A. J., The ethics of war.179. 35 Ibid., 115.

Page 13 of 34

originated from the JIB principles is found in the four Geneva conventions and two

protocols on law and armed-conflict.36 The JIB ethical dimension provides guidance

when one has to make a situation arises and is not covered by the legal framework. The

responsibility to ensure that the norm are adhere to from both JIB and LOAC, is

bestowed to military commanders, officers, and soldiers who formulate and execute the

plan. It still behooves to the heads of state to ensure that the justified end is pursued by

justified means. Hence the role of the rules of engagement. Theses rules provides

consistency in the application of force and prevent escalation through proportional use of

force. To be in abeyance the soldiers may target only “those engage in harm”37

(discrimination), the soldiers may use only the minimum force required to achieve the

aim (micro-proportionality), and cannot use means that are wrong ( No Means Mala in

Se)38. The law in armed conflict oversight is the role of the International Court of Justice

(ICJ) is the principal judicial organ of the United Nations and thus has the oversight role

of the law of armed conflict.39 Lets suppose also that according to JAB and JIB principles

are met and, therefore, the conditions are such that we have just cause, and the right

instruments to enable the state to conduct a just war; the state is left wondering what will

be consider a right ending with regard to its own citizenry, the population remaining

behind, and international community.

The third pillars is addressed in Kant JPB ethical construct when coined the term Jus

Post Bellum by discussing basic principles. Little attention were given to theses

36 One World, Frequently Asked Questions about IHL. What treaties make up international law? http://nt.oneworld.org/cfdocs/icrc/anyfs.cfm?pagepath=pages/page1232.htm 37 Orend, B. War and International Justice: A Kantian perspective. 205-211. 38 Orend, B. Stanford Encyclopedia of Phylosophy. 2000, 4. http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/standford/archives/spr2000/entries/war 39 The International Court of Justice. General Information: The Court at a Glance. 2001, March 26. http://www.icj-cij.org/icjwww/igeneralinformation/icjgnnot.html

Page 14 of 34

principles until recently when Brian Orend began exploring this uncharted territory by

proposing a Kantian’s perspective on how a just war should end.40 The five rules of JPB

as follows:

x� Just Cause for termination; x� Right intention; x� Public declaration, legitimate authority, and domestic rights-protection; x� Discrimination; and x� Proportionality.

To have just cause to end a war or in a lesser degree to end a nation’s commitment to

a humanitarian intervention, Brian Orend states that “a just war should end when there is

a reasonable vindication of those rights whose violation grounded the resort to war in the

first place.”41 The government’s intent to end the conflict must aim towards an equal

application of the law towards the investigation and prosecution of war criminals on both

sides of the armed conflict.42 Furthermore, to have a just end to a war, as stated in Kant’s

theory, “the term of the peace must be publicly proclaimed by a legitimate authority,” 43

and is reinforced by the article 32 to 41 of The Hague Convention IV. The convention is

very limited in its application of JPB. It only speaks of the role of the white flag in

providing the rights of the flag-bearer and the rights of the one receiving the flag of truce

and also regulates the capitutilation process.44 However, Walzer warns that at the end of

the conflict there is a tendency for the victor to re-establish the previous ground rules that

were present before the intervention began. He also insists that the last thing one should

do is to re-establish the status quo since returning to the pre-war status quo might become

40 Orend, B. (2000). War and International Justice: A Kantian perspective, 217-256. 41Ibid.42 Ibid, 232. 43 Ibid, 228. 44 Ibid, 218.

Page 15 of 34

the breathing ground for the conditions that caused the war in the first place. Another

duty from the just government is to avoid discrimination at all cost, thereby keeping to a

minimum the potential resentment that the populations may have against each other and,

in the process, preventing further conflict. Brian Orend warns, in his work on war and

international justice, that “Undue and unfair hardship is not to be brought upon the

civilian population in particular: punitive measures are to be focused upon those elites

most responsible for the aggression.” 45 Finally, on the principle of proportionality no

crusade is allowed. The aggressors still have human rights. This argument does not

prevent a need to demilitarize to the point that they have sufficient forces to maintain law

in order internally and to protect their border. 46

Without knowing, at least from a risk-management point of view, the desire goal and

end-state, the head of states cannot fulfil their social contracts with their citizenry and

members of their armed forces. A possible solution proposed in this paper is to enshrine

JPB principle in the UN Charter or other UN policy instruments. It would go a long way

towards reassuring states governance that all the conditions are favorable to a successful

intervention and would minimize the position governments find themselves in engaging

in a humanitarian intervention.

