194
A New Approach to Quantum Logic K.Engesser [email protected] D.M. Gabbay dov.gabbay @kcl.ac.uk D. Lehmann [email protected]

A New Approach to Quantum Logic

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    2

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

A New Approach to Quantum Logic

K.Engesser [email protected]. Gabbay dov.gabbay @kcl.ac.ukD. Lehmann [email protected]

Page 2: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2

Page 3: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Contents

1 Introduction 7

2 A Crash Course in Logic 112.1 Basics of Classical Propositional Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11

2.1.1 Introductory Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 122.1.2 Syntax of Classical Propositional Logic . . . . . . . . . . 132.1.3 A Hilbert style deductive system for classical proposi-

tional logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 142.1.4 Semantics of Classical Propositional Logic . . . . . . . . . 192.1.5 Soundness and Completeness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 192.1.6 Compactness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 202.1.7 Lattices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 212.1.8 The Lindenbaum algebra . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22

2.2 Basics of Nonmonotonic Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 242.2.1 What is nonmonotonic logic? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 242.2.2 Non-monotonicity in quantum mechanics . . . . . . . . . 252.2.3 Inference operations and consequence relations . . . . . . 262.2.4 The concept of a GKLM model . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26

3 Some Hilbert Space Theory 293.1 The Concept of a Hilbert Space . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 293.2 Closed subspaces and projections in Hilbert space . . . . . . . . . 313.3 Orthonormal systems and the Fourier expansion . . . . . . . . . 323.4 More Lattice Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 353.5 The lattice of closed subspaces and projections of an orthomod-

ular space . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 383.6 Characterising classical Hilbert lattices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40

4 Basics of the Formalism of Quantum Mechanics 434.1 Some History . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 434.2 Hermitian operators . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 454.3 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46

3

Page 4: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

4 CONTENTS

5 Birkhoff- von Neumann 1936 495.0.1 Structure of the paper . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 505.0.2 Novel logical notions in quantum mechanics. . . . . . . . 505.0.3 Experimental Propositions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 525.0.4 A propositional calculus for quantum mechanics . . . . . 535.0.5 The correspondence between Birkhoff and von Neumannn

during the writing of the paper . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 585.0.6 The Kochen-Specker and the Schutte Tautologies . . . . . 60

6 The Dynamic Viewpoint: Propositions as Operators 616.1 Propositions viewed dynamically . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 616.2 The Concept of an M-Algebra . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 626.3 Motivation and Justification . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63

6.3.1 States . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 646.3.2 Measurements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 646.3.3 Illegitimate . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 656.3.4 Zeros . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 656.3.5 Idempotence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 666.3.6 Preservation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 666.3.7 Composition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 676.3.8 Interference . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 676.3.9 Cumulativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 686.3.10 Negation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 696.3.11 Separability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69

6.4 Examples of M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 696.4.1 Logical Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 696.4.2 Orthomodular and Hilbert spaces . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 71

6.5 Properties of M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 726.6 Connectives in M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 74

6.6.1 Connectives for arbitrary measurements . . . . . . . . . . 746.6.2 Connectives for commuting measurements . . . . . . . . . 75

6.7 Amongst commuting measurements connectives are classical . . . 786.8 Separable M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80

7 The Local Viewpoint: States as Logical Entities 817.1 What can logic do about quantum mechanics? . . . . . . . . . . 817.2 States as logical entities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 847.3 M-algebras and their languages . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 867.4 Implication M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 877.5 Conjunction M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 887.6 Strongly separable M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 89

7.6.1 States encode each other . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 907.6.2 Positive and Negative Introspection . . . . . . . . . . . . 907.6.3 States as self-contained logical entities . . . . . . . . . . . 917.6.4 Conjunction: the source of classical inconsistency in M-

algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93

Page 5: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

CONTENTS 5

7.6.5 Phase M-algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 967.6.6 Limiting case theorems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 977.6.7 The three faces of truth . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98

8 Aspects of Quantum Reality 998.1 General Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 998.2 The wave particle dualism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1018.3 Measurement as an unseparable whole: The Copenhagen inter-

pretation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1028.4 Are there ”elements of reality”? EPR and non-locality . . . . . . 1048.5 Bohm on wholeness and his experiment with language . . . . . . 1058.6 Informal reflections . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108

9 Holistic Logics 1119.1 Consequence Revision Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111

9.1.1 Formal Motivation: the Lindenbaum algebra viewed as anoperator algebra . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111

9.1.2 Consequence relations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1129.1.3 The Concept of a Consequence Revision System . . . . . 1149.1.4 The Concept of an Internalsing Connective . . . . . . . . 1169.1.5 Classical Logic Revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1199.1.6 The Semantics of Consequence Revision Systems . . . . . 1219.1.7 H-Models and Classical Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123

9.2 The Concept of a Holistic Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1249.2.1 Orthogonality, Encodedness, Dimension . . . . . . . . . . 1259.2.2 Selfreferential Soundness and Completeness . . . . . . . . 1269.2.3 Connection with the Modal System D . . . . . . . . . . . 1299.2.4 No Godel fixed points . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1329.2.5 Justifying logical rules . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1329.2.6 The case of a complete classical theory . . . . . . . . . . . 133

9.3 No Windows Theorems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1339.3.1 The Local No Windows Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1339.3.2 The Global No Windows Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135

9.4 Limiting case theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1369.4.1 Non-commuting operators in consequence revision sytems 1379.4.2 The Limiting Case Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137

9.5 Reflecting on Self-Referential Completeness . . . . . . . . . . . . 1399.5.1 How an agent with full introspection can be consistent . . 1399.5.2 The invisible proof operator in classical logic and classical

mechanics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1419.5.3 Feynman on the uncertainty principle: the logical tightrope142

10 Towards Hilbert Space 14310.1 Presenting Holistic Logics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 143

10.1.1 Orthomodular Holistic logics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14310.1.2 The Canonical H-Model for a Hilbert Space Logic . . . . 145

Page 6: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6 CONTENTS

10.1.3 Hilbert space logics as holistic logics: some properties . . 14610.2 Kochen-Specker-Schutte revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147

10.2.1 Classical inconsistency in Hilbert space logics . . . . . . . 14710.2.2 Birkhoff-von Neumann revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 148

10.3 Symmetry and Hilbert Space Presentability: The RepresentationTheorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14910.3.1 More about Holistic Logics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14910.3.2 Symmetry and Hilbert Space Logics . . . . . . . . . . . . 15110.3.3 Reflecting on the Representation Theorem . . . . . . . . . 154

10.4 Formal Reflections on the Connectives in Hilbert Space Logics . 15610.4.1 Quantum Consequence Relations and Inference Operations 15610.4.2 The Birkhoff-von Neumann Extension . . . . . . . . . . . 15710.4.3 The Lehmann Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15810.4.4 The Engesser-Gabbay Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16010.4.5 Discussing Negation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16110.4.6 Comment on ¬ −R2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 163

11 Some Speculative Reflections 16511.1 A Look at the Measurement Problem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165

11.1.1 General Remarks . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16511.1.2 The measurement problem in a nutshell . . . . . . . . . . 16711.1.3 Some more thoughts on measurement . . . . . . . . . . . 16811.1.4 Combining and correlating Hilbert space logics . . . . . . 16811.1.5 Passing to the limit . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17011.1.6 Complete classical theories and one-dimensional Hilbert

space logics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17111.1.7 Temporal evolution in measurement as correlating a Hilbert

space logic with a phase logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17411.1.8 Disentanglement and projection in measurement . . . . . 17411.1.9 Classical Measurement and the Idempotence of Measure-

ment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17711.1.10Schroedinger’s cat revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17811.1.11 Is the Hilbert space formalism the whole story? Legget’s

macrorealism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17911.1.12Does logic depend on decoherence? . . . . . . . . . . . . . 182

11.2 A Bit of Metaphysics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18311.2.1 Dualism versus Monism in Physics and Logic . . . . . . . 18311.2.2 Logical Monadology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 184

11.3 Reflections on holicity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 188

Page 7: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 1

Introduction

The main purpose of this monograph is to present the new approach to quantumlogic developed by the authors in recent years in the coherent form of a book.This approach constitutes a new way of looking at the connection betweenquantum mechanics and logic.

Only part of the ideas and the material presented here has been publishedso far. The published material consists of ”Quantum logic, Hilbert space,revision theory” by Engesser and Gabbay in Artificial Intelligence, 2002 and”Algebras of Measurements: the logical structure of Quantum mechanics” byLehmann-Engesser-Gabbay in the International Journal of Theoretical Physics,2006. These publications together with several preprints and drafts form thebasis of a more extensive theory which was developed collaboratively during thelast two years. This general theory is to form the core of the monograph.

The message of the book is of interest to a broad audience consisting of lo-gicians, mathematicians, philosophers of science, researchers in Artificial Intel-ligence and last but not least physicists. These communities, however, stronglydiffer in their scientific backgrounds. Normally, a physicist has no training inmathematical logic, and a logician is by no means expected to master the Hilbertspace formalism of quantum mechanics. This fact constitutes a major problemin any attempt to present the topic of quantum logic in a way accessible to thebroad audience to which, in principle, it is of interest. In a journal article forinstance it is extremely difficult, if not impossible, to solve this problem. Theprime intention of the authors is, apart from giving an extensive and coher-ent account of their theory, to present their approach in such a way that it isaccessible to the heterogeneous audience described.

Therefore, the first chapters serve to provide the reader with the logical andmathematical background that will enable him to understand the subsequentchapters. Chapter 2 presents the prerequisites from logic. In chapter 3 weintroduce the concept of a Hilbert space, which constitutes the core structureof the formalism of quantum mechanics. We summarise- for the most partwithout proof- basic facts of Hilbert space theory which provide the readerwith the mathematical equipment essential for the understanding of the core

7

Page 8: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

8 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

chapters. Chapter 3, however, contains a first result of our resarch, namely acharacterisation of classical Hilbert lattices which is of interest from the purelymathematica point of view.

In Chapter 4 we give a similar summary of the the main facts about themathematical formalism of quantum mechanics.

Quantum logic has its origin in the famous 1936 now classic paper byBirkhoff-von Neumann entitled ”The logic of quantum mechanics”. This pa-per is still today by far the most widely quoted paper in the field. We devoteChapter 5 to a detailed analysis and, in a sense, to a reconstruction of this clas-sic. The reason for this is twofold. The Birkhoff-von Neumann paper is, today,not easy to read, and it is thus an end in itself to interpret and reconstruct it inmodern terminology and highlight its main ideas. Moreover, this chapter servesas a basis for putting in perspective the approach to quantum logic put forwardin this book. This approach may, to a considerable extent at least, be viewedas a refinement of the ideas of Birkhoff and von Neumann. The relationship be-tween the two views is on the one hand a ’local-global’ relationship. In a senseto be made precise the authors’ theory may be viewed as the ’local’ version ofBirkhoff-von Neumann style quantum logic. On the other hand the refinementconsists in our view of propositions. In the approach presented in this bookthe focus is on viewing propositions as projections in Hilbert space rather than(closed) subspaces as do Birkhoff and von Neumann. This allows for a dynamicview of propositions.

The core of the message of the book is contained in chapters 6,7,9 and 10.In these chapters we introduce and investigate new concepts which we think canplay a fruitful role in quantum logic. Formally, these concepts are abstractionsfrom structures we find in Hilbert space. In chapter 6 we abstract from thelattice of projections of a Hilbert space introducing and studying structureswhich we call algebras of measurements, M-algebras for short. In coining theterm M-algebra for these structures we are aware of the fact that this is aloose way of making use of the term ”algebra”. In the strict sense of UniversalAlgebra these structures do not qualify as algebras. Logically, the novelty ofthis approach consists in a new way of treating propositions. It is inspired bythe analogy between propositions and measurements in physics, in particularquantum measurements. Suppose a physicist performs a measurement of acertain physical quantity A pertaining to a certain physical system. Supposethis system is in a certain state x. The physicist will then in general formulatethe result of his measurement as a proposition of the form A = µ, where µ isthe value of A measured, and he will then claim this proposition to be a truestatement about the system under investigation. In this there is no differencebetween classical and quantum physics. There exists, however, an essentialdifference between the classical and the quantum case which seems to us offundamental importance from the logical point of view. Namely, the meaningsof the physicist’s assertion that A = µ is true differ in the two cases, classicaland quantum. In classical mechanics the proposition A = µ is a true statementabout the physical system in state x. In the quantum case it is a true statementtoo. The crucial difference, however, is that in the quantum case the proposition

Page 9: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9

A = µ is in general no longer a true statement about the state x but about acertain state y distinct from x, namely about the state of the system ’aftermeasurement’. The reason for this is that quantum measurements generallyinvolve, in contrast to ’classical’ measurements, a change of state of the systemmeasured. Logically speaking, the situation we have in classical mechanics isthis. Given a state x (state of affairs, state of the world...) and some propositionα. Then α has some truth value in state x. In bivalent logic these truth valuesare ’true’ and ’false’. In multi-valued logic there are more truth values, possiblyeven infinitely many. The situation in quantum mechanics is different. Givena state x and a proposition α. Then α does not necessarily possess any truthvalue in x. Rather it is only in some other state distinct from x , namely inthe state ’after measurement’, that it acquires a truth value. In Chapter 6 wetake this dynamic aspect of quantum propositions seriously. It is the source ofinspiration for developing a general logical framework in which the static notionof truth of a proposition prevailing in traditional logic is replaced by the moregeneral dynamic notion of a proposition acting on states. This framework turnsout to be a natural generalisation of the traditional static view in which thelogical structure of classical and quantum mechanics can be described and theirrelationship be put in evidence. Classical logic and correspondingly classicalmechanics appear as the static limiting cases of a dynamic framework.

In chapter 7 we introduce what we call the local viewpoint in quantum logic asopposed to the global point of view that prevailed in the preceding chapters. Inthe Birkhoff-von Neumann paper propositions are represented as sets of states.The concept of a state itself is not the focus of attention. The same is truefor our framework of M-algebras as developed in Chapter 6. In that frameworkstates are primitive notions. In chapter 7 we make the concept of a state itselfthe focus of investigation. This chapter may be viewed as a logical enquiry intothe nature of physical states.

Chapter 8 is an interlude addressing primarily those readers who haven’t hadmuch contact with quantum mechanics yet. We give a report on some of thewell known ’odd’ features of the quantum world. Again our intention is twofold.First, the reader can hardly appreciate logical considerations on quantum me-chanics without being familiar with the salient physical features of the quantumworld. Second, we regard this chapter as a vehicle for conveying the impres-sion to the reader that quantum mechanics touches on fundamental issues, evenbeyond the realm of physics. It seems that, in contrast to previous physicaltheories, quantum mechanics raises not just the question what are the laws thatgovern physical reality but the issue of the very nature of (physical) reality itself.It is often argued both in the seriously philosophical and the popular scientificliterature that the proper understanding of quantum mechanics requires a re-vision of the view of reality to which we are used from classical physics. It isfrequently argued that a main obstacle to the proper understanding of quan-tum mechanics consists in the ’fragmented’ world view which underlies classicalmechanics and, by the way, also classical logic. The intuition all pervading theliteature is that quantum mechanics requires a more holistic view of reality thanwe are used to from classical mechanics. Bohm’s classic book ”Wholeness and

Page 10: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION

the Implicate Order” is a most profound and eloquent account of this.In chapter 9 we introduce and study another new concept of crucial impor-

tance, namely that of a holistic logic and as a special case that of a Hilbertspace logic. Again, the concept of a holistic logic is an abstraction from logicalstructures we find in Hilbert space as is the concept of an M-algebra.

In chapter 10 entitled ”Towards Hilbert space” we pursue the questionwhether the concept of a Hilbert space can be characterised in terms of thelogical structures studied in the preceding chapters. We present a representa-tion theorem which may be regarded as a positive answer to the above question.This is part of what in the literature on the foundations of quantum mechanicsis sometimes called the representation enterprise, a term denoting the projectof deriving the formalism of quantum mechanics from certain first principles.In our case these first principles are of a purely logical nature.

The last chapter has a speculative character. There we even permit ourselvesa little bit of metaphysics. We speculate about the possible implications ourresults and considerations presented thus far may have for the treatment ofcertain foundational problems of quantum mechanics. In particular, we presentan admittedly speculative treatment of the measurement problem in which theparadoxical nature this problem displays in other approaches is avoided.

As a rough summary we can say that, conceptually, the message of this bookrests on two pillars. The first pillar is the dynamic view of propositions. Weview propositions as acting on states (of the world) and changing them ratherthan just being true or false in these states. The second pillar is a logical enquiryinto the nature of physical states.

The main mathematical results presented in this book arise from these twosources.

Page 11: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 2

A Crash Course in Logic

Abstract:. The reason for including this chapter is to make the book as self-contained as possible. It should in particular be accessible to physicists, whonormally have no training in formal logic. We present the basics of classicalpropositional logic and non-monotonic logic. In fact, it is possible to providethe reader with all the logical equipment he needs in order to understand thelogical investigations in later chapters. The material covered by the introductionto classical propositional logic comprises the following:

The language of classical propositional logicThe notion of a consequence relation, monotonic or notPresenting classical consequence in (old fashioned) Hilbert styleTruth functional semanticsSoundness and Completeness TheoremCompactness theoremDeduction theoremThe Lindenbaum (-Tarski) algebraThis is, in particular, sufficient to enable the reader to understand the logical

investigations in the chapters 6, 7 94and10.Basics of Nonmonotonic Logic ¥

2.1 Basics of Classical Propositional Logic

All the reader needs to know about classical propositional logic is:

• The Deduction Theorem

• The Soundness and Completeness Theorem

• The Compactness Theorem

• The Concept of a Lindenbaum (-Tarski) Algebra

11

Page 12: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

12 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

2.1.1 Introductory Remarks

Logic nowadays means formal logic. Modern logic studies logical systems asformal systems based on a precisely defined formal language. The concept mostcentral to logic is that of logical consequence. Logical consequence is a relationbetween two statements α and β or, more generally, a relation between a set ofstatements Σ and a statement α. One may synonymously say ”α is a logicalconsequence of Σ” or ”α follows (logically) from Σ” or ”α can be deducedlogically (or is deducible) from Σ”. Logical deduction is a vital part of ourcompetence as human beings in both everyday and scientific discourse, and it isone of the seminal achievements of modern mathematical logic to have providedthe tools for a mathematically rigorous analysis of the intuitive concept of logicalconsequence.

Given two statements α and β in some (natural or formal) language. Whatdoes it mean to say that β is a logical consequence of α? The first idea thatmay come to mind is to say that β can, in some way, be proved from α in thesense that if α is assumed then we can deduce β using certain rules of logicaldeduction. On this view ”β follows from α” means ”β is provable from α”. Itis thus obvious that a rigorous analysis must then provide a precise definitionof what it means to say ”is provable”. In other words, the logician’s task thenconsists in making precise the concept of a proof.

Another natural intuition in approaching the issue of logical consequence isthis. We may say that ”β follows from α” means something like ”Whenever αis true, then so is β”. In this case a rigorous treatment requires a ’theory oftruth’.

In fact, modern (formal) logic reflects these natural intuitions in the way itexplicates and studies logical consequence.

Generally, in modern style, logical consequence is specified in a twofold way,namely syntactically and semantically. Its syntactic specification consists inpresenting a formal deductive system by a set of logical axioms and a set of rulesof deduction. Such a system may look as follows. Given a set Σ of statementsand let α be some statement. Then we say that α is a logical consequence ofΣ, symbolically Σ ` α, if α can be proved from Σ. We then have to say what’proved from Σ’ means. Essentially, the idea is this. Assume we have certainpurely logical axioms, logical truths so to speak, which can be used freely in anyproof. Moreover, consider the statements in Σ as given assumptions that canequally be used freely in the proof. If we can then ’derive’ α from these givenstatements using the rules of deduction we say that α can be proved from Σ. Adeductive system of this sort is called a Hilbert syle deductive system. There arevarious other types of deductive systems such as those introduced by Gentzenor natural deduction type systems introduced by Prawitz. There are also logicalsystems which put restrictions on the use of axoims and assumptions in proofssuch as resource logics in which assumptions are viewed as sort of resource thatcan be ’used up’ in the course of the proof and can therefore not be used freelyin the proof. In this introductory chapter to logic we will present a Hilbert styledeductive system that which goes back to Hilbert and Bernays [30]. The reader

Page 13: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.1. BASICS OF CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 13

should note that a proof will be a completely formal procedure involving justthe formal manipulation of symbols.

The semantic approach to the concept of logical consequence invokes thenotion of truth. As we said, from the semantic point of view, to say that α is alogical consequence of Σ means that α is true whenever all statements of Σ aretrue, in symbols Σ |= α. In this, clearly, two things must be made precise. Firstwe need to make precise what it means to say that a statement is true. Second,we need to make precise what it means to say ”whenever α is true” We will seeshortly how this works.

Once we have defined logical consequence in this twofold way, there arises aproblem. We need to study how these two notions of logical consequence, syn-tactic and semantic, are related. More precisely, we want to prove soundnessof the logic. This means we need to show that α ` β implies α |= β. This is anatural requirement saying that syntactic consequence implies semantic conse-quence. If we can prove the other direction too, i.e. that semantic consequenceimplies syntactic consequence, we say that the logical system is complete. Gen-erally a logical system is required to be sound. There are well established logics,however, which are not complete.

In this chapter we present the basics of classical propositional logic in thestyle described. In particular, we will see that classical propositional logic issound and complete.