45 Ibid. 46 Ibid.

Page 16 of 34

The practice

A reflection on what happen in Rwanda in the dark days of the 1994 genocide

can shed some light on why UN member states failed to recognize that a humanitarian

intervention was the right thing to do.

Jus Ad Bellum: Let’s review the principle of just intervention and ending an

intra-state conflict in the context of Rwanda genocide in 1994.

On just cause: Even though Rwanda did not commit interstate armed aggression, its

massive human rights violation were a just cause for nations to commit military forces to

the conflict. Grotius, Oppenheim and Walzer all agree that a state forfeits its claim to

sovereignty when leaders violate their subjects human rights’ in such a way as to make

the concept of self-determination irrelevant. On 6 April 1994, the plane of Rwanda’s

President was shot down near Kigali airport, and the same night Thousands were killed

on the first day while the UN forces standed still while Tutsis and Hutus moderate were

being killed. 47 On 21 April 1994, the Prime Minister was killed and the 10 Belgians

guarding the Prime Minister’s residence were disarmed, tortured, and hacked to death.48 .

Up to 800,000 Rwandans were killed that spring. As Luban pointed out when a large

number of lives are at stake, the other nations are obligated to help.49 In the spring of

1994, because of the extremely serious human rights violation, the Rwandans right to

self-determination were non-existent, therefore, the sovereignty status as under Article

2(4) of the UN Charter was not applicable. Hence, there was just cause for UN mandated

humanitarian intervention.

47 Ibid.48 Ibid.49 Luban, D. ‘Just war and human rights,’ Philosophy in public Affairs.

Page 17 of 34

On right intent: On 30 April 1994 the UN Security Council, while thousands of

Rwandans were being systematically killed, the Security council was debating whether

the crisis was a genocide. 50 After a long debate within the security council on the

Rwandan crisis, there was a resolution condemning the killing. The word genocide was

not included in the resolution.51 Finally, on 17 May 1994, the Security Council supported

the need to send a force of approximately 7000 armed personnel to defend Rwandan on

the basis that an act of genocide may have been committed. 52 This force was not

deployed due to the arguments over who would pay the bill and provide the equipment.53

Even though there was just cause to get involved, there was clearly no intent to change

the mandate from observer force to peace enforcement. The world had simply no

intention to intervene in Rwanda’s affair!

Canada is signatory of the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the

Crime of Genocide of which Article 1 clearly states that crimes against humanity, hence,

genocide cannot and will not be tolerated by the signatories of the agreement. 54 Canada,

therefore, had a moral and legal duty to act with its allies to prevent or stop the

cataclysm. Although, the crisis did not affect Canada’s vital interest, the PM’s policy on

Peace, Order, and Good Government mentioned earlier (p.7) suggests that Canada must

participate in assisting troubled states in reinstating a justice system and police force able

maintain peace and order on its territory. Good government in Canadian terms entails a

responsibility on the part of government to provide citizens with the basics requirement

50 Loeterman, Ben & Robinson, Mike, dir. Triumph of evil. PBS Video, 1999. 51 Keane, Fergal & Destexhe, Alain. Rwanda: A historical chronology.52 Ibid. 53 Ibid.54Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide. Approved and proposed for signature and ratification or accession by General Assembly resolution 260 A (III) of 9 December 1948

Page 18 of 34

needed to rear a country. These include health, education, economic development, social

justice, and the ability to collect taxes to pay for those services. Only Chechoslovakia,

New Zealand, and Spain ambassadors pressured the UN for the return of troops to the

crisis area.55 Canada remained quiet on the issue.

On proper authority, public declaration and domestic rights protection: The

government had consent from Rwanda to intervene. Not only were the Rwandans

consenting, both Hutus (before the killing started to escalate) and Tutsis (once the killing

started to escalate) called for foreign assistance.56 Furthermore, Article 3 of the UN

Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide provided the

international authority with the necessary legal framework to intervene. The convention

stipulates that genocide is an act of committing with intent to destroy, in whole or in part,

nationals, ethnical, racial or religious group such as:

x� Killing members of the group; x� Causing serious bodily or mental harm to members of the group x� Deliberate inflicting on the group conditions of life calculated to bring about its

physical destruction in whole or in part; x� Imposing measures intended to prevent births within the group; and x� Forcibly transferring children of the group to another group.

In fact, Canada and the other131 nations57 which are party to the genocide

Convention were non-compliant with Article 8 which calls for action on infraction

entry into force 12 January 1951, in accordance with article XIII. http://www.unhchr.ch/html/menu3/b/p_genoci.htm 55 Gourevitch, P., (1998). [Excerpted from chapter 11]. We wish to inform you that tomorrow we will be killed with our families. 56 Orend, B. War and International Justice: Akantian Perspective, 208. 57 Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights. (1997). Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide: Approved and proposed for signature and ratification or accession by General Assembly resolution 260 A (III) of 9 December 1948 entry into force 12 January 1951, in accordance with article XIII. Geneva, Switzerland. http://www.preventgenocide.org/law/convention/reservations/

Page 19 of 34

committed at article 3 above. Hence, there was not only just cause to intervene on 6

April 1994, it was a duty to do so.

On no precipitate force: The UN or any countries that wanted to get involved would

need to wait until compelling evidence was available that things were spinning out of

control in Rwanda. There was plenty of credible, verifiable information from

international organizations, non-governmental organizations, and the media. All the

evidences pointed to the fact that if a viable political solution were not soon sought, there

would be mass slaughters in Rwanda.58

On probability of success: The UNAMIR force to Rwanda was poorly equipped and

supported. A well conceived plan with more better equipment would have stopped the

killings (as expressed on many occasion prior the actual genocide). 59 The tragedy of the

assassination of the 10 Belgium soldiers and the subsequent withdrawal of their forces

could have been avoided if General Dallaire had been provided with sufficient armed

forces and Rules of Engagement (ROE) to maintain a proper mandate to ensure Peace,

Order, and Good Governance.60

On proportionality: The Rwanda civil war was a very complex problem, and the

resources of continued deployment that were required would have been very costly.

However, if one puts it in perspective, it would not have cost anything close to the Gulf

War overall cost of $26061 billion.

58 Loeterman, Ben & Robinson, Mike, dir. Triumph of evil. 59 Orend, B. (2000). War and International Justice: A Kantian perspective. 205-211. 60 Loeterman, Ben & Robinson, Mike, dir. Triumph of evil. 61 Ralston Saul, J., (1994). Voltaire’s Bastard: The dictatorship of reason in the west. Toronto: Penguin Books.

Page 20 of 34

Jus In Bello

On proportionality: Presuming, at least in hindsight, that there was a genocide

being perpreted in Rwanda in 1993/94, a humanitarian intervention would have met the

JAB conditions. The expected benefits of the intervention would have been to protect

Tutsis and moderate Hutus from being massacred by members of the Hutus power. The

Hutu regime had proved themselves to be outlawed, devoid of rigths to non-interference,

because of its systamic human rights violations, against their own citizens. As long as

they would have abided to the JIB principles, UNAMIR troops were within the bounds of

international law to intervene, with lethal force if necessary. Since the majority of the

killings in Rwanda were perpretated with small arms, mostly machetes, the risk for the

UN troops of not abiding to the JIB principles of proportionality would have been slight.

On discrimination: Even though, on 23 November 1993, General Dallaire had

requested from the UN, approval for the draft rules of engagement (ROE) that he had

sent, the same day, General Dallaire received no formal response. The confusion

surrounding the ROE may have well been a contributing factors to the ten Belgians

soldiers surrending without a fight and, hence, their subsequent atrocious death.62 Due to

the UN’s inability to endorse a clear set of ROE and a suitable mandate, the UN not only

put Rwandans at risk but also its own troops.