2.1.2 Syntax of Classical Propositional Logic

We start by defining the language of classical propositional logic. We are awareof the fact that the way we do this does not meet the standards of linguisticprecision the pure logician might expect.

To those readers who are interested in a presentation of the highest standardswe recommend Friedrichdorf’s excellent textbook [16].

The language of propositional logic is built up from the following symbols:1) A set of propositional variables2) Symbols for the connectives: ¬ (negation)and → (implication)3) BracketsWe define the set Fml of well formed formulas of the language of proposi-

tional logic, formulas for short, inductively by the following clauses:

• Every propositional variable p is a formula.

• If α and β are formulas, so are ¬α and (α → β).

If there is no danger of misunderstandings we omit the brackets. To be a bitmore precise, Fml is the smallest set satisfying the above conditions.

Fix a certain variable p and define the symbols > and ⊥ as abbreviationsfor p → p and ¬> respectively. Moreover we use the following abbreviations.

• α∧β for ¬(α → ¬β)

• α ∨ β for (¬α → β)

Page 14: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

14 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

• α ↔ β for (α → β) ∧ (β → α)

2.1.3 A Hilbert style deductive system for classical propo-sitional logic

Definition 2.1 A (Hilbert style) deductive system consists of a set of formulascalled axioms and a set of rules of inference. Given a deductive system L and aset Σ of formulas. A proof from Σ in L is a sequence of formulas such that eachelement is either an axiom or an element of Σ or it can be inferred from previouselements using a rule of inference. The elements of Σ are called assumptions.If α is the last element of the sequence, the sequence is called a proof of α fromΣ. We say that α is provable from Σ, denoted by Σ ` α, if there exists a proofof α from Σ. If Σ is a set of axioms, we write ` α.

Definition 2.2 H is a deductive system with four axiom schemes and one ruleof inference. More precisely, for any formulas α, β, γ, the following formulasare axioms:

• Axiom scheme 1: (α → (β → α))

• Axiom scheme 2: ((α → (β → γ)) → ((α → β) → (α → γ))

• Axiom scheme 3: (α → (¬α → β)

• Axiom scheme 4: (α → β) → ((¬α → β) → β)

The rule of inference is called modus ponens (MP for short). For any formulasα, β: if ` α and ` α → β, then ` β.

` α, ` α → ββ

The proof of the following important lemma is an exercise in deduction inthe above deductive system.

Lemma 2.1 Far any δ we have ` δ → δ.

Proof. Consider axiom scheme A2 for α =: δ and β =: δ → δ and γ =: δ.Then we have by A2

(1) ` (δ → ((δ → δ) → δ)) → (δ → (δ → δ)) → (δ → δ))

Consider axiom A1 for α =: δ and β =: δ → δ. Then we have by A1

(2) ` (δ → ((δ → δ) → δ))

Modus ponens applied to (1) and (2) gives us

(3) ` δ → ((δ → δ) → δ) → δ)

By A1 we have

Page 15: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.1. BASICS OF CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 15

(4) ` δ → (δ → δ)

Modus ponens aplied to (4) and (5) yields what we want.

(5) ` δ → δ

¥

We have the following derived rulesR1:

Σ ` αΣ ` β → α

R2:Σ ` α → (β → γ), Σ ` α → β

Σ ` α → γR3 :Σ ` α, Σ ` ¬α

Σ ` βR4 :Σ ` α → β, Σ ` ¬α → β,

Σ ` βWhat does ’derived rule’ mean? Consider R1. It says that given a set

Σ of assumptions and suppose Σ ` α. Then R1 says that Σ ` β → α. Infact, suppose Σ ` α. This says that there exists a proof of α from Σ: ...α.Considering that α → (β → α) is an axiom and using modus ponens we seethat ...α, α → (β → α), β → α is a proof of β → α from Σ. As to R2 supposethat ...α → (β → γ) and ...α → β are proofs from Σ. Using Axiom scheme 2and aplying modus ponens twice we see that the following sequence is a prooffrom Σ: ...α → (β → γ...α → β, (α → (β → γ) → ((α → β) → (α → γ)),(α → β) → (α → γ), α → γ.

Analogously we can prove that R3 and R4 are in fact derived rules.DO THE PROOFS.The following lemma states some obvious facts about provability.

Lemma 2.2 • (i) If Σ ⊂ Ω and Σ ` α, then Ω ` α

• (ii) Suppose Σ ` δ for all δ ∈ ∆ and ∆ ` α. Then Σ ` α

• (iii) Suppose Σ ` α and Σ ` α → β. Then Σ ` β

• (iv) Σ ` α iff there exists a finite ∆ ⊂ Σ such that ∆ ` α

Definition 2.3 We call a set of formulas Σ consistent if not Σ ` ⊥. We say Σis maximal consistent if it is consistent and does not admit a proper consistentextension.

Lemma 2.3 A set of formulas Σ is consistent iff every finite subset of Σ isconsistent.

Page 16: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

16 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

Proof. For the direction from left to right suppose Σ is consistent and thereexists a finite ∆ ⊂ Σ which is inconsistent. This means that ∆ ` ⊥. Bylemma 2.2 we then have Σ ` ⊥. Thus Σ would be inconsistent contrary to thehypothesis.

For the other direction assume every finite ∆ ⊂ Σ is consistent and Σ isinconsistent. It follows that Σ ` ⊥. By lemma 2.2 there exists a finite ∆ ⊂ Σsuch that ∆ ` ⊥. But this would mean that ∆ is inconsistent contrary to thehypothesis. ¥

The next lemma is called Lindenbaum’s Lemma

Lemma 2.4 Let Σ be consistent. Then there exists a maximal consistent set Ωsuch that Σ ⊂ Ω

In the sequel we assume the language to be denumerable although, later onin the book, we also want to admit non-denumerable languages. All theoremsproved in this chapter also hold for non-denumerable languages. In some of theproofs we then have to use Zorn’s lemma.

Proof. Choose an enumeration α0, α1, α2... of all formulas.Then define a sequence of sets of formulas Σ0 ⊂ Σ1 ⊂ Σ2... as follows:

Σ0 = Σ, Σn+1 =: Σn ∪ αn, if Σ ∪ αn is consistent, otherwise Σn+1 =: Σn

Let Ω be the union of all these sets, i.e. Ω =⋃

Σn

First note that Ω is an extension of Σ by construction.We claim that Ω is maximal consistent. To see this, first note that any Σn is

consistent by construction. Assume Ω is inconsistent. This would by ?? meanthat a there exists a finite ∆ ⊂ Ω that is inconsistent. But we have ∆ ⊂ Σn forsome n. Thus Σn would be inconsistent contrary to the way it was constructed.It follows that Ω is consistent.

We still need to prove that Ω is maximal consistent. Assume it is not maxi-mal consistent. This means that there exists a proper consistent extension Ω∗ ofΩ which is consistent. Then there exists a formula α ∈ Ω∗ such that not α ∈ Ω.We have α = αn for some n in the above enumeration. Since not αn ∈ Ω,we have that in the above construction not α ∈ Σn+1. But this means thatΣn ∪ α is inconsistent and thus Ω∗ is inconsistent because Σn ∪ α ⊂ Ω∗,which is a contradiction. ¥

The next theorem is called the Deduction Theorem.

Theorem 2.1 Σ ∪α ` β iff Σ ` α → β

Proof. For the direction from right to left assume that there exists a proof ofα → β from Σ. Then by modus ponens there exists a proof of β from Σ ∪ α,which means that Σ ∪ α ` β.

The direction from left to right is less obvious. The proof of this direction isby induction on the length of the proof of β from Σ ∪ α. More precisely, weprove the following. Let δ1, δ2, ..., δn = β be a proof of β from Σ∪α. Then we

Page 17: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.1. BASICS OF CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 17

have by the induction hypothesis that Σ ` α → δ1,Σ ` α → δ2, ...Σ ` α → δn−1

We then need to show that Σ ` α → δn. Consider two cases.Case 1: δj ∈ Σ or δj is an axiom, then Σ ` δj . Applying the derived rule

R1 we get Σ ` α → β.Case 2: δj is obtained by modus ponens from two preceding formulas, i.e.

there exist j1 ∈ 1, ..., n − 1 such that δj is obtained from δj1 and δj1 → δj

by modus ponens. By the induction hypothesis we have Σ ` α → δj1 andΣ ` α → δj1 → δj . Applying the derived rule R2 gives us Σ ` α → β ¥

Suppose (α → β) ∈ Ω and α ∈ Ω. We prove that α ∈ Ω. By i) we haveΩ ` α and Ω ` α → β. By modus ponens we have Ω ` β and thus by (i) β ∈ Ω.

For the other direction it suffices to show that if not α ∈ Ω, then (α → β) ∈ Ωand if β ∈ Ω, then α → β) ∈ Ω.

So assume that not α ∈ Ω. By (ii) we have ¬α ∈ Ω and thus Ω ` ¬α. Usingthe derived rule R1 we then get Ω ` α → ¬α. On the other hand we have byaxiom 3 Ω ` α → (¬α → β. Applying the derived rule R2 we get Ω ` α → βand thus (α → β) ∈ Ω.

Finally assume that β ∈ Ω. By the derived rule R1 we have Ω ` α → β andthus (α → β) ∈ Ω

Lemma 2.5 If not Σ ` α, then Σ ∪ ¬α is consistent.

Proof. Given the hypothesis, we need to prove that not (Σ ∪ ¬α ` ⊥. Forthis we show that Σ ∪ ¬α ` ⊥ implies Σ ` α. So let

(1) Σ ∪ ¬α ` ⊥We have by lemma 2.1 and the detinition of the symbol >

(2) Σ ∪ ¬α ` >We get by (1) and (2) and the derived rule R3 that

(3) Σ ∪ ¬α ` α

It follows from (3) and the Deduction Theorem that

4 Σ ` ¬α → α

Again by lemma 2.1 we have

5 Σ ` α → α

The derived rule R4 applied to (4) and (5) then gives us

Σ ` α

¥

Definition 2.4 let Σ be a consistent set. Then call Σ a theory or synonymouslydeductively closed if Σ ` α implies α ∈ Σ. Call Σ complete if for any α we haveeither α ∈ Σ or ¬α ∈ Σ.

Page 18: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

18 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

Theorem 2.2 Let Σ be consistent. Then the following statements are equiva-lent

• (i) Ω is maximal consistent.

• (ii) Ω deductively closed, i.e. a theory.

• (iii) Ω is complete.

Proof. We prove that (i) implies (ii). So let Ω be maximal consistent. Considerthe set ∆ := β | Ω ` β. We have Ω ⊂ ∆. Moreover, ∆ is consistent because∆ ` ⊥ would, by 2.2, imply Ω ` ⊥ contradicting the consistency of Ω. So ∆ is aconsistent extension of Ω. Since Ω is maximal consistent, it follows that ∆ = Ω.We have proved that Ω ` α implies α ∈ Ω which means that Ω is deductivelyclosed.

We now prove that (ii) implies (iii).Assume that both α and ¬α are in Ω. Then (i) would give us Ω ` α

and Ω ` ¬α and, by the derived rule R3 we would have Ω ` ⊥, which is acontradiction because Ω is assumed to be consistent. It follows that at mostone of the formulas α and ¬α are in Ω. Assume now that neither α nor ¬α isin Ω. This would mean, since Ω is maximal consistent, that the sets Ω ∪ αand Ω ∪ ¬α are inconsistent, i.e. Ω ∪ α ` ⊥ and Ω ∪ ¬α ` ⊥. It wouldthen follow by the Deduction Theorem that Ω ` α → ⊥ and Ω ` ¬α → ⊥. Bythe derived rule R4 we would have Ω ` ⊥, a contradiction.

We still need to prove that (iii) implies (i). Supose Ω is complete. Assumeit’s not maximal consistent. This means that there exists a consistent extensionΩ∗ of Ω a formula α such that α ∈ Ω∗ and not α ∈ Ω. Since Ω is complete wehave ¬α ∈ Ω and thus ¬α ∈ Ω∗. Again using the derived rule R3 would give usΩ∗ ` ⊥ contradicting the consistency of Ω∗. It follows that Ω does not admit aproper consistent extension, i.e. that it is maximal consistent.

¥

Theorem 2.3 Let Ω be maximal consistent. Then we have (α → β) ∈ Ω iffnot α ∈ Ω or β ∈ Ω

Proof. Suppose (α → β) ∈ Ω and α ∈ Ω. We prove that β ∈ Ω. We haveΩ ` α and Ω ` α → β. By modus ponens we have Ω ` β and, since Ω isdeductively closed, β ∈ Ω.

For the other direction we need to show that if not α ∈ Ω, then (α → β) ∈ Ω,and if β ∈ Ω, then α → β) ∈ Ω.

So assume that not α ∈ Ω. By 2.2 we have ¬α ∈ Ω and thus Ω ` ¬α. Usingthe derived rule R1 we then get Ω ` α → ¬α. On the other hand we have byA3 Ω ` α → (¬α → β. Applying the derived rule R2 we get Ω ` α → β andthus, since Ω is deductively closed, (α → β) ∈ Ω.

Finally assume that β ∈ Ω. By the derived rule R1 we have Ω ` α → β andthus (α → β) ∈ Ω. ¥

Page 19: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.1. BASICS OF CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 19

2.1.4 Semantics of Classical Propositional Logic

As indicated earlier, we now approach the concept of logical consequence fromthe semantic point of view. For this we need, as already mentioned, a theory oftruth. In the following definition we explain what it means for a formula α tobe true under a valuation V .

Definition 2.5 A valuation V is any function assigning a truth value to anyformula, i.e. 1 or 0 such that

• (V )(¬α) = 1 iff V (α) = 0

• V (α → β) = 1 iff V (α) = 0 or V (β) = 1

We say that α is true under V if V (α) = 1. If α is true under any valuation Vwe say that α is a (classical) tautology.

Given a set Σ of formulas and a valuation V such that V (α) = 1 for allα ∈ Σ we say that V is a model for Σ.

In the above definition we used the ”or” (disjunction) of the English lan-guage. In the meta language, i.e. in English, a we define the disjunction to betrue if at least one disjunct is true.

The reader may think of a valuation V as follows. Given any functionV : V ar → 0, 1. Then V can be extended in a unique way to a valuation(again denoted) by V . This means that it suffices to specify a valuation byspecifying its values for the propositional variables.

In the next lemma we again use a meta connective, namely the ”and” (con-junction) of English. In the meta language (English) we define a conjunction tobe true iff both conjuncts are true.

Lemma 2.6 For any valuation V we have

• V (>) = 1

• V (⊥) = 0

• V (α ∧ β) = 1 iff V (α) = 1 and V (β) = 1

2.1.5 Soundness and Completeness

Lemma 2.7 Let Σ be maximal consistent. Σ has a model.

Proof. We define VΣ as follows. If p ∈ Σ then VΣ(p) = 1 otherwise VΣ(p) = 0We prove that VΣ has the properties above by induction on the construction ofwff.

If α is a variable the claim holds by the definition of VΣ.In the case α = ¬β we argue as follows. VΣ(α) = 1 iff VΣ(β) = 0 This is,

by the induction hypothesis, the case iff not β ∈ Σ and, since Σ is maximalconsistent, this is equivalent to α ∈ Σ. The other cases are analogous. ¥

Page 20: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

20 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

The following theorem is an immediate consequence of the above lemma.

Theorem 2.4 Any consistent set Σ of wff has a model, i.e there exists a valu-ation V such that V (α) = 1 for all α ∈ Σ.

We now give the semantic definition of logical consequence.

Definition 2.6 Given a set Σ of formulas and a formula α. We say that α isa semantic consequence of Σ, in symbols Σ |= α, if for model V of Σ we haveV (α) = 1

It is routine to verify the following. Given any axiom α, then we have forany valuation V that V (α) = 1, i.e. every axiom is a tautology. Moreover, giventwo formulas α and β and a valuation V such that V (α) = 1 and V (α → β) = 1,then we have V (β) = 1. Thus any axiom is true under any valuation and modusponens preserves truth.

The next theorem, which expresses soundness of classial propositional logic,is an immediate consequence of the above facts.

Theorem 2.5 Σ ` α implies Σ |= α

The following theorem is the Completeness Theorem of classical propositionallogic. As always in logic completeness is more hard to prove than soundness.

Theorem 2.6 Σ |= α implies Σ ` α

Proof. We show that not Σ ` α implies that not Σ |= α. Assume that notΣ ` α. It follows by lemma 2.5 that Γ =: Σ ∪ ¬α is consistent. By theorem2.4 Γ has a model, i.e. there exists a valuation V such that V (β) = 1 for allβ ∈ Γ. In particular we then have V (β) = 1 for all β ∈ Σ and V (¬α) = 1 andthus V (α) = 0. But this means that not Σ |= α

¥

2.1.6 Compactness

Suppose that Σ ` α. Since any proof of α from Σ involves only finitely manyassumptions there exists a finite ∆ ⊂ Σ such that ∆ ` α.

We therefore have the following theorem, which is known as the CompactnessTheorem of classical propositional logic.

Theorem 2.7 Σ ` α (or equivalently Σ |= α) iff there exists a finite ∆ ⊂ Σsuch that ∆ |= α or (equivalently ∆ ` α).

Page 21: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.1. BASICS OF CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 21

2.1.7 Lattices

We define the concepts ofa latticean orthocomplemented latticeBoolean algebra

Definition 2.7 A partially ordered set (in short poset) is a pair 〈L,≤〉, where Lis a non empty set and ≤ is a binary relation satisfying the following conditions

• (i) A ≤ A for any A ∈ L (reflexivity)

• (ii) If A ≤ B and B ≤ A, then A = B (antisymmetry)

• If A ≤ B and B ≤ C, then A ≤ C (transitivity)

Call ≤ a partial order.Let S ⊂ L. An upper bound of S is an element a ∈ L such that b ≤ a for all

b ∈ S. a least upper bound of S is is an element a ∈ L such that a is an upperbound and a ≤ b for every upper bound of S. Analogously we define the conceptof lower bound of S and the concept of a greatest lower bound.

It is readily seen that, if a least upper bound exists for S, then it is uniqueand analogously for the greatest lower bound.

Definition 2.8 The partially ordered set 〈L,≤〉 is called a lattice if for any twoelements A and B there exists the least upper bound denoted by A ∨ B and thegreatest lower bound denoted by A ∧ B and there exists a zero elment 0 and aunit element 1, i.e. elements such that for all A ∈ L we have 0 ≤ A and A ≤ 1.The lattice is called complete if any subset of L has a greatest lower bound anda smallest upper bound.

The reader may realise that we denote the least upper bound (greatest lowerbound) in a lattice by the same symbol as the propositional connectives of con-junction (disjunction) which should not lead to any confusion. It is readilyverified that greatest lower bounds and least uper bounds are uniquely deter-mined if they exist. The same is true for the zero and unit element.

Definition 2.9 We call a lattice distributive if the following holds for anyA,B, C ∈ L

A ∨ (B ∧ C) = (A ∨B ∧ (A ∨ C)

Definition 2.10 Let L be a lattice. A map

A 7→ A⊥

is called an orthocomplementation and A⊥ the orthocomplement of A if it hasthe following properties

Page 22: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

22 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

• (i) A⊥⊥ = A

• (ii) if A ≤ B then B⊥ ≤ A⊥

• (iii) A ∧A⊥ = 0

• (iv) A ∨A⊥ = 1

We call a 〈L,≤,⊥ 〉 an orthocomplemented lattice or simply an ortholatticeif ⊥ is an orthocomplement of the lattice 〈≤〉.

Definition 2.11 A Boolean algebra is an orthocomplemented and distributivelattice.

2.1.8 The Lindenbaum algebra

We now make the connection between classical logic on the hand and certainalgebraic structures on the other. In the case of classical logic it is the conceptof a Boolean algebra that constitutes its algebraic counterpart. At this stagewe introduce the concept of a Lindenbaum algebra in the traditional manner.We will look at this concept in a new way in Chapter 9

Given a consistent set Σ. We then write `Σ α for Σ ` α. Call two formulas αand β Σ-equivalent, in symbols ≡Σ, if `Σ α ↔ β. We will see that this is in factan equivalence relation. Denote the equivalence class of α by [α] and denotethe set of these equivalence classes by AΣ. These equivalence classes form a(Boolean) algebra in a natural way. Namely, define [α] ≤Σ [β] if Σ ∪ α ` βThis is well defined as we will see. Similarly define [α]∗=: [¬α]. Again, this iswell defined. The proof of the following theorem is straightforward and is, inother books sometimes left to the reader as an exercise. We present it here inmore detail than is usual because, in this book, we will look at the concept ofa Lindenbaum algebra from a more general point of view later on will prove amore general theorem of which the next theorem is a special case. The readercan then compare the difference in level of these approaches. The gist of thisviewpoint is that we can view the Lindenbaum algebra as an operator algebrain a natural way. This viewpoint will permit us to generalise the concept of aLindenbaum algebra and to prove a more general theorem of which the nexttheorem is a special case.

Theorem 2.8 LTΣ = 〈AΣ,≤Σ, ∗〉 is a Boolean algebra.

The proof of the above theoem relies on certain facts of classical logic whichwe stated in the following lemmata. It is routine, and we therefore do notpresent it in all details. Rather we describe the general procedure of the proofelaborating on just a few typical items. The reader is invited to work out thefull proof as an exercise.

It should be noted that theorem is a purely syntactic statement and so arethe lemmata below. The reader might therefore expect purely syntactic proofs.In fact, this way of proceeding is perfectly feasible. It would, however, as the

Page 23: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.1. BASICS OF CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 23

reader can easily convince himself, be fairly tedious at least compared to theway we will actually proceed.