Jus Post Bellum

On just cause: On 4 August 1993, the Arusha Peace Agreement was signed by

the various factions in Rwanda.63 It allowed the return of Hutus refugees to Rwanda from

62 Des Forges, Allison, (March, 1999) Leave None To Tell The Story. New York: Human Rights Watch Publications,133. 63 Keane, Fergal & Destexhe, Alain. Rwanda: A historical chronology

Page 21 of 34

Uganda and the establishment of a share Hutus/Tutsis coalition government.64 To assist

the government of Rwanda, the UNAMIR was established from in the fall of 1993. At its

peak UNAMIR was up to 2548. 65 At that critical juncture, it was clear that there was no

legitimate government in power, and that the Rwandans human rights were seriously

violated. The UNAMIR mandate should have changed from an assistance mission to a

military intervention. The mandate was not changed. As Walzer points out when “a state

which the governments turns against its own people and engages in “terrible human

rights violations such as massacre. Such state violates the thin and universal moral code

and becomes illegitimate.”66 Thus the UN Security Council had just cause to act and

chose not to. The council decided to reduce it’s commitment to assist Rwanda instead.

On right intent: The Hutu Power’s were expecting UN troops to withdraw once

the UNAMIR forces were at risk. 67 The Hutu Power’s prediction was pretty accurate.

The force was reduced to 250 within 14 days of the assassination of Rwanda Prime

Minister and gruesome killing of the ten Belgian soldiers sent to protect her.68 The UN’s

withdrawal of the majority of its troops was questionable at best. There was no intention

to prevent genocide. And if the UN didn’t have enough evidence to call it genocide, they

had information to the effect that one was certainly brewing.

On public declaration: The Arusha Peace Accord was never successfully

Council refusal to call the mass killing genocide as shown on 30 April 1994, when, after

discussing the Rwanda situation, it could not get the necessary support to call the crisis a

64 Ibid. 65 Ibid. 66 Walzer, M , On just cause: Resorting to force. Canadian Journal of Political Science, 3, XXXIII: 2000 (9 April 2001), 5 , Walzer, M , On just cause: Resorting to force. Canadian Journal of Political Science, 3, XXXIII: 2000 (9 April 2001), 5 , http://www.wlu.ca/~wwwpress/jrls/cjps/issues/33.3/orend.html 67 Keane, Fergal & Destexhe, Alain. Rwanda: A historical chronology68 Ibid.

Page 22 of 34

genocide.69 The reluctance to call the Rwanda crisis a genocide had the effect to prevent

a nasty humanitarian intervention, since there was no crime against humanity taking

place; thus, there was no humanitarien intervention needed.

On public discrimination: By February 1997, 21 suspects are indicted for crime

against humanity.70 The Hutus male population are arrested in mass and their most basic

human rights are taken away. To this date, very few of the Hutus incarcerated have been

prosecuted. 71 Undue and unfair hardship has been brought to the Hutus population.

On proportionality: The Rwanda tragedy in 1993/94 was not only messy, it has

been volatile ever since. For the Rwandans, it is very important that the conditions for

peace were in place so they do not return to a state of War. To that effect, the Western

governments had pledged $600 Million in to aid to Rwanda on the condition that the

political base of the new government be expended.72 Why? After all, the genocide

occurred not long after the Arusha Peace Accord was signed which was based on

allowing the return of refugees and the coalition government of Hutu-Tutsi. The

conditions to the financial aid had the effect to increase, in mid-May 1995, the tensions

between the UN and Rwanda. The international aid was very limited to rebuild a country

that had been so devastated. 73 To tie that financial aid to condition similar to the Arusha

Peace Accord which was a total failure to begin with, was short sighted. One would not

argue that it would be just to insist on conditions that financial aid should be directed

toward promoting Peace, Order, and Good Government; values proudly espoused by

Canada.

69 Ibid.70 Ibid.71 Ibid.72 Ibid.

Page 23 of 34

How did Canada do in its obligations to aid Rwanda. According to Canadian

Council for International Co-operation (CCIC) funds allocated to provide African aid

were cut during the early to mid 90s by 58%.74 All funding allocations to the

development of education were reduced dramatically in the fiscal year 1993/94 budget. 75

In fact, Rwanda was a low priority in Canada’s foreign policy and international relation

and never saw fit to established a foreign embassy in the region.76 If all developed

countries were to take this approach, it would be impossible to create the right conditions

to enable the UN to end the intervention.

From the experience gained in Rwanda, we can see that there was a significant

reluctance from UN member states to intervene in a conflit that had no end in sight. Due

to this uncertainty there was a serious lack of will from the international community to

intervene.

73 Ibid.74 Canadian Council for International Co-operation. (April 95), Implementing the Cuts: The Implications of Budget Cuts to NGO/NGI Programs in the Partnership Branch of CIDA. 75 Ibid. 76 Delvoie, Louis, Canada and internal security operations: The search for policy rationales. Canadian Military Journal (summer 2000), 9.

Page 24 of 34

The Rwanda humanitarian crisis provides the international community with the

essence of the problem. Without a strong Jus Post Bellum pillar, the Jus Ad Bellum and

Jus In Bello pillars are not sufficients to support the commitment of UN member states

towards humanitarian intervention as depicted below at Figure 3. Thus, without a strong

Jus Post Bellum construct, the lack of will to commit military forces in intra-state conflict

will remain.

J

U S

A

B E L L U M J U S

A D

B E L

J U S AD BE L L U M

Humanitarian Intervention

J US I N

BE L L O

Political Dimension

Legal Dimension

Figure 3.

A solution

How can the UN pursue the challenge? One needs only to look at specific articles in

Chapter VII and Chapter VIII of the UN Charter to see the key role the Security Council

Page 25 of 34

plays in the legitimisation of a humanitarian intervention. Article 39 clearly states that an

intervention in an armed conflict is possible when sanctioned by the Security Council

under Chapter VII of the Charter. As expressed in Articles 41 and 42 the Security

Council “shall determine the existence of any threat to the peace, breach of the peace, or

act of aggression, and then makes recommendations or decides on measures, if necessary

provides the Security Council with alternate means to military intervention to main tain

international peace and security by affirming that: “ The Security Council may decide

what measures not involving the use of armed force are to be employed to give effect to

its decisions, and may call upon the Members of the United nations to apply such

measures. These may include complete or partial interruption of economic relations and

of rail, sea, air, postal, telegraphic, radio, and other means of communication, and the

severance of diplomatic relations.” 77 Nevertheless, the Charter is very explicit in the use

of military options as last resort as illustrated by Article 42: “Should the Security

Council consider that measures provided for in Article 41 would be inadequate or have

proved to be inadequate, it may take such action by air, sea, or land forces as may be

necessary to maintain or restore international peace and security. Such action may

include demonstrations, blockade, and other operations by air, sea, or land forces of

Members of the United Nations.” 78

On the subject of the right of individual and collective self-defence, it is expressed in

Chapter VII of the charter article 51 and includes the protection of nationals’ abroad. 79

The right to self-defence is only authorised by the Security Council until it can put in

place the measures necessary to maintain international peace and security. To that effect

77 Ibid. 78 Ibid.

Page 26 of 34

article 51 states that: “Nothing in the present Charter shall impair the inherent right of

individual or collective self-defence if an armed attack occurs against a Member of the

United Nations, until the Security Council has taken measures necessary to maintain

international peace and security.” 80 Finally, article 53 highlights the pre-eminence of

the Security Council and reinforces the fact that the right of self-defence applies only to

states, and claiming it for other entities (e.g. Kosovo) has no foundation in international

law by iterating that: “The Security Council shall, where appropriate, utilise such

regional arrangements or agencies for enforcement action under its authority. But no

enforcement action shall be taken under regional arrangements or by regional agencies

without the authorisation of the Security Council etc.” 81

Considering some of the roles bestowed to the Security Council in the UN Charter, it

could be advantageous for the council to encourage reputable academic institutions to

pursue Kant’s work on JPB. Briand Orand in his newly published work, War and

International Justice: A Kantian perspective82, provides the line of departure. Much

debate on JPB needs to occur. However, before Kant’s views can be entrenched in Just

War Theory and into international law.