Rather we will prove the syntactic lemmata below in a more transparentway semantically. What does this mean? It means that by the soundness andcompleteness theorems all the syntactic statements involved in the lemmatabelow are equivalent to certain semantic statements. It therefore suffices -bysoundness and completeness- to prove the semantic equivalents of the lemmatabelow. All the statements to be proved reduce to proving statements of the form`Σ α. By the soundness and completeness we know that these statements areequivalent to statements of the form Σ |= α. In order to prove such a statementwe can, by the semantic definition of logical consequence, proceed as follows.Given any valuation V such that V (ϕ) = 1 for all ϕ ∈ Σ, i.e. V is a model ofΣ, then show that V (α) = 1.

In the sequel Σ denotes a consistent set of formulas.

Lemma 2.8 • (1) `Σ α ↔ α

• (2) If `Σ α ↔ β, then `Σ β ↔ α

• (3) If `Σ α ↔ β and `Σ β ↔ γ, then `Σ α ↔ γ

Proof. We restrict ourselves to (3). The other cases are proved analogously.Assume that Σ |= α ↔ β and Σ |= β ↔ γ. We need to show that Σ |= α ↔ γ.Let V be any model of Σ. Then we have by the first hypothesis that eitherV (α) = V (β) = 1 or V (α) = V (β) = 0. In the first case we get from thesecond hypothesis that V (β) = V (γ) = 1. It follows that V (α ↔ β) = 1. In thesecond case we get from the second hypothesis that V (α) = V (γ) = 0 and thusV (α ↔ γ) = 1. ¥

Lemma 2.9 Suppose that `Σ α ↔ α′ and `Σ β ↔ β′. Then we have

• (1) `Σ α ∧ β ↔ α′ ∧ β′

• (2) `Σ α ∨ β ↔ α′ ∨ β′

• (3) `Σ ¬α ↔ ¬α′

• (4) `Σ (α → β) ↔ (α′ → β′)

Proof.¥

Lemma 2.10 • (1) `Σ α ↔ α

• (2) If `Σ α → β and `Σ β → α, then `Σ α ↔ β.

• (3) If `Σ α → β and β → γ, then `Σ α → γ

The leave the proof of the following lemmata to the reader as an exercise inthe procedure applied above.

Page 24: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

24 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

Lemma 2.11 • (1) `Σ (α ∧ β) → α

• (2) `Σ (α ∧ β) → β

• (3) If `Σ γ → α and `Σ γ → β, then `Σ γ → (α ∧ β).

• (4) `Σ α → α ∧ β

• (5) `Σ β → α ∧ β

• (6) `Σ ⊥ → α

• (7) `Σ α>

Lemma 2.12 If `Σ γ → α and `Σ γ → β, then `Σ γ → α ∧ β.

Lemma 2.13 • (1) `Σ α ↔ ¬¬α

• (2) `Σ α ∧ ¬α ↔ ⊥• (3) `Σ α ∨ ¬α ↔ >• (4) α ∧ (β ∨ γ) ↔ (α ∧ β) ∨ (α ∧ γ)

We now prove the theorem.

Proof. We first need to show that ≡Σ is in fact an equivalence relation. Wejust verify transitivity. The other conditions are proved analogously. So letα ≡Σ β and β ≡Σ γ. By the definition of ≡Σ this says that `Σ α ↔ β and`Σ βγ. Lemma 2.8 then gives us α ≡Σ γ.

We now need to see that ≤ is well defined. For this we must verify thatgiven α ≡Σ α′ and β ≡Σ β′, `Σ α → β implies ` α′ → β′. But this is lemma2.9 (4). That ≤ is a partial order follows from 2.10.

[⊥] is the smallest element. In fact ⊥ → α is a tautology for any α. Fromthe fact α → > is a tautology it follows that [>] is the greatest element.

For given α and β it follows from 2.11 that [α ∧ β] is the greatest lowerbound of [α] and [β].

Finally lemma¥

2.2 Basics of Nonmonotonic Logic

2.2.1 What is nonmonotonic logic?

Make some remarks about the nature of nonmonotonic logic. Start from au-toepistemic logic. Classical logic is monotonic. Given a set Σ of assumptionsand a formula α such that Σ ` α. If we add more assumptions to Σ so asto get Σ∗ we will still have Σ∗ ` α. ’More information’ cannot invalidate in-ferences drawn on the basis of ’less information’. This is what monotonicity

Page 25: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.2. BASICS OF NONMONOTONIC LOGIC 25

means. In recent decades, logicians have studied modes of reasoning that donot have this property. In these so-called non-monotonic logics ’old inferences’may be invalidated by ’new information’. What reason can there be for thisphenomenon? One reason may be incomplete information. This is for instancethe case in commonsense reasoning. If we view a common sense reasoner’s ac-tivity as ’jumping to conclusions’ on the basis of certain ’pieces of information’,it seems quite natural that certain of his conclusions cannot be maintained inthe light of additional information.

Another source of non-monotonicity is perfect introspection of the (reason-ing) agent. Imagine a reasoner, i.e. an agent who can infer propositions fromsets of assumptions. Suppose, moreover, this reasoner has an additional ability.Namely assume that whenever he can, in his system of reasoning, infer a certainproposition α from a certain set Σ of assumptions, he can, in the same system,infer the proposition saying ”I can infer α” denoted by Iα and whenever hecannot infer α from Σ he can infer the proposition ”I cannot infer α”, i.e. ¬Iα.The former ability is called positive introspection, the latter is called negativeintrospection. Assume a consistent agent having both abilities. We give a (stillslightly informal) argument to the effect that such a reasoner cannot be mono-tonic. So assume he is monotonic. Given a set Σ of assumtions and let α be aproposition the reasoner cannot infer from Σ). By negative introspection he canthen infer ¬Iα. Aassume that α is consistent with Σ and can be consistentlyadded to Σ. Then, since he is assumed to be monotonic, he can infer α from αfrom Σ ∪ α and thus by (positive) introspection he can infer Iα from the en-larged set of assumtions. Since he is assumed to be monotonic, he can still infer¬Iα. But this would mean that he is inconsistent. It follows that he cannot bemonotonic.

The branch of non-monotonic logic that takes its origin in considerations ofthe above sort is called autoepistemic logic, see for instance [1] or [48]. We willcome back to this in Chapter 9.

2.2.2 Non-monotonicity in quantum mechanics

The reader may, at this point, ask the question why we want to considernon-monotonic logics in our study of quantum logic. The answer is that non-monotonicity is, from the logical point of view, an essential feature of quantummechanics. We encounter non-monotonic (logical) systems in nature so to speak.This has to do with Heisenberg’s famous Uncertainty Principle, more generallythe uncertainty relations we have in quantum mechanics. What are uncertaintyrelations? We cannot, at this stage, explain this quantitatively. But, qualita-tively, it means the following. Consider, say, the electron of a hydrogen atomand assume a certain physical quantity of this electron, say its (total) energy Eis measured. Through measurement we get a certain value, say µ. Viewing ameasurement as a sort of proof we then have ’proved’ the proposition E = µ.Now assume we measure the position P of the electron. Again, we get a value,say λ, and we have proved the proposition P = λ. We are now, used to classi-cal physics and classical logic as we are, inclined to say that we now know the

Page 26: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

26 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

energy and the position of the electron and any subsequent measurement of theenergy of the electron could only confirm the proposition E = µ and P = λ. Itis an empirical and perhaps slightly surprising fact, however, that this is not thecase. A subsequent measurement of the energy of the electron will even withcertainty yield a value different from µ. The measurement of position invalidatesthe result of the measurement of energy. This is essentially what we mean bysaying that there exists an uncertainty relation between energy and position.From the point of view of logic this is non-monotonicity.

2.2.3 Inference operations and consequence relations

Here we introduce the concept of an inference operation and as a special casethat of a consequence relation. This is routine and still needs to be done.

We state some minimal condition a consequence relation is supposed to sat-isfy. The following are the minimal conditions as suggested by Gabbay in [?].The reader may verify that the classical consequence relation ` or equivalently|= defined above in fact satisfies these conditions.

Reflexivityα |∼ α

Cutα ∧ β |∼ γ, α |∼ βα |∼ γ

Restricted Monotonicityα |∼ β, α |∼ γα ∧ β |∼ γ

In the paper by Kraus–Lehmann–Magidor (in short KLM , see [34], these threeconditions are, as suggested by Gabbay in [?], considered to be the minimalconditions a respectable consequence relation should satisfy.As observed in the KLM paper, any consequence relation satisfying the aboveconditions has the following property AND:

α |∼ β, α |∼ γα |∼ β ∧ γ

For a given consequence relation |∼ define

α ≡ β iff α |∼ β and β |∼ α

2.2.4 The concept of a GKLM model

The semantics of consequence relations has its origin in investigations on thesemantics of conditionals. The essential step in developing semantics of such asort is the definition of a model for a consequence relation rather than a modelfor a formula. Having accomplished this is one of the merits of the seminal

Page 27: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

2.2. BASICS OF NONMONOTONIC LOGIC 27

paper by Kraus-Lehmann- Magidor [34]. In the sequel we give a definition dueto Gabbay [18] which is a slight generalisation of the definition given in theKLM paper.

Definition 2.12 • A Scott model for Fml is any function s : Fml →0, 1.

• A GKLM (Generalised Kraus–Lehmann–Magidor) model is a structureof the form 〈S, <, l〉, where S is a non-empty set, < is a binary relationon S and l is a function associating with each t ∈ S a set of Scott modelsl(t). The model is required to satisfy the smoothness condition stated inthe next definition.

Definition 2.13 Let M = 〈S,<, l〉 be a structure as described in the last defi-nition. Let t ∈ S and α a formula. Then define the satisfaction relation t |= αas follows:

• t |= α iff for all s ∈ l(t) we have s(α) = 1

• Let A ⊂ S. We say that t is <-minimal in A iff for all t′ ∈ A such thatt′ < t we have t′ = t. We say that A is smooth iff for every t ∈ A, eithert is minimal in A or for some s ∈ A, s < t and s is minimal in A.

• Let [α] = t ∈ S | t |= α. We say that M is smooth iff for all α, [α] issmooth.

• For a smooth model M we define the consequence relation |∼M as follows:α |∼M β iff for all t minimal in [α], we have t |= β.

• Given a consequence relation |∼ and a smooth model M. We say M is amodel for |∼ iff |∼=|∼M.

Page 28: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

28 CHAPTER 2. A CRASH COURSE IN LOGIC

Page 29: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 3

Some Hilbert Space Theory

Abstract:. In order to understand the idea of quantum logic it is indispens-able to have a basic knowledge of quantum mechanics and its mathematicalformalism. Moreover, the reader needs such a basic knowledge in order to un-derstand our interpretation of the Birkhoff-von Neumann paper, which initiatedquantum logic. We therefore give an introduction to this in this chapter. Wedefine the core concept of the mathematical formalism, namely the concept of aHilbert space and develop elementary Hilbert space theory. In this we assumesome familiarity with basic concepts of linear algebra on the part of the reader.In particular, we assume the reader to be familiar with the concept of a vectorspace, linear independence,... We also expect the reader to be familiar withelementary topological concepts such as metric space, continuity, convergence...We introduce and study the lattice of closed subspaces, equivalently the lat-tice of projections, of a Hilbert space, which constitutes the dominant algebraicstructure in quantum logic. On this we will build heavily in later chapters. ¥

3.1 The Concept of a Hilbert Space

In this chapter we first summarise some well known material from Hilbert spacetheory. In this we omit the proofs with few exceptions. The reader may findthe proofs in most textbooks on Functional Analysis. We report most of thematerial without explicitly formulating definitions or theorems. It’s only whenwe want to highlight certain concepts or results that we choose the explicitformulation as a definition or a theorem. Not all of the things we say aboutHilbert spaces are actually needed in the subsequent chapters, but all of theresults that are actually needed are included.

We also present an unpublished result by the authors on the characterisationof classical Hilbert lattices which will prove useful in our considerations later inthe book.

The core mathematical structure of the formalism of quantum mechanics isthat of a Hilbert space.

29

Page 30: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

30 CHAPTER 3. SOME HILBERT SPACE THEORY

Definition 3.1 Let H be a vector space over the real or the complex numbersor the quaternions and let ‖ .. ‖ H → [, [0∞)] be a function such that

• ‖ x ‖= 0 iff x = 0

• ‖λx‖ = |λ|‖x‖• ‖x + y‖ ≤ ‖x‖+ ‖y‖

Then we say that H is a normed space with norm ‖..‖

Given a normed space H with norm ‖..‖, we can define a metric d in anatural way, namely by d(x, y) = ‖x − y‖. Thus a normed (linear) space is ametric space in a natural way.

We thus have the topological concepts of continuity, Cauchy-sequence... Letus just recall the definition of a Cauchy-sequence. Let M be a metric space andlet xnn∈N be a sequence in M . We say that xnn∈N is a Cauchy-sequence if thefollowing holds. For any ε > 0 there exists an n0 such that for any n,m > n0

we have d(xn − xm) < ε.We call a metric space M complete if every Cauchy sequence in M converges.

A complete normed space is called a Banach space.

Definition 3.2 Let H be a vector space over scalar (skew) fields of the realor the complex numbers or the quaternions. A mapping 〈...〉 → from H ×Hinto the scalar (skew) field is called an inner (scalar) product, if the followingconditions are satisfied:

• 〈x1 + x2, y〉 = 〈x1, y〉+ 〈x2, y〉• 〈λx, y〉 = λ〈x, y〉• 〈x, y〉 = 〈y, x〉• 〈x, x〉 ≥ 0

• 〈x, x〉 = 0 iff x = 0 if 〈...〉 is an inner product we call 〈H, 〈...〉 〉 (or in abuseof notation just H) an inner product space (synonymously a Pre-Hilbertspace).

We get as a consequence that

〈x, y1 + y2〉 = 〈x, y1 + y2〉〈x, λy〉 = λ〈x, y〉The following is the Cauchy-Schwarz inequality. This important inequality

will not be explicitly used in the sequel. We mention it because it basic in thesense that it plays an important part in the proofs of the theorems mentioned(not proved) in the sequel.

Let H be an inner product space. Then

• | 〈x, y〉 |2 ≤ 〈x, x〉〈y, y〉

Page 31: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

3.2. CLOSED SUBSPACES AND PROJECTIONS IN HILBERT SPACE 31

we have equality iff x and y are linearly dependent.We call two elements x and y of an inner product space orthogonal if <

x, y >= 0. We write x⊥y.Note that in inner product spaces we have the Pythagorean theorem: If x

and y are orthogonal, then ‖ x ‖2 + ‖ y ‖2 = ‖ x + y ‖2.

Definition 3.3 We call an inner product space a Hilbert space if it is completeas a normed space. Equivalently we may say that an inner product space iscalled a Hilbert space if it is a Banach space.

The reader should note that we did not impose any condition on the dimen-sion of a Hilbert space although, historically, the concept arose in connectionwith infinite dimensional vector spaces. In fact, the most interesting exam-ples of Hilbert spaces in Functional Analysis are infinite-dimensional functionspaces. We thus consider both finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces and infinite-dimensionl Hilbert spaces. There are, however, marked differences between thefinite-dimensional and the infinite-dimensional case which should be kept inmind.

It is for instance true that any finite-dimensional inner product space isa Hilbert space, i.e. complete as a normed space. This does not hold in theinfinite- dimensional case. There exist infinite-dimensional inner product spacesthat are not complete. Other peculiarities of infinite-dimensional Hilbert spacesconcern the role of subspaces and that of bases.

3.2 Closed subspaces and projections in Hilbertspace

Given any vector space H and S ⊂ H. Then we say that S is a subspace of H(in the sense of Linear Algebra) if 0 ∈ S and if x, y ∈ S then λx + µy ∈ S forany scalars λ and µ.

Given a finite-dimensional inner product space 〈H, 〈〉〉 and let S be a sub-space of H. If we then restrict the inner product to S and denote its restrictionagain by 〈〉 then 〈S, 〈〉〉 is again a Hilbert space. We cannot expect this to holdin the infinite dimensional case because we cannot take for granted that 〈S, 〈〉〉is complete. If, however, we require S to be closed then 〈S, 〈〉 is in fact a Hilbertspace. It is the closed subspaces that in the infinite dimensional case play, essen-tially, the role of subspaces in the finite-dimensional case. Let us take a closerlook at closed subspaces of a Hilbert space. To be precise, we call a subset S ofa Hilbert space a closed subspace if S is a subspace in the sense of linear algebraand if S is a closed set in the norm topology.

For a given subset S of a Hilbert space we denote its closure, i.e. the smallestclosed set containing S, by S. It is easily seen that for any subspace S its closureS is a closed subspace. For two (not necessarily closed) subspaces A and B wedenote by A + B the smallest (not necessarily closed) subspace containing Aand B. For two closed subspaces A and B denote by A ∨B the smallest closed

Page 32: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

32 CHAPTER 3. SOME HILBERT SPACE THEORY

subspace containing A and B. We clearly have A + B ⊂ A ∨B. We will see inthat this may be be a proper inclusion. Call two subspaces A and B orthogonalif for any x ∈ A and y ∈ B we have x⊥y.

For any subspace A define its orthogonal complement S⊥ by

A⊥ =: x ∈ H | (∀y ∈ A)x⊥y One can then prove that A is again a subspace.If A is closed so is A = A⊥. Moreover, we have that A is a closed subspace iffA = A⊥

Theorem 3.1 Let A be a closed subspace of the Hilbert space H and x ∈ H.Then x has a unique decomposition x = y + z with y ∈ A and z ∈ A⊥.

Given a closed subspace A and x ∈ H. Let x = y + z the unique decomposi-tion of x as above. Then we call y the projection of x onto A. We denote, sincethere is no confusion, the mapping assigning to every x ∈ H its projection ontoA again by A. We call these mappings projections. Note that any projection Ais idempotent, A2 = A.

Theorem 3.2 (Projection Theorem) Let H be a Hilbert Space, x ∈ H andA be a closed subspace of H. Then there exists a unique y ∈ A such thatd(x, y) = infz∈A d(x, z) and we have Ax = y.

3.3 Orthonormal systems and the Fourier ex-pansion

Recall from linear algebra that any vector space and thus any Hilbert space -finite dimensional or not- admits a basis. A basis in the sense of linear algebra isa family of linearly independent vectors that spans the whole space. Every vectorhas then a unique representation as a linear combination of basis vectors. In thecase of infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces it is not the bases in the sense of linearalgebra that play the dominant role but other systems, which are in general notbases in the sense of linear algebra. These systems are called orthonormal bases.Their main characteristic is that every vector has a (unique) ’Fourier expansion’in terms of such systems. In this subsection we summarise the main propertiesof orthonormal bases of a Hilbert space.

Definition 3.4 Let S ⊂ H. We call S an orthonormal system if every x ∈ Shas norm 1, i.e. ‖ x ‖= 1, and any two distinct elements x and y are orthogonal.We call an orthonormal system S an orthonormal basis if it is maximal in thesense that for any orthonormal system T such that S ⊂ T we have S = T .

Using Zorn’s lemma one can prove that every Hilbert space and thus everyclosed subspace of a Hilbert space possesses an orthonormal basis. Moreover,it can be proved that any two orthonormal bases have the same cardinality. AHilbert space having countable orthonormal bases is called separable.

Page 33: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

3.3. ORTHONORMAL SYSTEMS AND THE FOURIER EXPANSION 33

The reader should note that, in the infinite-dimensional case, an orthonormalbasis need not be a basis for the Hilbert space in the sense of linear algebra.It is a linearly independent set of elements which, however, need not (linearly)span the whole space. We will see shortly, however, that for any orthonormalbasis S every vector of the Hilbert space has a ’Fourier expansion’ in terms ofS which in the finite-dimensional case reduces to a linear combination of theelements of S.

We also have, in the infinite-dimensional case, the following analogy with thefinite-dimensional case. It is well known that given a finite-dimensional Hilbertspace and any linearly independent family x1, ...xn there exists an orthonormalset y1, ...yn spanning the same space. Generally, given any countable linearlyindependent set of vectors T = xn, n ∈ N we may construct an orthonormalbasis S such that the closures of the subspaces spanned by T nd S coincide.The reader may find this in the textbooks as the ’Gram-Schmidt construction’.

As already mentioned, the chief function of an orthonormal basis of Hilbertspace H consists in the fact that any x ∈ H has a Fourier expansion in termsof this orthonormal basis. We need, at this point, reflect on two things. First’Fourier series’ are ’infinite sums’. Second, not every Hilbert space is separable,i.e. this means that orthonormal bases need be countable, if we do not wantto restrict ourselves to separable Hilbert spaces, we will encounter infinite sumswith non-denumerable index sets. In the next definition we explain what wemean by

Definition 3.5 Let H be a normed space with norm ‖‖. Let x1, x2, ... be count-able sequence of elements of H. Then we say the series

Proposition 3.1 Let en, n ∈ N be a countable orthonormal system and x ∈H. Then we have∑ |< x, en >|2 ≤ ‖ x ‖2

Note that the series above converges absolutely. Rearranging terms neitheraffects convergence nor the limit.

The above inequality is known as Bessel’s inequality. Bessel’s inequality hasthe following interesting consequence.

Corollary 3.1 Given any orthonormal system S and x ∈ H. Then Sx =: e ∈S |< x, e > 6= 0 is at most countable.

This can be seen as follows. Consider the sets Tx,n =: e ∈ S ||< x, e >|≥ 1/n.By Bessel’s inequality these sets are finite and thus T =

⋃n∈N Sx,n is finite or

countable.Let us now recall the concept of convergence in the norm. Given a normed

space H with norm ‖‖ ad a sequence of vectors xn, n = 1, 2.... We say the seriesnxn converges in the norm to x, in symols x =∞n xn if for any ε < 0 there existsan n0 such that ‖ x−∑∞

n=1 xn ‖< ε for all n ≥ n0.The significance of [?] is that for any orthornomal system S we can make

sense of a series of the form∑

e∈S < x, e > e. It’s always a ’countable’ sum.

Page 34: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

34 CHAPTER 3. SOME HILBERT SPACE THEORY

Theorem 3.3 Let S be an orthonormal basis and suppose that∑ | αe |2 < ∞

with αe =< x, e > for all e ∈ S. Note again that this series coverges absolutely.Then∑

e∈S αee converges absolutely (in the norm) with limit x.

Theorem 3.4 Let S ⊂ H be an orthonormal system. Then there exists anorthonormal basis T such that S ⊂ T .

The following conditions are equivalent:

• (i) S is an orthonormal basis.

• (ii) If x ∈ H is orthogonal to S then x = 0.

• (iii) H is the closure of the subspace spanned by S, S=linS

• (iv) Any x ∈ H has a Fourier expansion in therms of S. This means thatx =

∑e∈S < x, e > e.

• (iv) For any x, y ∈ H, < x, y >=∑

x∈S < x, e >< e, y >

As to the ’infinite sums’ in the above theorem note that these series areactually ’countable’ sums since by [?] only countably many members are non-zero. Moreover these series are invariant under any permutation of the index setin the sense that ’rearranging’ terms neither affects convergence nor the limitof the series. Call such series absolutely convergent.

Theorem 3.5 Let S be an orthonormal system. Then for any x the series∑e∈S < x, e > e converges absolutely to the orthogonal projection of x on linS.

As a consequence we have the following useful observation. Given an or-thonormal system xii∈I and let A be the smallest closed subspace containingit, then the elements of A are precisely those having the form

∑i∈I αixi with∑

i∈I | αi |2 < ∞.It can be proved that if two closed subspaces A and B of a Hilbert space are

orthogonal, then A + B is closed. Generally, however, this is not true.We now give an example for two closed subspaces A and B of an infinite

dimensional Hilbert space such that A + B 6= A ∨B. For this first note that inan infinite dimensional Hilbert space we may find two orthonormal sequencesxnn∈N and ymm∈N such that xn⊥ym. In the construction below we closely fol-low Halmos’ book [26]. Consider the sequence zn =: cos(1/n)xn + sin(1/n)yn.By the Pythagorean theorem we have ‖ zn ‖2 = cos2(1/n)+sin2(1/n)01. More-over, a straightforward calculation shows < zn, zm > =0forn 6= m. Thusthe sequence zn is an orthonormal system. Let A and B be the smallestclosed subspace containing xn and zn respectively. Since cos(1/n) 6= 0 wehave yn ∈ A + B. Now note that

∑∞n=1 sin2(1/n) < ∞. By ? y =

∑∞i=1

makes sense and is an element of A ∨ B. We now prove that y is not inA + B. Suppose y ∈ A + B. Then we would have y = x + z with x ∈ Aand z ∈ B. Using the fact that < zn, ym >= δnm we get sin /1/m) =<

Page 35: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

3.4. MORE LATTICE THEORY 35

y, ym >=< x + z, ym >=< z, ym >=<∑∞

i=1 < z, zn >< zn, ym >=< z, zm ><zm, ym >=< z, zm > sin(1/m). It would follow that for all m < z, zm >= 1,which contradicts the fact that the sequence of Fourier coefficients < z, zm >tendstozero.Wehavethereforefoundaysuchthaty ∈ A ∨B but not y ∈ A + B.

The above example may also serve as an example of a subspace of an infinitedimensional Hilbert space which is not closed.

3.4 More Lattice Theory

Definition 3.6 The lattice L is called modular if the modular condition (MC)holds:

If A ≤ B then A ∨ (B ∧ C) = (A ∨B) ∧ (A ∨ C)

If A ≤ B then A ∨ B = B and thus the modular condition is equivalent to thefollowing:

If A ≤ B then A ∨ (B ∧ C) = B ∧ (A ∨ C)

Definition 3.7 An orthocomplemented lattice is called an orthomodular latticeif the orthomodular condition (OMC) holds: If A ≤ B and A⊥ ≤ C then A ∨(B ∧ C) = (A ∨B) ∧ (A ∨ C) In fact, in this case we have A ∨ (B ∧ C) = B

There are various equivalent definitions of orthomodularity, see for instanceRedei’s book [54]

The following version will be of use later in the book.

Proposition 3.2 An orthocomplemented lattice is orthomodular iff A ≤ B im-plies B = A ∨ (A⊥ ∧B).

Note that distributivity implies modularity and modularity implies ortho-modularity. The converse implications do not hold.

We write A < B for A ≤ B and A 6= B.

Definition 3.8 Given any lattice L and A, B ∈ L. We say that B covers A ifA < B and A < C < B is satisfied by no C.

An element A ∈ L is called an atom if it covers 0. L is called atomic if forany B ∈ L there exists an atom A such that AB. L is called atomistic if anyelement B is equal to the least upper bound of those atoms A satisfying A ≤ B.We say that L has the covering property if the following holds. Let P be anatom and A ∈ L. Then A ∨ P covers A. We say that A commutes with B ifA = (A ∧ B) ∨ (A ∧ B⊥). Call the set of all elements of L commuting with allothers the center of L. If the center of L consists of 0 and 1 only we call Lirreducible.

Remark: In the lattice of projections of a Hilbert space two projectionscommute in the sense above iff they commute as operators.

Page 36: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

36 CHAPTER 3. SOME HILBERT SPACE THEORY

Definition 3.9 Given any poset P we may define the notion of a chain andthat of the length of a chain in a straightforward way. We then define the heightof P denoted by h(P ) as the supremum over the lengths of all chains of P minus1.

Proposition 3.3 In an orthocomplemented lattice we have the de Morgan rules:

• (∨

i A⊥i)) =∧

Aibot

• (∧

i A⊥i)) =∨

Ai⊥

In the sequel we will use the term ’polynomial’. For this note that ∧ and ∨,⊥ may be viewed as algebraic operations. The term ’polynomial’ may then bedefined as usual in algebra. By a (lattice) conditional we mean a polynomialin two variables. For instance, given two elements A and B of an orthocomple-mented lattice, then the polynomial S(A,B) =: A⊥∨B represents a conditional,namely ’material implication’.

Lemma 3.1 Let L be an orthocomplemented lattice. Suppose there exists aconditional S(A,B) satisfying the following condition.

A ∧ C ≤ B iff C ≤ S(A, B

Then L is a Boolean algebra.

Proof.Fr the sake of convenience we write A ; B for S(A, B). Given any elements

A,B,C. We need to show that ((A ∨B) ∧ C) = (A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ C). For this itsuffices to show that ((A ∧B) ∨ C) ≤ (A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ C). We have

A ∧ C) ≤ (A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ C)

and

(B ∧ C) ≤ (A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ C)

Using the condition on S(A,B) we obtain

A ≤ (C ; ((A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ C)))

and

B ≤ (C ; ((A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ C)))

Hence

(A ∨B) ≤ ((C ; ((A ∧ C) ∨ (B ∧ C)))

Applying the condition on S(A,B) in the other direction we get

Page 37: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

3.4. MORE LATTICE THEORY 37

(A ∨B) ∧ C ≤ (A ∨B) ∧ (A ∨B)

This is what we wanted to prove.¥

Theorem 3.6 (Mittelstaedt) Let L = 〈L,≤,⊥ 〉 be an orthocomplementedlattice. Then L is orthomodular if there exists a conditional S(A,B) such thatthe following conditions are satisfied.

(i) A ∧ S(A,B) ≤ B

(ii) A ∧ C ≤ B implies A⊥ ∨ (A ∧ C) ≤ S(A, B)

A conditional satisfying the above conditions is unique, namely

S(A,B) = A⊥ ∨ (A ∧B).

L is a Boolean algebra if the above conditions are satisfied by ’material implica-tion’, i.e. S(A,B) = A⊥ ∨B.

We denote A⊥ ∨ (A ∧B) by A ;s B.

Proof. Assume there exists a conditional satisfying (i) and (ii). We need toshow that L is orthomodular. So let B ≤ A and C ≤ A⊥. Then we have

B = B ∧A ≤ A⊥ ∨ (A ∧B) = A ;s B)

Moreover we have

C ≤ A⊥ ≤ A⊥ ∨ (A ∧B) = A ;s B

Hence

B ∨ C ≤ A ;s B

and thus

A ∧ (B ∨ C) ≤ A ∧ (A ;s B)

By condition (i) we have

A ∧ (A ;s B) ≤ B

It follows that

A ∧ (B ∨ C) ≤ B

Page 38: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

38 CHAPTER 3. SOME HILBERT SPACE THEORY

and by the definition of orthomodularity this means that L is orthomodular.For the proof of uniqueness let S′(A,B) be any conditional satisfying (i)

and (ii). We can then assume orthomodularity of L. Putting C = B weget by (ii) that A ;s B ≤ S′(A, B). Since S′(A, B) satisfies (i) it follows thatA∧S′(A,B) ≤ (A∧B) ≤ A⊥∨(A∧B) = A ;s B. Hence A⊥∨(A∧S′(A,B)) ≤A ;s B). Considering that A⊥ ≤ S′(A,B) we have by orthomodularity thatA⊥ ∨ (A ∧ S′(A,B)) = S′(A,B). It follows that S′(A,B) ≤ A ;s B. S′(A, B)and A ;s B are thus equal.

We still need to prove that if conditions (i) and (ii) are satisfied by S(A,B) =:A⊥ ∨B, L is a Boolean algebra. For this we have to verify the condition in thepreceding lemma. First note that in this case A⊥ ∨(A ∧ B) = A⊥ ∨ B. Soassume A ∧ B ≤ C. Then it follows from condition (ii) of this theorem thatA⊥ ∨ C ≤ A⊥ ∨ B. Hence C ≤ A⊥ ∨ B. For the other direction assumeC ≤ A⊥ ∨B. Then we have (A∧C) ≤ A∧ (A⊥ ∨B). By condition (i) we haveA ∧ (A⊥ ∨B) ≤ B. Thus (A ∧ C) ≤ B. This completes the proof.

¥

3.5 The lattice of closed subspaces and projec-tions of an orthomodular space

In this section we do not restrict ourselves to Hilbert spaces. Rather we alwayshave in mind the more general case of an orthomodular space. The conceptof an orthomodular space is more general than that of a Hilbert space, but itsuffices for many purposes. Unless explicitly mentioned otherwise the spacesunder consideration in this section are orthomodular spaces.

Definition 3.10 Let K be a (not necessarily commutative) field with an invo-lution τ , i.e. a function τ : K → K such that

τ(a + b) = τ(a) + τ(b),τ(ab) = τ(b)τ(a), ττ(a) = a

Now, let H be a vector space over K and 〈〉 : H ×H → K be a Hermitian formon H, i.e. 〈〉 satisfies

〈ax + by, z〉 = a〈x, z〉+ b〈y, z〉

〈z, ax + by〉 = 〈z, x〉τ(a) + 〈z, y〉τ(b)

〈x, z〉 = τ(〈z, x〉)

then call the pair 〈H, 〈〉〉 a Hermitian space. Call 〈〉 anisotropic iff

〈x, x〉 = 0 implies x = 0

Define the concepts of orthogonality of vectors and the orthogonal comple-ment U⊥ of a subspace U as in the case of Hilbert spaces. Call a subspace Uclosed iff U = U⊥.

Page 39: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

3.5. THE LATTICE OF CLOSED SUBSPACES AND PROJECTIONS OF AN ORTHOMODULAR SPACE39

Definition 3.11 Call a Hermitian space 〈H, 〈〉〉 an orthomodular space iff forevery closed subspace U we have

H = U ⊕ U⊥

Every Hilbert space H is an orthomodular space. A subspace of H is closedin the sense of the topology of Hilbert space iff it is closed in the sense of anorthomodular space as defined above.

We denote the set of closed subspaces of H as Sub(H). It is obvious thatset inclusion is a partial order on Sub(H). Given M,N ∈ Sub(H), then M ∩Nis the greatest lower bound of M and N . The lowest upper bound of N and Mdenoted by M ∨N is given by the smallest closed subspace containing M andN . Orthogonal complement formation is an orthocomplementation of Sub(H).The zero space is the null element of the lattice and H is the unit element.Sub(H) is thus an orthocomplemented lattice.

We can, as in the case of a Hilbert space, associate a projection with everyclosed subspace. The set of projections forms, in a natural way, an orthocom-plemented lattice (ortho)- isomorphic to the lattice of closed subspaces. Anorthoisomorphism between orthocomplemented lattices is a bijctive mappingrespection all ’latice operations’ including orthocomplementation. In the sequelwe mean ortho-isomorhism (automorphism) whenever we use the term isomor-phism (automorphism).

The following proposition generalises an observation made by Hardegree in[44]. in connection with Hilbert spaces.

Proposition 3.4 Let H be an orthomodular space, x ∈ H, A,B ∈ Sub(H).Then Ax ∈ B iff x ∈ A⊥ ∨ (A ∧B)

Proof. First note that the closed subspaces A⊥ and A ∧ B are orthogonal.Then we have A⊥ ∨ (A ∧B = A⊥ ⊕ (A ∧B).

For the direction from left to right let x = y+z be the unique decompositionof x with respect to A and A⊥, i.e. y ∈ A and z ∈ A⊥. We have Ax = y. Thehypothesis says that y ∈ B. Thus y ∈ A∧B. It follows that x ∈ A⊥ ⊕ (A∧B).

For the direction from right to left observe A⊥ ⊕ (A ∧B) is again an ortho-modular space with the Hermitian form properly restricted. We have thus, inaddition to the above decomposition, a decomposition x = y1 + z1 with y1 ∈ Aand z1 ∈ A ∧B. Since the decomposition is unique we have y = y1 and z = z1.It follows that Ax = y = y1 ∈ B. ¥

We call, for historical reasons, a lattice a Hilbert lattice if it is isomomorphicto the lattice of closed subpaces of an orthomodular space.

Theorem 3.7 A Hilbert lattice is an atomistic, complete, orthomodular irre-ducible lattice having the covering property.

The following theorem is Piron’s Representation Theorem

Page 40: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

40 CHAPTER 3. SOME HILBERT SPACE THEORY

Theorem 3.8 (Piron) An ortholattice L of height ≥ 4 is a Hilbert lattice iff itis atomistic, complete, irreducible, orthomodular and it has the covering prop-erty.

Theorem 3.9 (Amemiah-Araki) A Hilbert H is finite dimensional iff Sub(H)is modular.

It is an important fact that for any infinite-dimensional Hilbert space H,Sub(H) is orthomodular but not modular.

3.6 Characterising classical Hilbert lattices

In quantum mechanics we are (primarily) concerned with infinite-dimensionalHilbert spaces. We define, for historical reasons, a classical Hilbert lattice to bea lattice isomorphic to the lattice of closed subspaces of an infinite - dimensionalHilbert space. Recall that we have already defined a Hilbert lattice to be a latticeisomorphic to the lattice of closed subspaces of some orthomodular space. Forthese lattices we have Piron’s representation theorem which characterises Hilbertlattices of height at least 4.

In this section we characterise classical Hilbert lattices among ortholattices.For this purpose we need, apart from Piron’s theorem, three deep theorems ofmodern Hilbert space theory, namely the theorems of Soler, Wigner and Mayet,which we state below.

In his pionering paper [36] Keller settled a long standing question, namely thequestion whether every infinite dimensional orthomodular space was already aHilbert space. Keller’s ingenious construction of a counter example settled thequestion in the negative. This, however, posed another problem, namely theproblem of characterising those orthomodular spaces that are in fact Hilbertspaces. This problem was solved by Maria Pia Soler in [61].

Theorem 3.10 (Soler) Let 〈H, 〈〉〉 be an orthomodular space over K and letc ∈ K. Suppose there exists an infinite family (xi)i∈I of pairwise orthogonalelements of H such that for all i ∈ I, 〈xi, xi〉 = c. Then K must be the (skew-)field of the real numbers,the complex numbers or quaternions and H is an infinite- dimensional Hilbert space.

Definition 3.12 Let H1 and H2 be two orthomodular spaces and σ : H1 →H2 be a bijective map. We say that σ is a semiunitary map iff the followingconditons are satisfied.

• For any x, y ∈ H1, σ(x + y) = σ(x) + σ(y).

• There exists an automorphism ρ of K such that, for any λ ∈ K and anyx ∈ H1, we have σ(λx) = ρ(λ) (σx).

• There exists λσ ∈ K such that, for any x, y ∈ H1, we have 〈σ(x), σ(y)〉 =ρ(〈x, y〉)λσ.

Page 41: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

3.6. CHARACTERISING CLASSICAL HILBERT LATTICES 41

If, moreover, we have ρ = idK and λσ = 1, we say that σ is unitary.

Theorem 3.11 (Wigner) Let H1 and H2 be orthomodular spaces of dimen-sion at least 3. Then every ortholattice isomorphism f : Sub(H1) → Sub(H2)is induced by some semiunitary map.

We need the following result by Mayet which, essentially, is a consequence ofWigner’s theorem.

Theorem 3.12 (Mayet) Let H be an orthomodular space of dimension at least3 and let X ∈ Sub(H) of dimension at least 2. Let f be an automorphism ofSub(H) whose restriction to [0, X] is the identical map. Then there exists aunique unitary operator σ on H inducing f such that the restriction of σ to Xis the identical map.

Soler’s theorem characterises Hilbert spaces among orthomodular spaces.We are interested in a charactersation of classical Hilbert lattices Hilbert latticesamong ortholattices.

The characterisation we give is in terms of a symmetry property.For a given ortholattice L we call two atoms σ1 and σ2 orthogonal if σ1 ≤ σ⊥2 .

This relation is readily seen to be symmetric.

Definition 3.13 Let L be a complete ortholattice and let ∆ = (σi)i∈I be an in-finite pairwise orthogonal family of atoms of L. We say that L satisfies the sym-metry property (synonymously: is symmetric) with respect to ∆ iff the followingholds. For any permutation f : I → I there exists an ortholattice automorphismρf of L with the following properties.

• ρf extends f , i.e. ρf (σi) = σf(i)) for any i ∈ I.

• If the set J of those elements of I which are left fixed by f is non-empty,ρf induces the identical map on [0, A], where A denotes the least upperbound of the family (σj)j∈J .

We say that L is symmetric iff there exists an infinite pairwise orthogonal family∆ of atoms of L such that L is symmetric with respect to ∆.

Theorem 3.13 A Hilbert lattice L is a classical Hilbert lattice iff it is symmet-ric.

Proof: Let us first verify that for a given infinite - dimensional classical Hilbertspace H Sub(H) is symmetric. To see this consider a complete orthonormalsystem (xi)i∈I of H. Then the family of one - dimensional subspaces (〈xi〉)i∈I

is an infinite orthogonal system of Sub(H). Let f : I → I be any permutationof I. Recall that x =

∑i∈I〈x, xi〉xi. Define the map ϕf as follows. For x =∑

i∈I〈x, xi〉xi put ϕf (x) =:∑

i∈I〈x, xf−1(i)〉xi. ϕ is well defined. For any i ∈ Iwe have ϕf (xi) = xf(i). Moreover, ϕf is unitary, since for any x, y ∈ H wehave 〈ϕf (x), ϕf (y)〉 =

∑i∈I〈x, xf−1(i)〉〈y, xf−1(i)〉 =

∑i∈I〈x, xi〉〈y, xi〉 = 〈x, y〉.

Page 42: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

42 CHAPTER 3. SOME HILBERT SPACE THEORY

Suppose i | f(i) = i is non-empty and denote by X the smallest closedsubspace containing xi | f(i) = i. X is the smallest closed subspace containing〈xi〉 | f(i) = i and ϕf induces the identity on X. For the latter claim observethat ϕf induces the identity on the subspace spanned by xi | f(i) = i and andX is the closure of that subspace. Since ϕf is continuous, it induces the identityon X too. ϕf thus induces an ortholattice automorphism ρf on Sub(H) suchthat for any i ∈ I , ρf (〈xi〉) = 〈xf(i)〉. Clearly, ρf induces the identical map on[0, X]. Thus symmetry of Sub(H) is proved.For the other direction note that the symmetry property implies infinite height.It thus suffices by Piron’s Representation Theorem that any orthomodular spaceH such that Sub(H) has the symmetry property is an infinite - dimensionalclassical Hilbert space. So let (〈xi〉)i∈I be an infinite orthogonal family withrespect to which Sub(H) is symmetric. Let i0 ∈ I. For any j ∈ I, i0 6= jconsider the permutation fj of I defined as follows.

fj(i0) = j, fj(j) = i0, fj(i) = i else.

Denote by X the smallest closed closed subspace of X containing 〈xi〉 for alli ∈ I. X is infinite - dimensional. By symmetry there exists an automorphismρj of Sub(H) inducing the identity on [0, X] such that for all i ∈ I, ρj(〈xi〉) =〈xfj(i)〉. So, by Mayet’s theorem, ρj is induced by some unitary map ϕj . Putyj =: ϕj(xi0) for j 6= i0 and yi0 = xi0 . Then, since ϕj is unitary, the family(yj)j∈I is a family as required in Soler’s theorem. It follows by Soler’s theoremthat H must be an infinite - dimensional classical Hilbert space. 2

As a corollary we get the following theorem, which gives another characterisationof Hilbert spaces among orthomodular spaces.