Who could be better suited than the Security Council to become the change agent and

lead the world in developing the JPB pillar. The international community cannot morally

fail again when a crime against humanity is committeed. The international community

needs strong leadership form the Security Council so that, as in the case of Rwanda,

although the UN member states had the obligation to intervenve, they did not. The

79 Ibid. 80 id. Ib 81 Ibid. 82 Orend, B. War and International Justice: A Kantian perspective. 205-211.

Page 27 of 34

mandate was never changed from being an observation to an intervention mission. The

inadequate mandated resulted in confusion on the ROE. The outcome was the tragic

deaths of hundreds of thousands of human beings. One the root cause to this inaction is

the dillemma of committing troops to a mission that has no end in sight and that has

nothing to do with one state national interest. The UN must lead and create the

conditions to avoid becoming helpless, once again, when serious violations of human

rights and/or crime against humanity are being committed. Only when just war theory

gives due consideration to the JPB principles, and when the international law is

supported by a comprehensive legal construct, the UN will be able to rally the politician

to engage in a future humanitarian intervention. Right now the Just Post Bellum pillar is

almost non-existant.

CONCLUSION

Rwanda’s genocide and the subsequent inaction of the international community

illustrate the uneasiness of the UN Member states to engage their military forces in an

armed-conflict with no end state. It will always be very difficult to generate willingness

to jumanitarian interventionss. Presently there is no question that troops committed in

humanitarian intervention have a high probability of being committed for the long-term.

The problem is made more difficult because of the many different point of views

among the 132 UN members states that are signatory on the Charter, mainly because of

their different legal, and political dimensions. Nevertheless, they all have this in

common; they all signed on the Human Rights declaration and the Convention on the

Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, Geneva conventions and

protocols, declarations and resolutions that cover a wide range of issues including the

Page 28 of 34

JAB and JIB pillars. Furthermore, no state can afford to remain engaged in a

humanitarian intervention indefinitely. States need to know how and when a mission will

end before they can commit to an intervention. Thus, the importance of JPB. The UN

Security Council could be the change agent to provide the impetus to include JPB

principles in international law.

Unless, the UN takes up the challenge and addresses the JPB aspects of just war

theory and the legal construct to support humanitarian intervention, the international

community willl remain helpless in its ability to engage and succeed in its humanitarian

intervention. Therefore, the UN needs to show resolve in establishing the JPB otherwise

enthusiasm for humanitarian intervention will continue to wane.

Page 29 of 34

Bibliography

Andrikson, D.C., & Rosenthal J. H. (Ed). (1993). Ethics and international affairs: The

ethics of collective security. (2nd ed.). Washington D.C.: George Town University

Press.

Brunk,G. & al, (1996). Understanding attitudes about war: Modelling moral judgement.

Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

Canadian Council for International Co-operation. (April 95), Implementing the Cuts: The

Implications of Budget Cuts to NGO/NGI Programs in the Partnership Branch of

CIDA.

Christopher, Paul, (1999). The ethics of war and peace: an introduction to legal and

moral issues. Toronto; Prentice Hall.

Coates, A. J., (1997). The ethics of war. Manchestor & New York: Manchestor

University Press.

Cohen & al (Eds.), (1974). War and moral responsibility. Princeton: Princeton

University Press.

Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1st ed. (New York: Routledge, 2000).

Delvoie, Louis, Canada and internal security operations: The search for policy rationales.

Canadian Military Journal (summer 2000).

Des Forges, Allison, (March, 1999) Leave None To Tell The Story. New York: Human

Rights Watch Publication.

Finnis, John, & Nardin, Terry (Ed.). (1996). The ethics of war & peace: Religious and

secular perspectives. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Page 30 of 34

Foltion, N., & Elfstrom, G. (1986). Military Ethics: Guidelines for Peace and war.

Boston, London, and Henley: Ruthledge & Kegan

Government of Canada (GC), (2001) The Canadian way in the 21st century. Ottawa,

Ont: Prime Minister Office (PMO).

http://pm.gc.ca/default.asp?Language=E&Page=keyinitiatives&Sub=TheCanadia

nWayinthestCen.html

Gourevitch, P., (1998). [Excerpted from chapter 11]. We wish to inform you that

tomorrow we will be killed with our families. Farrar, Straus & Giroux, Inc.