Theorem 3.14 Let 〈H, 〈〉〉 be an orthomodular space over K. Then the follow-ing conditions are equivalent.

• There exists an infinite family (xi)i∈I of pairwise orthogonal elements ofH and a non zero c ∈ H such that for all i ∈ I we have 〈xi, xi〉 = c.

• Sub(H) is symmetric.

• H is an infinite - dimensional classical Hilbert space.

Page 43: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 4

Basics of the Formalism ofQuantum Mechanics

4.1 Some History

It is a common experience among students of physics that their first course onquantum mechanics comes as a sort of shock. In such a course the student isconfronted with a discipline that does not display the pattern he is used to fromthe physical theories he has already mastered such as Newtonian mechanics,electrodynamics, special relativity... The student must swallow the fact thatin contrast to these classical physical theories quantum mechanics is essentiallya mathematical formalism. He is taught how to make use of this formalismin order to calculate certain physical quantities such as the energy levels ofthe electron in the hydrogen atom. The success of the formalism of quantummechanics is unique in the history of science yielding the correct results withunprecedented precision for a vast range of phenomena which were entirelyuntractable in classical physics. This is the reason for the wide spread sloganthat quantum mechanics is the ”most successful physical theory ever”.

However, the student’s question ”Why this formalism? Where does it comefrom?” gets normally, if at all, an evasive and unsatisfactory answer. The plaintruth is that this formalism is the result of guesswork, ingenious guessworkadmittedly.

The first version of the formalism of quantum mechanics became known asmatrix mechanics. The first and already crucial step in this process of guessingwas taken in June 1925 by Werner Heisenberg, a then 23 year old post-doc, in hisfamous paper [28]. Essentially, the discovery was that physical quantities such asenergy, momentum...are to be represented by infinite matrices in such way thatthe possible values a physical quantity can assume are given by the eigenvaluesof the corresponding matrix. The matrices representing physical quantities werenot required to commute and non-commutation of matrices was to be regardedas ”non-simultaneous measurability” of the coresponding physical quantities.

43

Page 44: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

44CHAPTER 4. BASICS OF THE FORMALISM OF QUANTUM MECHANICS

It is interesting to note that Heisenberg did not explicitly use the concept ofa matrix. In fact, he did not even know that concept at the time. The conceptof a matrix was then not part of a mathematician’s standard background letalone a physicist’s. The technical tools used in the paper were somehow vagueas a sort of ’schemata of numbers’ that are multiplied in a way reminiscentof the multiplication of Fourier series. It was Heisenberg’s teacher Max Bornwho, after Heisenberg’s paper had appeared, realised that these mathematicalschemata were actually (infinite) matrices and Heisenberg’s way of combiningthem was actually matrix multiplication. In the joint paper [7] by Born andJordan, which appeared only a few months after Heisenberg’s paper, the firstprecise account of matrix mechanics was given for systems with one degree offreedom. In particular it contains the first mathematically precise statement ofHeisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle: If P is the matrix representing the positionof a particle and Q is the matrix representing its momentum we have

PQ−QP = h/πi

In the subsequent classic paper by Born-Heisenberg-Jordan [6] the formalismof matrix mechanics was fully established. The concept of a Hilbert space,however, still had no place in this. This had to wait for John von Neumann’swork in the late twenties, see [62], [63] and in particular his classic book [64]of 1932 in which the Hilbert space formalism of quantum mechnics received itsfinal elegant shape.

It is interesting that similar guesswork led to Schrodinger’s wavemechanicswhich later on was proved to be equivalent to matrix mechanics.

In 1926 Erwin Schrodinger published his famous paper [58], which, essen-tially earned him the Nobel Prize as did Heisenberg’s paper [28] for Heisenberg.In this paper he claimed and proved to have found a (partial) differential equa-tion with a remarkable property. This differential equation has become knownas the Schrodinger equation, which nowadays is probably the mnost famousequation of physics. And what was so remarkable about it? Well, the claimSchrodinger made and proved was that his equation had square integrable solu-tions exactly for those eigenvalues that correspond to the experimentally foundenergy levels which the electron in the hydrogen atom can assume. This is allSchrodinger claimed and proved. The solution of Schrodinger’s equation usuallydenoted by Ψ(x, y, z) is (in the stationary case) a complex valued functions ofthe three spatial coordinates x, y, z and in the non-stationary case also of time t.Schrodinger had, at the time when his paper appeared, no idea of the physicalmeaning of the function Ψ. The nowadays generally accepted physical inter-pretation given to the Ψ function by Born in [5] is that | ψ |2dxdydz representsthe probability with which the particle can be found in the infinitesimal volumedxdydz. So, according to this interpretation, the solutions of the Schrodingerequation are probability waves. It is an irony of the history of science thatSchrodinger himself never accepted this interpretatiom of the function Ψ.

To summarise, the core of quantum mechanics is a formalism, and this for-malism was guessed. It always works with amazing precision. One of the aims

Page 45: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

4.2. HERMITIAN OPERATORS 45

we pursue in this book is to put logic to good use in order to shed light on thisformalism.

4.2 Hermitian operators

We will see that certain operators on Hilbert spaces play a vital role in the for-malism of quantum mechanics. These operators are called Hermitian operators.

Given a Hilbert space H. Then we call any linear map of H into itself anoperator of H. Let T be an operator of H. We call T bounded if there exists apositive real number c such that for all x ∈ H we have ‖ Tx ‖≤ c ‖ x ‖ .

One can then prove that an operator is bounded iff it is continuous. It canalso be proved that given any bounded operator T there exists a unique operatorT ∗ such hat for all x and y we have 〈Tx, y〉 = 〈x, T ∗y〉. T ∗ is called the adjointof T .

Definition 4.1 Call a bounded operator T Hermitian if T = T ∗. Call a Her-mitian operator T positive definite if for any x ∈ H we have 〈x, Tx〉 ≥ 0. Calla bounded operator T unitary if T is bijective and for any x and y we have〈Tx, Ty〉 = 〈< x, y〉

It can then be proved that a unitary operator may also be defined as abijective Hermitian operator the adjoint of which is its inverse.

Proposition 4.1 Let T be an Hermitian operator. Then

• There exists an orthonormal basis of eigenvectors of T .

• The eigenvalues of T are real numbers.

• All eigenvalues are positive iff T is positive definite.

From this it follows that, given a Hermitian operator T , any vector has aFourier expansion in terms of eigenvectors of T .

Proposition 4.2 Let S and T be Hermitian operators. Then the followingconditions are equivalent

• S and T commute, i.e. ST = TS

• ST is a Hermitian operator.

• There exists an orthonormal basis which is a family of eigenvectorswhichis common to boh S and T .

Page 46: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

46CHAPTER 4. BASICS OF THE FORMALISM OF QUANTUM MECHANICS

4.3 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics

In this section we make the connection between Hilbert space and quantummechanics. We describe the basics of the formalism of quantum mechanics. Inthis we heavily rely on the excellent textbook [9].

Let us first keep in mind the following fact which marks a main difference be-ween classical and quantum physics. Given a physical system S in a certain stateand let A be any physical quantity pertaining to S. Suppose a measurement ofA is performed. On the view of classical mechanics A possesses a certain ’true’value in every state of S and the function of measurement consists in ’findingout’ this value. There is no reason to assume that the process of a measurementshould change the state of the system. In fact, this view is completely alien toclassical mechanics. This view cannot be maintained in quantum mechanics.Rather, according to quantum mechanics, we may in general get a variety ofvalues as a result of measurement each with a certain probabilty which dependson the state of the system. We will state the precise rule for this below as partof the mathematical formalism. In general the state of the system undergoeschange in the process of measurement. Every subsequent measurement of A,however, leaves the state unchanged and yields the same value as the initialmeasurement.

Gven any physical system S. Then, according to quantum mechanics, wecan associate with S a Hilbert space H such in such a way that there is aone-to-one correspondence between the states of S and the rays. i.e. the one-diensional subspaces of H. The physical quantities of S such as energy, angularmomentum...are represented by Hermitian operators of H. If a physical quantityof S is represented by the Hermitian operator T then the values this quantity canassume are precisely the eigenvalues of T , which, as eigenvalues of a Hermitianoperator, are real numbers. Suppose this observable is measured. Then aftermeasurement the system is in a state which is corresponding to an eigenvectorof T , more precisely by the ray spanned by this eigenvector.

The mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics provides the answers tothe follwing questions..

1) How is the state of a physical system S represented mathematically?2) What are the possible outcomes of measurements in a given state?3) How does a given state change in the process of measurement?3)How does the system evolve over time?Let us now present some of the postulates of the formalism of quantum

mechanics.This still needs some extension which can be done routinely

Postulate 1 At any fixed time there exists a one-to-one correspondence betweenthe states of S and the rays of H.

Postulate 2 Every physical quantity A of ScorrespondstoanHermitianoperatorAofH.We call the Hermitian operator A the observable corresponding to A.

Page 47: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

4.3. POSTULATES OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 47

Postulate 3 The possible results of the measurement of a physical quantity Aare eigenvalues of the corresponding observable A.

Note that Hermitian operators may have a continuous set of eigenvaluesrather than a discrete one. For the of sake of simplicity we formulate the follow-ing postulates only in the discrete case. In the discrete case we again have todistinguish between two cases, the non-degenerate case and the degenerate case.We have the degenerate case whenever the eigenspace corresponding to someeigenvalue has dimension greater than one otherwise we have the non degeneratecase.

Postulate 4 (non-degenerate case) When the physical quantity A is mea-sured in the normalised state x, the probability of obtaining the (non-degenerate)eigenvalue an is given by

P (an = |< yn, x >|2,where yn is the normalised eigenvector corresponding to the eigenvalue an.

The following postulate is called the Projection Postulate

Postulate 5 Suppose the system is in state 〈x〉 and a measurement of the quan-tity A is performed in this state. Suppose we get as a result of this measurementthe value a. By Postulate 2 a is an eigenvalue of A. Denote by Pa the projec-tion onto the eigenspace corresponding to the eigenvalue a. Then the state ofthe system ’after measurement’ is 〈y〉 where y = Pa(x).

The reader will miss an important postulate here, namely the postulate con-cerning the combination of two systems. this postulate says hat the combinationof two systems is represented by the tensor product of their respective Hilbertspaces. The reason is that we still have to think about the way we will intro-duce the tensor product of Hilbert spaces. On the one hand we do not have thehighly non-elementary resources available in this book to this in a way meetingthe highest mathematical standards. On the other hand we do not want to dothis in the very loose form adopted in most textbooks on quantum mechanics.We try, for didactic reasons, to find a way of introducing the tensor product ina way which is somewhere in the middle between these extremes. We will needthe tensor product again in Chapter 11.

Page 48: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

48CHAPTER 4. BASICS OF THE FORMALISM OF QUANTUM MECHANICS

Page 49: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 5

Birkhoff- von Neumann1936

Abstract:. In this chapter we attempt a detailed analysis of the classic 1936paper by Birkhoff-von Neumann paper( BvN), which initiated quantum logic.We deal extensively with BvN for two reasons. This seminal paper is essentialfor the understanding of any approach to quantum logic. Second, this paper is,though quoted frequently, not easy to read. It also has an interesting history, aswe know from the correspondence between Birkhoff and von Neumann duringthe writing of the paper. This is of interest in its own right. We will revisitBvN in Chapter..., where we establish the connection with our own work.

We then describe a surprising discovery by Kochen, Specker and Schuttewhich highligts the peculiar nature of the relationship between quantum logicand classical logic. It says that there exists a classical tautology which is acontradiction in quantum logic. At this stage this phenomenon has no deeperexplanation. We will come back to this in Chapter10, where we will generalisethis result and look at it in a new light. In a sense, this will turn out to bea special case of the theorem on holistic logics which we call the No WindowsTheorem and which will be proved in Chapter 9. ¥

It was in 1932 that John von Neumann’s classic book ”Mathematische Grund-lagen der Quantenmechanik” [64] appeared in print. In that book the mathe-matical formalism of quantum mechanics received its elegant modern form withHilbert space as its core mathematical structure. In 1936 John von Neumannpublished a paper entitled ”The logic of quantum mechanics” [2] jointly withthe Harvard mathematician Garret Birkhoff. This paper marks the birth ofwhat has become known as quantum logic.

Birkhoff and von Neumann’s seminal work has something in common withKeynes’ famous book ”General Theory of Money, Interest and Employment”,which initiated Keynesianism. Both works are widely quoted, but not all ofthose quoting them have actually studied these works in depth. Possibly thisis due to the fact that these works were not only highly influential in their

49

Page 50: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

50 CHAPTER 5. BIRKHOFF- VON NEUMANN 1936

respective fields but that they are also not easily readable, to say the least.The paper is frequently quoted as introducing the lattice of closed subspaces

of a Hilbert space as the core algebraic structure of the ’logic of quantum me-chanics’. This is a poor description of this important work. In this section weattempt a detailed analysis of this paper. This is, in view of the importance ofthis work, an end in itself, but it is also fruitful for making the connection withthe approach adopted in this book. In this section we will analyse and in a wayreconstruct and interpret this work quoting extensively from the paper itself.

In this enterprise Redei’s article [55] ”The prenatal history of quantum logic”is extremely useful. It gives insight into the correspondence between Birkhoffand von Neumann during the writing of the paper which cannot be gained fromthe paper itself. There are some highly interesting passages in the letters whichare relevant to the approach adopted in this book. The analysis given by Redeican be supplemented fruitfully by looking at it from the point of view of thisbook. We will revisit this topic in Chapter 9.

5.0.1 Structure of the paper

The paper starts with an Introduction and ends with an Appendix. Its core isdivided into three parts:

(1) Physical Background(2) Algebraic Analysis(3) ConclusionsWe will give a summary of each of these parts and will try to make trans-

parent the train of thought and the peculiar reasoning, which, as pointed outby the authors themselves, is not free from heuristic features. Our special in-terest concerns ”Physical Background” where the connection between the ’logicof quantum mechanics’ and closed subspaces of a Hilbert space is made.

5.0.2 Novel logical notions in quantum mechanics.

The paper starts, in the Introduction, as follows: ”One of the aspects of quan-tum theory which has attracted the most general attention is the novelty ofthe logical notions it presupposes. It asserts that even a complete mathemat-ical description of a physical system S does not in general enable one to topredict with certainty the result of an experiment on S, and that in particularone can never predict with certainty both the position and the momentum of S(Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle). It further asserts that most pairs of obser-vations cannot be made on S simultaneously (Principle of Non-commutativityof Observations.”

This is worth reflecting on. The authors start by saying that quantumtheory presupposes new logical notions unfamiliar from classical logic. Thentwo examples for such ”novel logical notions” are given. The first example isHeisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle, and the second example is what the authorscall the Principle of Non-Commutativity of Observations. At first glance theseprinciples seem to be purely physical in nature. What is interesting here is

Page 51: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

51

that Birkhoff and von Neumann obviously consider these principles not justas (novel) physical principles, which they undoubtedly are, but also as (novel)logical notions. This is in fact remarkable.

The paper continues as follows: ”The object of the present paper is to dis-cover what logical structure one may hope to find in physical theories which,like quantum mechanics, do not conform to classical logic. Our main conclusion,based on admittedly heuristic arguments, is that one can reasonably expect tofind a calculus of propositions which is formally indistinguishable from the calcu-lus of linear subspaces with respect to set products, linear sums and orthogonalcomplements -and resembles the usual calculus of propositions with respect toand, or , and not”.

Again, this passage is worth reflecting on. What do Birkhoff and von Neu-mann mean by saying that quantum mechanics does not conform to classicallogic? Why does it not conform to classical logic? Is it not true that physicistsuse classical logic in reasoning about quantum systems? And in fact, Popper forinstance does not share the view that quantum mechanics does not ’conform’ toclassical logic. In [51] he says: ”...physical theories, including quantum mechan-ics, do conform to classical logic, even according to Birkhoff and von Neumann’sproposal.”

There is a letter written by von Neumann to Birkhoff dated November 21935 -the paper was received by Annals of Mathematics on April 4, 1936.-which may cast light on this. John von Neumann writes: ”Looking at the papernow I see, that I forget to say this...: That while common logics did apply toquantum mechanics, if the notion of simultaneous measurability is introducedas an auxiliary notion, we wished to construct a logical system, which appliesdirectly to quantum mechanics-without any extraneous secondary notions likesimultaneous measurability. And in order to have such a consequent, one-piecesystem of logics, we must change the classical class calculus of logics.”

This passage is crucial to the understanding of the Birkhoff-von Neumannenterprise. From the modern point of view one can reconstruct this as follows.Given a (formal) language L1 that permits us to make statements about classicalmechanics. Then these statements (propositions) are expected to obey classicallogic. In such a language there is no need for talking about compatibility orincompatibility of propositions or simultaneous (non-simultaneous measurabil-ity) because all propositions are compatible and there is no ’non-simultaneousmeasurability’. In quantum mechanics, however, this distinction does matter.We might then think of constructing a richer language say by introducing addi-tional operators reflecting non-simultaneous measurability (non-compatibility)of propositions into the language that would allow statements about compatible(incompatible) and simultaneously (non-simultaneously) measurablable observ-ables in quantum mechanics. There is no reason to believe that such statementsshould not ’conform’ to classical logic, at least in the sense that the propsitionalconnectives combining them should behave classically. And, in fact, the (infor-mal) language physicists use in reasoning about quantum systems is of such anature, and the (propositional) logic they use is classical logic. Birkhoff andvon Neumann were well aware of this, and it is important to note that this is

Page 52: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

52 CHAPTER 5. BIRKHOFF- VON NEUMANN 1936

exactly what they did not want in building ’the logic of quantum mechanics’ asis obvious from John von Neumann’s letter quoted above.

Phrased in modern terminology, Birkhoff and von Neumann want to retainthe language of propositional logic as the language of the ’logic of quantummechanics’. This is what they mean by a calculus that ”resembles the usualcalculus of propositions with respect to and, or and not”. The ’novel logicalnotions’ mentioned are to be reflected in the propositional (quantum) logic tobe constructed. This logic of course cannot be expected to be classical.

Note that the term ’calculus’ is obviously not used in the modern sense. Itbecomes evident from the further progression of the paper that what the authorshave in mind is not (necessarily) a deductive system. Rather it is reminiscentof algebraic logic where logics can be defined using algebraic structures. In al-gebraic logic, Boolean algebras for instance define classical logic. Generally, thepaper does not display the distinction between syntax and semantics commonin presenting logical systems in modern style.

In any case it seems that Birkhoff and von Neumann envisage a logical sys-tem in (whatever sense) or (in their terminology) logical structures into whichnotions such as non-commutativity (of observations) or non-simultaneous mea-surarability, i.e. notions which at first glance seem to have nothing to do withlogic, can be incorporated. As indicated these novel features of quantum me-chanics should be part of the logic and not of the language of the logic. It seemsthat this view of the uncertainty relations as being logical in nature is the mainintuition of the Birkhoff-von Neumann paper. This is an insight which plays avital role in the approach to quantum logic taken in this book.

The quotations above are from the Introduction of the paper.Let us now take a closer look at the proper contents of the paper.

5.0.3 Experimental Propositions

In the first paragraphs of ”Physical Background” the authors set out to expli-cate the concept of an experimental proposition. In this they build on variousother concepts. First there is the concept of a physical system which is unprob-lematic and taken for granted by the authors. Another basic concept is that ofa set of compatible measurements. We may think of this as ”single compositemeasurement”, in modern terminology a set of mutually compatible observablesrepresented by mutually commuting Hermitian operators. They then proceed tothe concept of an observation on S: Let µ1, ...µn be n compatible measurementswith outcomes x1, ..., xn. The observation amounts to specifying these values.Call the set of all n-tuples that can arise as values in compatible measurementsan observation space of the system. Note that the concept of an observationspace is relative to a finite number of compatible observations. So, in casen = 1, we have just one observable and the observation space coresponding tothis observable is the set of all possible values it can assume as a result of anexperiment. It is then natural to define an experimental proposition to be asubset of an observation space. We may view such an experimental propositionas a sort of prediction saying that the value of an observable that we get in a

Page 53: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

53

certain experiment belongs to a certain subset of the observation space. It ismade clear, however, in the paper that not every subset of observation space isa proper candidate for this. It would for instance be absurd, as mentioned byBirkhoff and von Neumann, to call the assertion that the angular momentumof of the earth around the sun was at a particular instant a rational mumberan experimental proposition. What, however, is important to note is that inclassical physics those subsets of observation space that do represent experi-mental propositions must form a Boolean algebra with respect to the usual setoperations. This reflects the requirement that classical mechanics ’conforms’to classical logic. Those subsets of observation space that actually representexperimental propositions have later been described as Borel measurable sets.

The next crucial concept is that of a phase space. In classical mechanics,phase space means the following. Given a physical system of, say n particles.Then the ’state’ of this system is characterised by the positions and momentaof these particles. Using the words of Birkhoff and von Neumamm: ”Thus, inclassical mechanics, each point of Σ corresponds to a choice of .. n position andmomentum coordinates... Hence in this case Σ is a region of 2n-dimensionalspace.”