Available http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/frontline/shows/evil/

Graham, G., (1997). Ethics and International Relations. Cambridge: Blackwell

Publishers Inc.

Hare, R.M., (1981). Moral thinking . Oxford: Clarendon Press, 105.

Hasmi , H. Sohail, & Nardin, Terry (Ed.). (1996). Interpreting Islamic Ethics. Princeton:

Princeton University Press.

Huntington, Samuel, P., (1992, autumn). New contingencies, Old rules. Joint Forces

Quarterly.

Isaak, Jeffrey, (1998). Democracy in Dark Times. New York: Cornell University Press.

Kant, Immanuel, (1983). Perpetual peace and other essays. Translated by T. Humphrey.

IN: Hackett.

Keane, Fergal & Destexhe, Alain. Rwanda: A historical chronology. Keegan, J., (1993). An history of warfare. London: Hutchinson.

Lackey, D., (1989). The ethics of war and peace. New Jersey: Prentice Hall.

Page 31 of 34

Lacroix, W.L., (1988) War and international ethics: Tradition and today. New York:

University Press of America.

La Hague: The International Court of Justice. General Information: The Court at a

Glance. 2001, March 26.

http://www.icj-ij.org/icjwww/igeneralinformation/icjgnnot.html

Leslie, J., (1996). The end of the world: The science and ethics of human extinction.

New York: Routledge.

Locke, Hume, Rousseau, (1962). Essays on Social Contract. New York; Oxford

University Press.

Loeterman, Ben & Robinson, Mike, dir. Triumph of evil. PBS Video, 1999.

McMahan, & Nardin Terry (Ed.). (1996). The ethics of war & peace: Realism, Morality,

and war. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Nuttal, J., & Rosenthal, J. H. (Ed), (1993). Ethics and international affairs: Polity. (2nd

ed.). Washington D.C.: George Town University Press.

O’Brien, W.V. (1981). The conduct of a just an limited war. New York: Praeger.

One World, Frequently Asked Questions about IHL. What treaties make up international

law? http://nt.oneworld.org/cfdocs/icrc/anyfs.cfm?pagepath=pages/page1232.htm

Orend, Brian, (2000). War and international justice: A Kantian Perpective.Waterloo,

Ontario, Canada: Wilfrid Laurier University Press.

Pearsall, Judy, (Ed.). Oxford, Concise English Dictionary. (10th ed.) (1999). New York,

NY: Oxford University Press.

Page 32 of 34

Ralston Saul, J., (1995). The doubter’s companion: a dictionary of aggressive common

sense. Toronto: Penguin Books.

Ralston Saul, J., (1994). Voltaire’s Bastard: The dictatorship of reason in the west.

Toronto: Penguin Books.

Richard, B., (1979), A theory of the good and right. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Stanford Encyclopedia of Phylosophy. 2000.

Thomas, L., (1995). Routledge philosophy guide book: Locke on government. New

York: Routledge, 13.

United Nations, Charter. http://www.un.org/aboutun/charter/index.html

http://www.unhchr.ch/html/menu3/b/p_genoci.htm

United Nations, The UN in Brief. http://www.un.org/Overview/brief.html

United Nations, Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights.

(1997). Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide:

Approved and proposed for signature and ratification or accession by General

Assembly resolution 260 A (III) of 9 December 1948 entry into force 12 January

1951, in accordance with article XIII. Geneva, Switzerland.

http://www.preventgenocide.org/law/convention/reservations/

UN General assembly. “36/103. Declaration on the Inadmissibility of Intervention and

Interference in the Internal Affairs of States.” Resolution 36-103: 91st plenary

meeting. 1981, December 9 http://www.un.org/documents/ga/res/36/a36r103.htm

Walzer, Michael, & Nardin, Terry (Ed.), (1996). War, Peace, and Jewish traditions.

Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Walzer, Micheal, (1995, Spring). The politics of rescue. Social research 62.

Page 33 of 34

Walzer, M , On just cause: Resorting to force. Canadian Journal of Political Science, 3,

XXXIII: 2000 (2001, April), 5 ,

http://www.wlu.ca/~wwwpress/jrls/cjps/issues/33.3/orend.html

Page 34 of 34