What, now, is the analogue of this in quantum mechanics according toBirkhoff and von Neumann? They say: ”Similarly, in quantum theory thepoints of Σ correspond to so-called wave functions, and hence Σ is again afunction-space, usually assumed to be a Hilbert space.”

Hilbert space as the phase space in quantum mechanics enters the stage hereby way of analogy. The (heuristic) argument is this. The states of a classicalsystem are determined by a tuple of positions and momenta and the phase spaceof the system is therefore the set of these tuples. In quantum mechanics thestate of the sytem is determined by a wave function and therefore its phasespace is the space of its wave functions, which is a Hilbert space.

5.0.4 A propositional calculus for quantum mechanics

From the conceptual point of view, the core of the first part of the paper isthe paragraph 6 entitled ”A propositional calculus for quantum mechanics”,in which the core logical structure of the Birkhoff-von Neumann approach toquantum logic is introduced. It seems to us that this paragraph is not easyto read. We will therefore try to reconstruct the subtle and at times heuristicreasoning in detail so as to get a clear picture of what the authors preciselyhave in mind. This will help us later on in making the connection between theapproach put forward in this book and BvN.

So far there is the concept of an experimental proposition defined as a subsetof on observation space. What is needed now is to make the connection betweenexperimental propositions and phase space in quantum mechanics, i.e. Hilbertspace. Put differently, the question has to be answered which subsets of a Hilbertspace (mathematically) represent experimental propositions. Nowadays, we arefamiliar with the following answer to this question. An experimental propositionis mathematically represented as a closed subspace of a Hilbert space. Let us

Page 54: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

54 CHAPTER 5. BIRKHOFF- VON NEUMANN 1936

see how Birkhoff and von Neumann arrive at this conclusion.We quote:” The present section will be devoted to defining such a connection,

proving some facts about it, and obtaining from it heuristically by introducinga plausible postulate, a propositional calculus for quantum mechanics”.

Note that the authors consider the argument heuristic and that a ’plausiblepostulate’ plays a role in it.

They continue: ”Accordingly, let us observe that that if α1, ..., αn are anycompatible observations on a quantum-mechanical system S with phase-spaceΣ, then there exists a set of mutually orthogonal closed linear subspaces Ωi

of Σ (which correspond to the families of proper functions satisfying α1f =λi,1f, ..., αnf = λi,nf) such that every point (or function) f ∈ Σ can be uniquelywritten in the form

f = c1f1 + c2f2 + c3f3 + ...[fi ∈ Ωi]”

Let us reconstruct this in modern terminoloy. The above sum is obviouslyinfinite. It is what we nowadays call the Fourier expansion of a vector in termsof a complete orthonormal system, see Chapter 3.3.

Here the term ’compatible observation’ must be made precise mathemati-cally. The context suggests that here α1, ..., αn represent mutually commutingHermitian operators. Then what they call the family of ’proper functions’ is thefamily of eigenfunctions (eigenvectors) common to α1, ..., αn and λi,1, ..., λi,n arethe corresponding eigenvalues. By ”..such that...” the fact is expressed that the(normalised) eigenvectors of a Hermitian operator form a complete orthonormalsystem. In case n = 1 the above just says in modern teminology that any vectorhas a unique Fourier expansion in terms of the eigenvectors of the Hermitianoperator representing α1)

The text goes on as follows:”Hence if we state the

Definition 5.1 By the ’mathematical representative’ of a subset S of any observation-space (determined by compatible observations α1, ..., αn) for a quantum-mechanicalsystem S, will be meant the set of all points f of the phase-space of S, which arelinearly determined by proper functions fk satisfying α1fk = λ1fk, ..., αnfk =λnfk, where (λ1, ..., λn ∈ S)

Then it follows immediately: (1) that the mathematical repesentative of any ex-perimental proposition is a closed linear subspace of Hilbert space (2) since alloperators of quantum mechanics are Hermitian, that the mathematical repre-sentative of the negative of any experimental proposition is the orthogonal com-plement of the mathematical representation of the proposition itself...” Notethat they define the negative of an experimental proposition (or subset S inobservation space) to be the experimental proposition corresponding to the set-complement of S in the same observation space.

Again, we think that this needs interpretation. Here, for the first time, thepaper uses the term ’closed (linear) subspace’. Why closed subspace? Whatdoes ’linearly determined’ mean? Assume ’linearly determined’ means ’linearly

Page 55: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

55

spanned’ in modern terminology. Then the conclusion that the resulting sub-paces are closed would not be justified. Recall that in an infinite-dimensionalHilbert space the linear span of a set of vectors need not be closed although wedo have this in the finite-dimensional case, see ?.

It seems that the only way of making sense of the above argument is this.Again let us assume the case n = 1, i.e. the observation space is determinedby one observable. Let α denote the (Hermitian) operator representing thisobservable and let an experimental proposition P be given. Thus P is a subsetof the set of eigenvalues of α. Let xλ | λ ∈ P be the set of eigenvectorscorresponding to the elements of P. According to the above definition themathematical representative of P the of set of vectors which are ’linearly de-termined’ in Birkhoff and von Neumann’s terminology by the x′λs. If, however,we take ’linearly determined’ by ’linearly spanned’ in modern terminology thisspan is not necessarily a closed subspace and conclusion (1) would be wrongsince the linear span of a set of vectors of a Hilbert space need not be closed inthe case of an infinite-dimensional vector space. This is generally true only ifthis subspace is finite-dimensional. As to terminology birkhff and von Neumannmean by ’Hilbert space’ what in modern terminology is an infinite-dimensionalHilbert space. Therefore ’linearly determined’ cannot mean ’linearly spanned’in modern terminology. We can, however, make perfect sense of the argumentas follows. Take ’linearly determined as meaning to be a finite or infinite sumof the xλ’s, where infinite sum means a Fourier expansion in the xλ’s. Thenthe set of the ”infinite sums” is the boundary of the span of the x′λs and theresulting space is in fact a closed subspace. On this interpretation conclusion(2) is correct too.

For the sake of clarity let us put it this way. Consider the subspace apannedby the xλ’s. Then by definition any vector of this subspace is a linear combina-tion of the xλ’s. Now take the (topological) closure of this subspace. This is aclosed subspace and thus a Hilbert space itself. Any vector of this space has a aFourier expansion in terms of the xλ’s. It seems to us that this is what Birkhoffand von Neumann mean by ”linearly determined”. The term means ”being alinear combination or the result of a Fourier expansion”.

To summarise, the following has been achieved. So far, four meaningfulconcepts have been introduced in the paper, namely the concepts of an obser-vation space, an experimental proposition, the concept of a phase space, whichin quantum mechanics is a Hilbert space, and the concept of the mathemati-cal representation of an experimental proposition. The main conclusion of thepartially heuristic but nevertheless convincing reasoning so far is that an exper-imental proposition should be mathematically represented by a closed subspaceof a Hilbert space.

The paper proceeds by introducing the following Postulate: ”The set-theoreticalproduct of any two mathematical representatives of experimental propositionsconcerning a quantum-mechanical system, is itself the mathematical represen-tatitive of an experimental proposition”

What does this postulate say? Given any two closed subspaces A and Brepresenting the experimental propositions P and Q. We can then consider

Page 56: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

56 CHAPTER 5. BIRKHOFF- VON NEUMANN 1936

A ∩ B which is again a closed subspace. The question is whether there is anexperimental proposition having A ∩ B as its mathematical representative. Itis important to note that this cannot be taken for granted. To understandthe meaning of the Postulate recall the concept of an experimental proposition.An experimental proposition presupposes an observation space which in turnpresupposes a (finite) set of compatible observables, in the simplest case oneobservable. Note that these are purely physical notions. What the Postulatesays is this. Given two observation spaces S1 and S2 and two experimentalpropositions P1 and P2 respectively which are mathemtically repesented by theclosed subspaces A and B respectively. Then it is postulated that there exists anobservation space S3 and an experimental proposition P3 relative to S3 such thatthe subspace A ∩B is the mathematical representation of P3. So the Postulateis about possible observation spaces and thus about possible observables. Itmay be viewed as a physical postulate or at least as a postulate concerning thelink between physical observables and the logic and the formalism of quantummechanics. It is in this light that the ensuing remark is to be understood:”This postulate would clearly be implied by the not unusual conjecture thatall Hermitian-symmetric operators in Hilbert space (phase space) correspond toobservables”

The reasoning now naturally proceeds as follows. Since the closed linear sumof any two closed subspaces A and B, i.e. A ∧B is A ∩B⊥ they conclude:

”The set product and closed linear sum of any two, and the orthogonalcomplement of any one closed linear subspace of Hilbert space representingmathematically an experimental proposition concernimg a quantum-mechanicalsystem S, is itself the representation of an experimental proposition concerningS”

They continue: ”...this defines the calculus of experimental propositions con-cerning S, as a calculus of experimental propositions and a relation of implica-tion...”

There is a passage in Paragraph 4 which also needs interpretation. ”Inquantum theory ...the possibility of predicting in general the readings frommeasurements on a physical system S from a knowledge of its ’state’ is denied;only statistical predictions are always possible. This has been interpreted as arenunciation of the doctrine of pre-determination; a thoughtful analysis showsthat another and more subtle idea is involved. The central idea is that physicalquantities are related, but are not all computable from a number of independentbasic quantities (such as position and velocity). We shall show in paragraph 12that this situation has an exact algebraic analogue in the calculus of proposi-tions.”

What now is said in Paragraph 12? Here they say: ”...we conclude thatthe propositional calculus of quantum mechanics has the same structure as anabstract projective geometry.”

Let us try an interpretation of this statement. In classical mechanics allphysical quantities can be computed, as is the terminology of BvN, from certainbasic quantities, namely position and velocity. If we substitute ’deducible’ for’computable’ here, the above statement could mean that the ’calculus’ of the

Page 57: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

57

propositions of quantum mechanics is not a deductive system (calculus) as isclassical logic. Rather it has the structure of a (projective) geometry describingrelations between states and propositions analogous to the relations we have ina projective geometry between points, lines, hyperplanes... One might say thatthe quantum mechanical calculus is geometrical rather than deductive.

This is an idea which becomes fully transparent in the concept of Hilbertspace logic which we will introduce later in the book.

Let us now give a short summary of part 2 of the paragraph entitled ”Alge-braic Analysis”. As indicated in the title this part is more technical in natureand less heuristic than the first part.

First it is suggested that the calculus of experimental propositions shouldhave an implication and this implication should be set inclusion.

The authors then proceed by defining the concept of a lattice. It is suggestedthat the experimental propositions should form a lattice and should thus satisfythe ’laws’ that hold in any lattice such as commutativity of join and meet andalso associativity.

They then define the concept of a complemented lattice remarking that inthe case of closed subspaces of a Hilbert space complementation is orthogonalcomplement formation.

In paragraph 10 an important issue is discussed, namely the question whetherthe calculus of quantum mechanics should satisfy the distributive identity, inBvN’s notation

L6 a ∪ (b ∩ c) = (a ∪ b) ∩ (a ∪ c

as well as its dual form. It is argued that the calculus of quantum mechanicsdoes not satisfy the distributive identity. This is even considered the ’centraldifference’ between the logic of classical and quantum mechanics. They write:”It is interesting that L6 is also a logical consequence of the compatibility of theobservables occurring in a and b and c... These facts suggest that the distributivelaw may break down in quantum mechanics”

Note that this passage is somewhat vague. What does the phrase ”compat-ible observables occurring in ...” mean? Again, it seems that this argument isheurisic Obviously BvN do not yet have the concept of compatibility of elementsin a lattice, see ? It is, however, suggested that a weakened form of the dis-tributive law should hold, namely the following identity called modularity, see?, in Bvn ’s notation

L5 If a ⊂ b, then a ∪ (b ∩ c) = (acupb) ∩ c

It is pointed out that finite-dimensional subspaces of a Hilbert space do satisfythe modular identity. Moreover, it is shown by a counterexample this is not thecase for infinite -dimensional closed subspaces, see also ?

Birkhoff and von Neumann make an interesting mathematical observationin that they observe that the modular identity follows from the existence of a’numerical dimension function’ d, i.e. a function with the following properties.

D1: If a > b, then d(a) > d(b)

Page 58: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

58 CHAPTER 5. BIRKHOFF- VON NEUMANN 1936

and

D2: d(a) + d(b) = d(a ∩ b) + d(a ∪ b)

Note that the modular identity is stronger than the orthomodular identity,see ?. It is interesting that BvN insist on this stronger version which, as alreadynoted, does not necessarily hold for infinite -dimensional closed subspaces of aHilbert space. As pointed out by Redei in [?] it is von Neumann’s hope thatsuch a dimension function which is similar to a probability function might beof use in understanding the probabilistic nature of Quantum Mechanics.

In many publications the Birkhoff-von Neumann paper is quoted as intro-ducing the lattice of closed subspaces of a Hilbert space as the ’logic of quantummechanics’. This statement appears unfounded in view of what Birkhoff and vonNeumann say in ”Conclusions”: ”One conclusion one can draw from the pre-ceding algebraic considerations, is that one can construct many different modelsfor a propositional calculus of quantum mechanics, which cannot be distiguishedby known criteria”. What follows then says in modern terminology that anyfinite dimensional projective geometry over any field with a suitable involuntaryanti-automorphism and a Hermitian form. It is worth noting that they insiston finite dimensionality because they want to retain the modular law. Even inthe infinite-dimensional case they consider it -in the spirit of Hankel’s principle”perseverance of formal laws”- desirable to retain the modular law. But thisexcludes the closed subspaces of a finite-dimensional Hilbert space as a proper’infinite-dimensional model’ of the logical calculus of quantum mechanics. It isthis fact that led von Neumann to develop his ”Continuous Geometry”.

A letter by von Neumann to Birkhoff written before the paper was publishedcontains the following passage (from Redei [55]: ”Your general remarks, I think,are very true: I too think that our paper will not be exhaustive or conclusive,but that we should not attempt to make it such : The subject is obviouslyonly at the beginning of a development, and we want to suggest the direction ofthis development much more, than reach ’final results’. I, for one, do not evenbelieve, that the right formal frame for quantum mechanics is already found.”

5.0.5 The correspondence between Birkhoff and von Neu-mannn during the writing of the paper

von Neumann to Birkhoff

The following has already been said.”Your general remarks I think are very true: I, too, think that our paper

will not be very exhaustive or conclusive, but that we should not attempt tomake it such: The subject is obviously only at the beginning of a development,and we want to suggest the direction of this development much more, than toreach final results. I, for one, do not even believe that the right formal framefor quantum mechanics is already found.”

Page 59: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

59

Birkhoff’ s conditional

The following should probably be said in connection with Implication M-algebras.von Neumann to Birkhoff: ”Last spring you observed: Why not introduce

a logical operation ab for any two (not necessarily simultaneously decidable)properties a and b, meaning this: If you first measure a you find that it ispresent, if you next measure b, you find that it is present too.

This ab cannot be described by any operator, and in particular not by a pro-jection (= linear subspace). The only answer I could then find was this: Thereis no state in which the property ab is certainly present, nor is any in which it iscertainly absent (assuming that a,b are sufficiently non-simultaneously definable= that their projection operators E,F have no common proper-functions not =0 at all).

Of course, for this reason ab is no physical quantity relatively to the themachinery of quantum -mechanics. But how can one motivate this, how canone find a criterion of what is a physical quality and what not, if not by the’causality’ criterion: A statement describes if and only if the states in which itcan be decided with certainty form a complete set.

I wanted to avoid this rather touchy and complicated question, and with-draw to the safe - although perhaps narrow- position of dealing with ’causal’statements’ only. Do you propose to discuss the question fully? It might becometoo philosophical, but I would not say that I object absolutely to it. But it isdangerous ground-except you have a new idea , which settles the question moresatisfactorily.”

Let us take a closer look at this letter. In this letters JvN refers to a ’logicaloperation’ proposed by Birkhoff in an earlier letter (spring 1935?). What doesBirkhoff mean by ’logical operation’? A oonnective probably, so ”ab” is aconditional in our sense. The conditional proposed by Birkhoff is similar to butdifferent from ours. Our conditional says: ”If you measure A, you end up in astate in which B is sharp.” Think of ”sharp” as ”provable”. So given a state x.Then after masuring A we are in state Ax. The requirement that in this state Bis sharp says that BAx = Ax. In this terminology, Birkhoff’s conditional says:”If you first measure A and then measure B, you end up in a state in which Ais still sharp.”. Mathematically this means: ABAx = BAx.

Now JvN is not satisfied with this arguing that this ’operation’ is not rep-resentable by a projection (subspace). The following is a reconstruction of hisargument. Let A, B such that A ∪B = 0, not B ⊂ A⊥ and not B ⊂ A. Sucha constellation exists in every Hilbert space of dimension at least 3.

His first observation is : ”There is no state in which the property ab iscertainly present” What does this mean? For A, B as above, ABAx = BAximplies BAx = 0 or equivalently Ax ∈ B⊥

In our terminology, the consequence relation has no internalising connectivedefinable by the lattice operations.

Think about this again.We will come back to this Chapter later in ”Birkhoff-von Neumann Revis-

ited”, where we we will establish the precise connection betweeen Birkhoff-von

Page 60: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

60 CHAPTER 5. BIRKHOFF- VON NEUMANN 1936

Neumann and the approach put forward in this book

5.0.6 The Kochen-Specker and the Schutte Tautologies

Although Birkhoff and von Neumann must have been fully aware of the factthat their logical ’calculus’ must differ from classical logic in important respects,they did not provide an explicit comparison between the two logics. The onlydifference they explicitly mention is that the distributive laws of classical logicno longer hold in the ’logic of quantum mechanics’. In view of the fact thatit was their chief motivation to incorporate the profound differences betweenclassical and quantum mechanics such as the existence of uncertainty relationsinto the logic this seems not too profound an observation. It took some timeuntil a truly surprising phenomenon was found which highlights the profounddifference between Birkhoff-von Neumann quantum logic and classical logic.Namely, Kochen and Specker discovered in their classic paper ”The problem ofhidden variables in quantum mechanics” [33], as a byproduct, the following fact.There exists a classical tautology which under a certain ’valuation’ in the latticeof closed subspaces in (three-dimensional) Hilbert space represents the zerospace. Loosely speaking there exists a classical tautology which is a ’quantumlogicical contradiction’ and the other way round. Kochen and Specker explicitlypresent such a tautology in 117 propositional variables. A similar tautology hadeven before the publication of the Kochen-Specker paper been found by Schutteas is known from a letter that Schutte wrote to Specker. Schutte’s tautology doesnot represent the zero space. But it does not represent the whole space either.It is a classical tautology which is not a quantum tautology. It is importantto note that both in the Kochen-Specker tautology and in Schutte’s tautologyonly compatible quantum propositions are combined via the connectives.

We will study this phenomenon of classical inconsistency in the Birkhoff-vonNeumann quantum logic from a general point of view in Chapters 7 and 9. Wewill see that this phenomenon is by no means accidental.

Page 61: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 6

The Dynamic Viewpoint:Propositions as Operators

6.1 Propositions viewed dynamically

Let us begin by pointing out a certain analogy between measurements andpropositions. A physical measurement, e.g., measuring the temperature of agas to be 138 K, asserts that the proposition the temperature of this gas is138 K holds true. A measurement, in a sense, asserts the truth of a propo-sition. This is the fundamental analogy between physics and logic: making ameasurement is similar to asserting a certain kind of proposition. The exampleabove has been taken from classical physics. Consider now measuring the spinof a particle along the z-axis to be 1/2. This measurement is akin to assert-ing the truth of the proposition the spin along the z-axis is 1/2. But, here,the assertion of the proposition, i.e., the measurement, changes the state of thesystem. The assertion holds in the state resulting from the measurement, butdid not necessarily hold in the state of the system before the measurement wasperformed. In fact it held in this previous state if and only if the measurementleft the state unchanged. Inspired by the analogy between measurements andpropositions we set ourselves to study the logic of propositions that not onlyhold at states, i.e., models, but also act on them, transforming the state in whichthey are evaluated into another one. A proposition holds in some state if andonly if this state is a fixpoint for the proposition.

Conceptualy this is the novelty of our approach to logic in this chapter. Weview propositions in a dynamic rather than in a static way. The motivationfor this is provided by the analogy between measurements and propositions,and thus in this chapter we restrict ourselves to propositions having a physicalmeaning such as ”The energy of the electron in the hydrogen atom is such andsuch”. One can now ask the question whether this dynamic aspect of proposi-tions is peculiar to a cetrain type of propositions, namely quantum mechanicalpropositions, or whether we should consider the dynamic view of propositions as

61

Page 62: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

62CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

the proper one even beyond the realm of quantum mechanics. Let us just notethat in the technical treatment of the dynamic nature of propositions presentedin this chapter the static view characteristic of traditional, in particular classicallogic is a special case of the dynamic view. We will go into this in more detailin the last chapter of this book.

6.2 The Concept of an M-Algebra

In inpired by the above consideration we define a new class of abstract structuresfor which we coin the term algebras of measurements, M-algebras for short.Formally, this concept is an abstraction from the the algebra of projections ofa Hilbert space. The most appealing feature of these structures consists in theintuitive content of its axioms. The main intuition is, as already pointed out,the analogy between measurements and propositions. Projections in Hilbertspace may be viewed as measurements that can change the state of the systemas is the case in quantum mechanics.

Section ?? will summarize in a most succinct and formal way the definitionof Algebras of Measurements (M-algebras), by presenting a list of properties.It should be used as an overview and memento only. The following sectionswill explain the properties, present motivation and explanation, and then provebasic properties of M-algebras.

The structures we are concerned with deal with a set X and functionsfrom X to X. We shall denote the composition of functions by and com-position has to be understood from left to right: for any x ∈ X, (α β)(x) =β(α(x)). If α : X −→ X, we shall denote by FP (α) the set of all fixpoints of α:FP (α) def= x ∈ X | α(x) = x.

Definition 6.1 An M-algebra is a pair 〈X, M〉 in which X is a non-emptyset and M is a set of functions from X to X, that satisfies the six propertiesdescribed below.

• Illegitimate ∃ 0 ∈ X such that ∀α ∈ M , 0 ∈ FP (α), i.e, α(0) = 0.

• Idempotence ∀α ∈ M , α α = α, i.e., for any x ∈ X, α(α(x)) = α(x).

The next property requires a preliminary definition.

Definition 6.2 For any α, β : X −→ X, we shall say that α preserves β ifand only if α preserves FP (β), i.e., if α(FP (β)) ⊆ FP (β), i.e., ∀x ∈ X,β(x) = x ⇒ β(α(x)) = α(x).

• Composition ∀α, β ∈ M , if α preserves β, then β α ∈ M .

• Interference ∀x ∈ X, ∀α, β ∈ M , if x ∈ FP (α), i.e., α(x) = x, and (β α)(x) ∈ FP (β),i.e., β(α(β(x))) = α(β(x)), then β(x) ∈ FP (α), i.e., α(β(x)) = β(x).

Page 63: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.3. MOTIVATION AND JUSTIFICATION 63

• Cumulativity ∀x ∈ X, ∀α, β ∈ M , if α(x) ∈ FP (β), i.e., β(α(x)) = α(x)and β(x) ∈ FP (α), i.e., α(β(x)) = β(x), then α(x) = β(x).

The next property requires some notation. For any α : X −→ X, we shalldenote by Z(α) the set of zeros of α: Z(α) def= x ∈ X | α(x) = 0.

• Negation ∀α ∈ M , ∃(¬α) ∈ M , such that FP (¬α) = Z(α), and Z(¬α) =FP (α), i.e., ∀x ∈ X, α(x) = 0 iff (¬α)(x) = x and ∀x ∈ X, α(x) = x iff(¬α)(x) = 0.

An additional property will be considered in Section 6.8.

Definition 6.3 An M-algebra is separable if it satisfies the following:

Separability For any x, y ∈ X − 0, if x 6= y then ∃α ∈ M such that α(x) = xand α(y) 6= y.

The above definition needs comment. The mathematically educated readerwill easily realise that the structures called M-algebras defined above althoughdo, in the strict sense of Universal Algebra, not qualify as algebras. Fromthe point of view of Universal Algebra as well as from the viewpoint of ModelTheory, algebras are first-order structures whereas what we call an M-algebrais a second order structure very much akin to a topological space. Perhapsthe appropriate term to denote them should be ”propositional space”, a non-empty set X equipped with a set M of functions from X to X as a topologicalspace is a non-empty set X equipped with a set of subsets of X. Both theelements of M in the case of an M-algebra and the topology in the case of atopological space are second order entities. The axiomas of both an M-algebraand a topological space are formulated in a second order language quantifyingover second prder entities. We retain the term ”M-algebra” for the sake of asuggestive terminology reminding the reader of the analogy with measurementsin quantum physics.

6.3 Motivation and Justification

In this section, we shall leisurely explain each one of the properties described inSection ??. Our explanation of each property will include three parts:

• an epistemological explanation whose purpose is to explain why the prop-erty is natural or even required when one thinks of measurements,

• an explanation of why the property holds in the algebra 〈H,L〉 where His a Hilbert space and L the set of all projections onto closed subspaces ofH,

• an explanation of the logical meaning of the property, based on the iden-tification of measurements with propositions.

Page 64: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

64CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

6.3.1 States

We shall reserve the term state for the elements of X. In physical terms, theset X is the set of all possible states of a system. When we say state we meana state as fully determined as is physically possible: e.g., in classical mechanics,a set of 6n values if we consider n particles (three values for position and threevalues for momentum), or what is generally termed, in Quantum Physics a purestate.

In the Hilbertian description of Quantum Physics, a (pure) state is a one-dimensional subspace, i.e., a ray, in some Hilbert space. The illegitimate state,0 is the zero-dimensional subspace.

In our study of M-algebras a state is a primitive notion and we need notreflect in depth on this at this stage. We will enter a detailed discussion of theconcept of state in Chapter 7.

6.3.2 Measurements

The elements of M represent measurements on the physical system whose pos-sible states are those of X. In Classical Physics one may assume that a mea-surement leaves the measured system unchanged. It is a hallmark of Quan-tum Physics that this assumption cannot be held true anymore. In QuantumPhysics, measurements, in general, change the state of the system. This is thephenomenon called collapse of the wave function. Therefore we model measure-ments by transformations on the set of states. Clearly not any transformationcan be called a measurement. A measurement changes the system in some min-imal way. A transformation that brings about a wild change in the systemcannot be considered to be a measurement. Many of the properties presentedabove and discussed below explicit this requirement.

A word of caution is necessary here before we proceed. When we speakabout measurement we do not mean some declaration of intentions such asmeasuring the position of a particle, we mean the action of measuring somephysical quantity and finding a specific value, such as finding the particle at theorigin of the system of coordinates. Measuring 0.3 K and measuring 1000 Kare not two different possible results for the same measurement, they are twodifferent measurements.

In the Hilbertian description of Quantum Physics measurable quantities areby Hermitian operators. Measurements in our sense are represented by a pair〈A, λ〉 where A is a Hermitian operator and λ an eigenvalue of A. The effectof measuring 〈A, λ〉 in state x is to project x onto the eigensubspace of A foreigenvalue λ. A measurement α is therefore a projection on a closed subspaceof a Hilbert space. The set FP (α) is the closed subspace on which α projects.Those projections onto eigensubspaces are the measurements we try to identify.Our goal is to identify the algebraic properties of such projections that makethem suitable to represent physical measurements in Quantum Physics.

¿From a classical logician’s point of view, a measurement is a proposition.A proposition α acts on a state, i.e., a theory T by sending it to the theory that

Page 65: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.3. MOTIVATION AND JUSTIFICATION 65

results from adding α to T and then closing under logical consequence. One seesthat, from this point of view, if T is maximal then α(T ) is either T (iff α is in T )or the inconsistent theory. We see here that a proposition (measurement) holdsin some model (state) if and only if the model is a fixpoint of the proposition.

This is the interpretation that we shall take along with us: a measurementα holds at some state x, or, equivalently x satisfies α, if and only if x ∈ FP (α).

6.3.3 Illegitimate

Illegitimate is mainly a technical requirement. The sequel will show whyit is handy. The illegitimate state 0 is a state that is physically impossible.Physicists, in general, do not consider this state explicitly, we shall. ¿Fromthe epistemological point of view, we just require that amongst all the possiblestates of the system we include a state, denoted 0 that represents physicalimpossibility. There is not much sense in measuring anything in the illegitimatestate, therefore, it is natural to assume that no measurement α operating on theillegitimate state can change it into some legitimate state. This is the meaningof our requirement that 0 be a fixpoint of any measurement. In other terms,the state 0 satisfies every measurement, every measurement holds at 0.

In the Hilbertian description of Quantum Physics the zero vector plays therole of our 0. Indeed, since a projection is linear, it preserves the zero vector.

¿From a logician’s point of view Illegitimate requires us to include theinconsistent theory in X. Clearly, the result of adding any proposition to theinconsistent theory leaves us with the inconsistent theory.

6.3.4 Zeros

We have described in Section 6.3.2 the interpretation we give to the fact thata state x is a fixpoint of a measurement α. We want to give a similarly centralmeaning to the fact that a state x is a zero of a measurement α: x ∈ Z(α),i.e., α(x) = 0. If measuring α sends x to the illegitimate state, measuring αis physically impossible at x. This should be understood as meaning that thestate x has some definite value different from the one specified by α.

If, at x, the spin is 1/2 along the z-axis, then measuring along the z-axis aspin of −1/2 is physically impossible and therefore the measurement of −1/2sends the state x to the illegitimate state 0. The status of the measurementthat measures −1/2 along the x-axis is completely different: this measurementdoes not send x to 0, but to some legitimate state in which the spin along thex-axis is −1/2.

It is natural to say that a measurement α has a definite value at x iff x iseither a fixpoint or a zero of α. We shall define: Def(α) def= FP (α) ∪ Z(α). Ifx ∈ Def(α), α has a definite value at x: either it holds at x or it is impossibleat x. If x 6∈ Def(α), α(x) is some state different from x and different from 0.

In the Hilbertian presentation of Quantum Physics, the zeros of a measure-ment α are the vectors orthogonal to the set of fixpoints of α.

Page 66: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

66CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

6.3.5 Idempotence

Idempotence is extremely meaningful. It is an epistemologically fundamentalproperty of measurements that they are idempotent: if α is a measurement andx a state, then α(α(x)) = α(x), i.e., measuring the same value twice in a row isexactly like measuring it once. Note that, by Illegitimate, if x ∈ Def(α), thenα(α(x)) = α(x). The import of Idempotence concerns states that are not inDef(α).

It seems very difficult to imagine a scientific theory in which measurementsare not idempotent: it would be impossible to check directly that a system isindeed in the state we expect it to be in without changing it. Idempotence is oneof the conditions that ensure that measurements change states only minimally.This principle seems to be a fundamental principle of all science, having to dowith the reproducibility of experiments. If there was a physical system and ameasurement that, if performed twice in a row gave different results, then sucha measurement would be, in principle, irreproducible.

In the Hilbertian description of Quantum Physics measurements are mod-eled by projections onto eigensubspaces. Any projection is idempotent. Butit is enlightening to reflect on the phenomenology of this idempotence. For anelectron whose spin is positive along the z-axis (state x0), measuring a negativespin along the x-axis is feasible, i.e., does not send the system into the illegit-imate state, but sends the system into a state (x1) different from the originalone, x0. Nevertheless, a consequence of the collapse of the wave function isthat, after measuring a negative spin along the x-axis, the spin is indeed nega-tive along the x-axis and therefore a new measurement of a negative spin alongthe x-axis leaves the state x1 of our electron unchanged, whereas measuring apositive spin along the x-axis is now an unfeasible measurement and sends x1

to the illegitimate state. Note that such a measurement of a positive spin alongthe x-axis in the original state x0 brings us to a legitimate state x3 differentfrom x0 and x1. The idempotence of measurements, probably epistemologicallynecessary, provides some explanation of why projections in Hilbert spaces are asuitable model.

¿From the logical point of view, idempotence corresponds to the fact thatasserting the truth of a proposition is equivalent to asserting it twice. For anyreasonable consequence operation C

C(C(T, a), a) = C(T, a).

6.3.6 Preservation

The definition of preservation encapsulates the way in which different measure-ments can interfere. If α preserves FP (β), the set of states in which β holds, αnever destroys the truth of proposition β: it never interferes badly with β.

Page 67: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.3. MOTIVATION AND JUSTIFICATION 67

6.3.7 Composition

Composition has physical significance. It is a global principle: it assumes aglobal property and concludes a global property. Measurements are mappings ofX into itself, therefore we may consider the composition of two measurements.According to the principle of minimal change, we do not expect the compositionof two measurements to be a measurement: two small changes may make a bigchange. But, if those two measurements do not interfere in any negative waywith each other, we may consider their composition as small changes that donot add up to a big change. Composition requires that if, indeed, α preservesβ, then the composite operation that consists of measuring β first, and then αdoes not add up to a big change and should be a bona fide measurement. Noticethat we perform β first, whose result is (by Idempotence) a state that satisfiesβ, then we perform α, which does not destroy the result obtained by the firstmeasurement β.

In the Hilbertian presentation of Quantum Physics, consider α, the projec-tion on some closed subspace A and β, the projection on B. The measurementα preserves β iff the projection of the subspace B onto A is contained in theintersection A ∩ B of A and B. In such a case the composition β α of thetwo projections, first on B and then on A is equivalent to the projection on theintersection A ∩B. It is therefore a projection on some closed subspace.

For the classical logician, measurements always preserve each other. If a ∈ T ,then a ∈ C(T, b) for any proposition b. This is a consequence of the monotonicityof C. Composition requires that the composition of any two measurements be ameasurement. For the logician, β α is the measurement β ∧ α. Compositionamounts to the assumption that M is closed under conjunction.

Technically, the role of Compositionis to ensure that two commuting mea-surements’ composition is a measurement. Equivalently, we could have, insteadof Composition, required that for any pair α, β ∈ M such that α β = β α,their composition α β be in M .

6.3.8 Interference

Interference has a deep physical meaning. It is a local principle, i.e., holdsseparately at each state x. It may be seen as a local logical version of Heisen-berg’s uncertainty principle. It considers a state x that satisfies α. Measuringβ at x may leave α undisturbed (this is the conclusion), but, if β disturbs α,then no state at which both α and β hold can ever be attained by measuring αand β in succession. In other words, either such a state, satisfying both α andβ is obtained immediately, or never.

We shall say that β disturbs α at x if x ∈ FP (α) but β(x) 6∈ FP (α). Notethat β preserves α if and only if it disturbs α at no x. Interference says thatif β disturbs α at x then α disturbs β at β(x), and β disturbs α at (β α)(x),and so on. We chose to name this property Interference since it deals with thelocal interference of two measurements: if they interfere once, they will continueinterfering ad infinitum.

Page 68: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

68CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

In the Hilbertian presentation of Quantum Physics, the principle of Inter-ference is satisfied for the following reason. Consider a vector x ∈ H and twoclosed subspaces of H: A and B. Assume x is in A. Let y be the projection ofx onto B and z the projection of y onto A. Assume that z is in B. Since bothx and z are in A, the vector z − x is in A. Similarly, the vector z − y is in B.But y is the projection of x onto B and therefore y − x is orthogonal to B andin particular orthogonal to z − y. We have 〈y − x, z − y〉 = 0, and

〈y, z〉 − 〈y, y〉 − 〈x, z〉+ 〈x, y〉 = 0.

Since z is the projection of y onto A, the vector z − y is orthogonal to A andwe have 〈(z − x), (z − y) = 0〉, and

〈z, z〉 − 〈z, y〉 − 〈x, z〉+ 〈x, y〉 = 0.

By substracting the first equality from the second we get:

−〈z, y〉 − 〈y, z〉+ 〈y, y〉+ 〈z, z〉 = 〈y − z, y − z)〉 = 0.

We conclude that y = z.For the logician, it is always the case that β(x) ∈ FP (α) if x ∈ FP (α), as

noticed in Section 6.3.7.

6.3.9 Cumulativity

Cumulativity is motivated by Logic. It does not seem to have been reflectedupon by physicists. It parallels the cumulativity property that is central tononmonotonic logic: see for example [?, ?, ?]. If the measurement of α at xcauses β to hold (at α(x)), and the measurement of β at x causes α to hold (atβ(x)) then those two measurements have, locally (at x), the same effect. Indeed,they cannot be directly distinguished by testing α and β. Cumulativity saysthat they cannot be distinguished even indirectly.

In the Hilbertian formalism, if the projection, y, of x onto some closedsubspace A is in B (closed subspace) then y is the projection of x onto theintersection A∩B. If the projection z of x onto B is in A, z is the projection ofx onto the intersection B ∩A and therefore y = z. In fact, a stronger propertythan Cumulativity holds in Hilbert spaces. The following property, similar tothe Loop property of [?], holds in Hilbert spaces: L-Cumulativity ∀x ∈ X, forany natural number n and for any sequence αi ∈ M , i = 0, . . . , n if, for any suchi, αi(x) ∈ FP (αi+1), where n + 1 is understood as 0, then, for any 0 ≤ i, j ≤ n,αi(x) = αj(x).

To see that this property holds in Hilbert spaces, consider the distance di

between x and the closed subspace Ai on which αi projects. The conditionαi(x) ∈ FP (αi+1) implies that di+1 ≤ di. We have d0 ≥ d1 ≥ . . . ≥ dn ≥ d0 andwe conclude that all those distances are equal and therefore αi(x) ∈ FP (αi+1)implies that αi(x) = αi+1(x). We do not know whether the stronger L-Cumulativityis meaningful for Quantum Physics, or simply an uninteresting consequence ofthe Hilbertian formalism.

Page 69: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.4. EXAMPLES OF M-ALGEBRAS 69

For the logical point of view, one easily sees that any classical measurementssatisfy Cumulativity, and even L-Cumulativity.

6.3.10 Negation

Negation also originates in Logic. It corresponds to the assumption that propo-sitions are closed under negation. If α is a measurement, α tests whether acertain physical quantity has a specific value v. If such a test can be performed,it seems that a similar test could be performed to test the fact that the physicalquantity of interest has some other specific value or does not have value v.

In the Hilbertian formalism, to any closed subspace corresponds its orthog-onal subspace, also closed.

For the logician, Negation amounts to the closure of the set of (classical)measurements, i.e., formulas, under negation.

6.3.11 Separability

We remind the reader that Separability is not included in the defining proper-ties of an M-algebra. Separability asserts that if any two non-zero states x andy are different, there is a measurement that holds at x and not at y. Indeed, ifall measurements that hold at x also hold at y it would not be possible to be surethat the system is in x and not in y. Compared to the previous requirements,Separability is of quite a different kind. It is some akin to a superselectionprinciple, though presented in a dual way: a restriction on the set of states noton the set of observables.

Note that this implies that, in any non-trivial M-algebra (an M-algebra istrivial if X = 0 and M = ∅), every state satisfies some measurement.

In the Hilbertian formalism, the projections on the one-dimensional sub-spaces defined by x and y respectively do the job.

For the logician, if T1 and T2 are two maximal consistent sets that aredifferent, there is a formula α in T1−T2. But, one may easily find (non-maximal)different theories T1 and T2 such that T1 ⊂ T2, contradicting Separability.

6.4 Examples of M-algebras

In this section we shall formally define the two paradigmatical examples of M-algebras that have been described in Section 6.3: propositional calculus andHilbert space.

6.4.1 Logical Examples

Propositional Calculus: a non-separable M-algebra and a separableone

We shall now formalize our treatment of Propositional Calculus as an M-algebra.In doing so, we shall present Propositional Calculus in the way advocated by

Page 70: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

70CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

Tarski and Gentzen. Let L be any language closed under a unary connective ¬and a binary connective ∧. Let Cn be any consequence operation satisfying thefollowing conditions (the conditions are satisfied by Propositional Calculus).

Inclusion ∀A ⊆ L, A ⊆ Cn(A),

Monotonicity ∀A, B ⊆ L, A ⊆ B ⇒ Cn(A) ⊆ Cn(B),

Idempotence ∀A ⊆ L, Cn(A) = Cn(Cn(A)),

Negation ∀A ⊆ L, a ∈ L, Cn(A,¬a) = L ⇔ a ∈ C(A),

Conjunction ∀A ⊆ L, a, b ∈ L, Cn(A, a, b) = Cn(A, a ∧ b).

Define a subset of L to be a theory iff it is closed under Cn: T ⊆ L is a theoryiff Cn(T ) = T . Let X be the set of all theories. Let M be the language L. Theaction of a formula α ∈ L on a theory T is defined by: α(T ) = Cn(T ∪ α). Insuch a structure α holds at T iff α ∈ T . Let us check that such a structure sat-isfies all the defining properties of an M-algebra. We shall not mention the usesof Inclusion. The illegitimate state is the theory L. Idempotence follows fromthe property of the same name. Composition follows from Conjunction: thecomposition a b is the measurement a ∧ b. Note that any pair of measure-ments commute. Interference is satisfied because a ∈ T implies a ∈ Cn(T, b).Cumulativity is satisfied because b ∈ Cn(T, a) implies Cn(T, a) = Cn(T, a, b)by Monotonicity and Idempotence. Negation holds by the property of thesame name.

The M-algebra above does not satisfy Separability since there are theoriesT and S such that T ⊂ S and every formula α satisfied by T is also satisfiedby S. This M-algebra is commutative: any two measurements commute since:Cn(C(T, a), b) = Cn(C(T, b), a).

If we consider the subset Y ⊂ X consisting only of maximal consistent the-ories and the inconsistent theory, we see that the pair 〈Y,L〉 is an M-algebra,because Y is closed under the measurements in L. In this M-algebra, all mea-surements do more than commute, they are classical, in the following sense.

Definition 6.4 A mapping α : X −→ X is said to be classical iff for everyx ∈ X, either α(x) = x or α(x) = 0.

The M-algebra above is separable: if T1 and T2 are diferent maximal consistenttheories there is a formula a ∈ T1 − T2.

Nonmonotonic inference operations

In Section 6.4.1 we assumed that the inference operation Cn was monotonic. Itseems attractive to consider the more general case of nonmonotonic inferenceoperations studied, for example in [?]. More precisely what about replacingMonotonicity by the weaker

Cumulativity ∀A,B ⊆ L, A ⊆ B ⊆ C(A) ⇒ C(B) = C(A).

Page 71: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.4. EXAMPLES OF M-ALGEBRAS 71

Notice that, in such a case, we prefer to denote our inference operation by C andnot by Cn. The reader may verify that all requirements for an M-algebra stillhold true, except for Composition. In such a structure all measurements stillcommute and we therefore need that every composition a b of measurements(formula) be a measurement (formula). But the reader may check that a ∧ bdoes not have the required properties: C(T, a ∧ b) = C(T, a, b) but, since C is notrequired to be monotonic, there may well be some formula c ∈ C(T, a) that isnot in C(T, a, b). In such a case C(T, a ∧ b) 6= C(C(T, a), b), as would be required.One may, then, think of extending the language L to include formulas of the formboxab acting as compositions. But the Negation condition of the definition ofan M-algebra requires every formula (measurement) to have a negation and thereis no obvious definition for the negation of a composition. The Monotonicityproperty seems therefore essential.

Revisions

Another natural idea is to consider revisions a la AGM [?]. The action of aformula a on a theory T would be defined as the theory T revised by a: T∗a.The structure obtained does not satisfy the M-algebra assumptions. The mostblatant violation concerns Negation. In revision theory negation does notbehave at all as expected in an M-algebra.

6.4.2 Orthomodular and Hilbert spaces

Orthomodular spaces

Given any orthomodular space H, denote by M the set of all closed subspacesof H. Then the pair 〈H,M〉 is an M-algebra, if any α ∈ M acts on H in thefollowing way: α(x) is the unique vector such that x = α(x) + y for some vectory ∈ α⊥. In light of Section 6.3 the reader will have no trouble proving that anysuch structure is an M-algebra. It is not separable, though: any two colinearvectors satisfy exactly the same measurements. The next section will present arelated separable M-algebra.

Rays

Given any orthomodular space H, let X be the set of one-dimensional or zero-dimensional subspaces of H. Let M be the set of closed subspaces of H. Theprojection on a closed subspace is linear and therefore sends a one-dimensionalsubspace to a one-dimensional or a zero-dimensional subspace and sends thezero-dimensional subspace to itself. The pair 〈X, M〉 is easily seen to be anM-algebra. This M-algebra is separable: notice that X ⊂ M and that x ∈ X isthe only state satisfying the measurement x.

Page 72: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

72CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

6.5 Properties of M-algebras

We assume that 〈X, M〉 is an arbitrary M-algebra. First, we shall show that anyM-algebra includes two trivial measurements: >, analogous to the truth-valuetrue, that leaves every state unchanged and measures a property satisfied byevery state and ⊥, analogous to false, that sends every state to the illegitimatestate, and is nowhere satisfied.

Lemma 6.1 [Negation, Composition, Idempotence] There are measurements>,⊥ ∈ M such that for every x ∈ X, >(x) = x and ⊥(x) = 0.

Proof. The set M of measurements is not empty: assume α ∈ M . Clearly,by Negation, the measurement ¬α preserves α. It follows, by Composition,that α (¬α) is a measurement. Let ⊥ = α (¬α). By Idempotence andNegation, for every x ∈ X, ⊥(x) = 0. We now let > = ¬⊥.

Then, we want to show that measurements are uniquely specified by theirfixpoints.

Lemma 6.2 [Idempotence, Cumulativity] For any α, β ∈ M , if FP (α) = FP (β),then α = β.

Proof. Assume FP (α) = FP (β). Let x ∈ X. By Idempotence α(x) ∈FP (α) and therefore, by assumption α(x) ∈ FP (β). Similarly β(x) ∈ FP (α).By Cumulativity, then, α = β.

Corollary 6.1 [Idempotence, Cumulativity, Negation] For any α ∈ M , ¬¬α =α.

Proof. Both α and ¬¬α are measurements and FP (¬¬α) = FP (α).

We shall now prove a very important property. Suppose x is a state in whichsome measurement (i.e., proposition) holds: for example, at x the spin alongthe x-axis is 1/2. Performing a measurement α on x may lead to a differentstate y = α(x). At y the spin along the x-axis may still be 1/2, or it may bethe case that the measurement α has interfered with the value of the spin. But,under no circumstance, can it be the case that the spin along the x-axis has adefinite value different from 1/2, such as −1/2. If the value of the spin alongthe x-axis at y is not 1/2, the spin must be indefinite. This expresses the factthat a measurement α, acting on a state in which β holds, can either preserveβ (when α(x) ∈ FP (β)) or can disturb β (when α(x) 6∈ Def(β)) but cannotmake β impossible at x, i.e., α(x) ∈ Z(β). This is a very natural requirementstemming from the minimal change principle. A move from a definite value toa different definite value is too drastic to be accepted as measurement.

In the Hilbertian presentation of Quantum Physics, measurements are pro-jections. The projection of a non-null vector x onto a closed subspace A is neverorthogonal to x, unless x is orthogonal to A. Therefore if x is in some subspaceB, but its projection on A is orthogonal to B, then this projection is the nullvector.

Page 73: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.5. PROPERTIES OF M-ALGEBRAS 73

Lemma 6.3 [Illegitimate, Interference] For any x ∈ X, α, β ∈ M , if x ∈ FP (β),i.e., β(x) = x, and α(x) ∈ Z(β), i.e., β(α(x)) = 0, then x ∈ Z(α), i.e., α(x) = 0.

Proof. Assume x ∈ FP (β) and β(α(x)) = 0. Then (α β)(x) = 0 ∈ FP (α).By Interference, then, α(x) ∈ FP (β) and β(α(x)) = α(x), i.e., 0 = α(x).

We shall now sort out the relation between fixpoints and zeros. The nextresult is a dual of Lemma 6.3.

Lemma 6.4 [Illegitimate, Interference, Negation] ∀x ∈ X, ∀α, β ∈ M , if x ∈Z(β) and α(x) ∈ FP (β), then x ∈ Z(α). In other terms, if β(x) = 0 andβ(α(x)) = α(x), then α(x) = 0.

Proof. Consider the measurement ¬β guaranteed by Negation. If we havex ∈ FP (¬β) and α(x) ∈ Z(¬β), then, by Lemma 6.3 we have x ∈ Z(α).

Lemma 6.5 [Illegitimate, Idempotence, Interference, Negation] For any α, β ∈ M ,FP (α) ⊆ FP (β) iff Z(β) ⊆ Z(α).

Proof. Suppose FP (α) ⊆ FP (β) and x ∈ Z(β). Since, by Idempotence,α(x) ∈ FP (α), we have, by assumption, α(x) ∈ FP (β). By Lemma 6.4, thenx ∈ Z(α).

Suppose now that Z(β) ⊆ Z(α). We have FP (¬β) ⊆ FP (¬α) and by whatwe just proved: Z(¬α) ⊆ Z(¬β). We conclude that FP (α) ⊆ FP (β).

We shall now consider the composition of measurements. First we show thesymmetry of the preservation relation.

Lemma 6.6 [Idempotence, Interference] For any α, β ∈ M , α preserves β iff βpreserves α.

Proof. Assume α preserves β, and x ∈ FP (α). By Idempotence, β(x) ∈FP (β). Since α preserves β, α(β(x)) ∈ FP (β). The assumptions of Interfer-ence are satisfied and we conclude that β(x) ∈ FP (α). We have shown that βpreserves α.

Lemma 6.7 [Illegitimate, Idempotence, Interference, Negation] For any α, β ∈ M ,if α β ∈ M , then FP (α β) = FP (α) ∩ FP (β).

Proof. Since Z(α) ⊆ Z(α β), Lemma 6.5 implies that FP (α β) ⊆ FP (α).By Idempotence of β, FP (α β) ⊆ FP (β). We see that FP (α β) ⊆ FP (α) ∩ FP (β).But the inclusion in the other direction is obvious.

We shall now show that the converse of Composition holds.

Lemma 6.8 [Illegitimate, Idempotence, Interference, Negation] For any α, β ∈ M ,if α β ∈ M , then β preserves α.

Page 74: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

74CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

Proof. By Lemma 6.7, FP (α β) ⊆ FP (α). For any x, (α β)(x) is thereforea fixpoint of α. Assume x ∈ FP (α). Then, (α β)(x) = β(x) is a fixpoint of α.

Lemma 6.9 [Illegitimate, Idempotence, Interference, Composition, Negation]For any α, β ∈ M , α β ∈ M , iff β preserves α.

Proof. The only if part is Lemma 6.8. The if part is Composition.

Lemma 6.10 [Illegitimate, Idempotence, Interference, Composition, Negation]For any α, β ∈ M , α β ∈ M iff β α ∈ M .

Proof. By Lemmas 6.9 and 6.6.

Lemma 6.11 [Illegitimate, Idempotence, Interference, Composition, Cumula-tivity, Negation] For any α, β ∈ M , α β ∈ M iff α and β commute, i.e., α β = β α.

Proof. Assume, first, that α β ∈ M . By Lemma 6.10, β α ∈ M . ByLemma 6.7, FP (α β) = FP (β α), which implies the claim by Lemma 6.2.

Assume, now that α and β commute. We claim that α preserves β: indeed,if β(x) = x, then β(α(x)) = α(β(x)) = α(x) and therefore, by Composition,β α is a measurement.

Lemma 6.12 [Illegitimate, Idempotence, Interference, Composition, Cumula-tivity, Negation] For any α, β ∈ M , if FP (α) ⊆ FP (β), then α β = β α = α.

Proof. If FP (α) ⊆ FP (β), then, clearly α β = α by Idempotence of α.Therefore α β ∈ M and, by Lemma 6.11, α and β commute.

6.6 Connectives in M-algebras

6.6.1 Connectives for arbitrary measurements

The reader has noticed that negation plays a central role in our presentationof M-algebras, through the Negation requirement and that this requirement iscentral in the derivation of many of the lemmas of Section 6.5. Indeed, Nega-tion expresses the orthogonality structure so fundamental in orthomodular andHilbert spaces. The requirement of Negation corresponds, for the logician, tothe existence of a connective whose properties are those of a classical negation.Indeed, for example, as shown by Corollary 6.1, double negations may be ig-nored, as is the case in classical logic. In [?], the logical language presentedincludes negation, interpreted as orthogonal complement, and this is consistentwith our interpretation. But [?] also defines other connectives: conjunction,disjunction and many later works on Quantum Logic define also implication(sometimes a number of implications). Our treatment in this chapter does not

Page 75: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.6. CONNECTIVES IN M-ALGEBRAS 75

require such connectives, or more precisely, our treatment does not require thatsuch connectives be defined between any pair of measurements.

Consider conjunction. One may consider only M-algebras in which, for anyα, β ∈ M there is a measurement α ∧ β ∈ M such that FP (α ∧ β) = FP (α) ∩ FP (β).There are many such M-algebras, since any M-algebra defined by an orthomod-ular space and the family of all its (projections on) closed subspaces has thisproperty since the intersection of any two closed subspaces is a closed sub-space. But our requirements do not imply the existence of such a measurementα, β ∈ M for every α and β.

For disjunction, one may consider requiring that for any α, β ∈ M therebe a measurement α ∨ β ∈ M such that Z(α ∨ β) = Z(α) ∪ Z(β), and the M-algebras defined by Hilbert spaces satisfy this requirement. Not all M-algebrassatisfy this requirement.

For implication, in general M-algebras, assuming conjunction and disjunc-tion, one could require that for any α, β ∈ M there be a measurement α → β ∈ Msuch that FP (α → β) = FP (¬α ∨ (α ∧ β)), and the M-algebras defined byHilbert spaces satisfy this requirement. Indeed, works in Quantum Logic some-times consider more than one implication, see [?].

It is an important feature of M-algebras is that conjunction, disjunction andimplication are defined only for commuting measurements. The next section willshow that this restriction leads to a classical propositional logic. If one restrictsoneself to commuting measurements, then, contrary to the unrestricted connec-tives of Birkhoff and von Neumann [?], conjunction and disjunction distribute,and, in fact, the logic obtained is classical.

6.6.2 Connectives for commuting measurements

Let us take a second look at propositional connectives in M-algebras, with par-ticular attention to their commutation properties. We shall assume that 〈X, M〉is an M-algebra.

Negation

Negation asserts the existence of a negation for every measurement. Let usstudy the commutation properties of ¬α.

Lemma 6.13 ∀α, β ∈ M , if α commutes with β, then ¬α commutes with β.

Proof. Assume α commutes with β. We shall see that β preserves ¬α.Let x ∈ FP (¬α). We have x ∈ Z(α). But (α β)(x) = (β α)(x). Therefore0 = α(β(x)), β(x) ∈ Z(α) and β(x) ∈ FP (¬α). We have shown that β preserves¬α. By Composition, (¬α) β ∈ M and, by Lemma 6.11, ¬α commutes withβ.

Corollary 6.2 ∀α, β ∈ M , α and β commute iff ¬α and β commute iff α and¬β commute iff ¬α and ¬β commute.

Page 76: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

76CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

Proof. By Lemma 6.13 and Corollary 6.1.

Conjunction

We shall now define a conjunction between commuting measurements.

Definition 6.5 For any commuting measurements α, β ∈ M , the conjunctionα ∧ β is defined by: α ∧ β = α β = β α.

By Lemma 6.11, the conjunction, as defined, is indeed a measurement.

Lemma 6.14 For any commuting α, β ∈ M , the conjunction α ∧ β is the uniquemeasurement γ such that FP (γ) = FP (α) ∩ FP (β).

Proof. By Lemmas 6.2 and 6.7.

One immediately sees that conjunction among commuting measurements is as-sociative, commutative and that α ∧ α = α for any α ∈ M .

Let us now study the commutation properties of conjunction.

Lemma 6.15 ∀α, β, γ ∈ M , that commute in pairs, α ∧ β commutes with γ.

Proof.(α ∧ β) γ = (α β) γ = α (β γ) = α (γ β) =

(α γ) β = (γ α) β = γ (α β) = γ (α ∧ β)

Disjunction

One may now define a disjunction between two commuting measurements in theusual, classical, way.

Definition 6.6 For any commuting measurements α, β ∈ M , the disjunctionα ∨ β is defined by: α ∨ β = ¬(¬α ∧ ¬β).

By Corollary 6.2, the measurements ¬α and ¬β commute, therefore their con-junction is well-defined and the definition of disjunction is well-formed.

The commutation properties of disjunction are easily studied.

Lemma 6.16 ∀α, β, γ ∈ M that commute in pairs, α ∨ β commutes with γ.

Proof. Obvious from Definition 6.6 and Lemmas 6.13 and 6.15.

The following is easily proved: use Definition 6.6, Negation and Lem-mas 6.5, 6.2 and 6.11.

Lemma 6.17 For any commuting measurements, α and β, their disjunctionα ∨ β is the unique measurement γ such that Z(γ) = Z(α) ∩ Z(β).

Lemma 6.18 If α, β ∈ M commute, then FP (α) ∪ FP (β) ⊆ FP (α ∨ β).

Page 77: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.6. CONNECTIVES IN M-ALGEBRAS 77

The inclusion is, in general, strict.

Proof. Since Z(α ∨ β) ⊆ Z(α), by Lemma 6.5.

Contrary to what holds in classical logic, in M-algebras we can have a state xthat satisfies the disjunction α∨ β but does not satisfy any one of α or β. Thisis particularly interesting when α and β represent measurements of differentvalues for the same physical quantity. In this case, one is tempted to say thatsuch an x satisfies α not entirely but in part and β in some other part. In theHilbertian formalism x is a linear combination of the two vectors α(x) and β(x):x = c1α(x) + c2β(x). The coefficients c1 and c2 describe in what proportionsthe state x, that satisfies α∨β satisfies α and β respectively. The considerationof structures richer than M-algebras that include this quantitative informationis left for future work.

Implication

Implication (→) is probably the most interesting connective. It will play acentral role in our treatment of connectives.

Definition 6.7 For any commuting measurements α, β ∈ M , the implicationα → β is defined by: α → β = ¬(α ∧ ¬β).

By Corollary 6.2, the measurements α and ¬β commute, therefore their con-junction is well-defined and the definition of implication is well-formed.

The commutation properties of implication are easily studied.

Lemma 6.19 ∀α, β, γ ∈ M that commute in pairs, α → β commutes with γ.

Proof. Obvious from Definition 6.7 and Lemmas 6.13 and 6.15.

The following is easily proved: use Definition 6.7, Negation and Lem-mas 6.5, 6.2 and 6.11.

Lemma 6.20 For any commuting measurements, α and β, their implicationα → β is the unique measurement γ such that Z(γ) = FP (α) ∩ Z(β).

Lemma 6.20 characterises the zeros of α → β. Our next result characterizesthe fixpoints of α → β in a most telling and useful way.

Lemma 6.21 For any commuting measurements, α and β, their implicationα → β is the unique measurement γ such that FP (γ) = x ∈ X | α(x) ∈ FP (β).Proof. Assume α and β commute, and x ∈ X. Now, α(x) ∈ FP (β) iff(by Negation) α(x) ∈ Z(¬β) iff (α (¬β))(x) = 0 iff (by Definition 6.5 andLemma 6.13) (α ∧ (¬β))(x) = 0 iff x ∈ Z(α ∧ (¬β)) iff (by Negation) x ∈FP (¬(α ∧ (¬β))) iff (by Definition 6.7) x ∈ FP (α → β).

The following is immediate.

Corollary 6.3 For any commuting measurements α and β, if x ∈ FP (α) andx ∈ FP (α → β), then x ∈ FP (β).

Page 78: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

78CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

One may now ask whether the propositional connectives we have definedamongst commuting measurements behave classically. In particular, assumingthat measurements α, β and γ commute in pairs, does the distribution law hold,i.e., is it true that (α ∨ β) ∧ γ = (α ∧ γ) ∨ (β ∧ γ). In the next section, we shallshow that amongst commuting measurements propositional connectives behaveclassically.

6.7 Amongst commuting measurements connec-tives are classical

Let us, first, remark on the commutation properties described in Lemmas 6.13,6.15, 6.16 and 6.19. Those lemmas imply that, given any set A ⊆ M of mea-surements in an M-algebra, such that any two elements of A commute, one mayconsider the propositional calculus built on A (as atomic propositions). Eachsuch proposition describes a measurement in the original M-algebra (an elementof M) and all such measurements commute. We shall denote by Prop(A) thepropositions built on A.

We shall now show that, in any such Prop(A) all classical propositionaltautologies hold at every state x ∈ X.

Theorem 6.1 Let 〈X, M〉 be an M-algebra. Let A ⊆ M be a set of commut-ing measurements. If α ∈ Prop(A) is a classical propositional tautology, thenFP (α) = X.

The converse does not hold, since it is easy to build M-algebras in which, forexample, a given measurement holds at every state.

We shall use the axiomatic system for propositional calculus found on p. 31of Mendelson’s [?] to prove that any classical tautology α built out using onlynegation and implication has the property claimed. We shall then show thatconjunction and disjunction may be defined in terms of negation and implicationas usual. The proof will proceed in six steps: Modus Ponens, the three axiomschemes of Mendelson’s system, conjunction and disjunction. The reader shouldnotice how tightly the three axiom schemas correspond to the commutationassumption. The reader of this deaft will notice that it would of course beappropriate to use the axiom system we gave in Chapter 1. This is routine andwill be done in the final version.

Lemma 6.22 For any commuting measurements α and β, if FP (α) = X andFP (α → β) = X, then FP (β) = X.

Proof. By Corollary 6.3.

Lemma 6.23 For any commuting measurements α and β,

FP (α → (β → α)) = X.

Page 79: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

6.7. AMONGST COMMUTING MEASUREMENTS CONNECTIVES ARE CLASSICAL79

Proof. Since α and β commute, for any x ∈ X: β(α(x)) = α(β(x)), there-fore, by Idempotence, we have β(α(x)) ∈ FP (α). By Lemma 6.21, for any x,α(x) ∈ FP (β → α). By the same lemma: x ∈ FP (α → (β → α)).

Lemma 6.24 For any pairwise commuting measurements α, β and γ

FP ((α → (β → γ)) → ((α → β) → (α → γ))) = X.

Proof. By Lemma 6.21, it is enough to show that for any x ∈ X, if y =(α → (β → γ))(x), then, if we define z = (α → β)(y), and define w = α(z), thenwe have: γ(w) = w. But since all the measurements above commute, by Idem-potence, the state w satisfies α → (β → γ), α → β and α. By Corollary 6.3, wsatisfies β and β → γ. For the same reason w satisfies γ.

Lemma 6.25 For any commuting measurements α and β,

FP ((¬β → ¬α) → ((¬β → α) → β)) = X.

Proof. By Lemma 6.21, it is enough to show that for any x ∈ X, if y =(¬β → ¬α)(x), then, if we define z = (¬β → α)(y) then we have: β(z) = z.But since all the measurements above commute, by Idempotence, the statez satisfies ¬β → ¬α and ¬β → α. Therefore, by Lemma 6.21, (¬β)(z) satisfiesboth ¬α and α. Therefore (¬β)(z) = 0 and therefore, by Negation, z ∈ FP (β).

Lemma 6.26 For any commuting measurements α and β, α ∧ β = ¬(α → ¬β).

Proof.

FP (¬(α → ¬β)) = Z(α → ¬β) = FP (α) ∩ Z(¬β) = FP (α) ∩ FP (β).

By Negation, Lemma 6.20 and Negation. The conclusion then follows fromLemma 6.14.

Lemma 6.27 For any commuting measurements α and β, α ∨ β = (¬α) → β.

Proof.Z((¬α) → β) = FP (¬α) ∩ Z(β) = Z(α) ∩ Z(β).

By Lemma 6.20 and Negation. The conclusion then follows from Lemma 6.17.

We have proved Theorem 6.1. The next Section will consider separable M-algebras.

Page 80: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

80CHAPTER 6. THE DYNAMIC VIEWPOINT: PROPOSITIONS AS OPERATORS

6.8 Separable M-algebras

Lemma 6.28 In a separable M-algebra, a measurement is classical if and onlyif it commutes with any measurement.

Proof. Suppose α is classical. Consider any x ∈ X and any β ∈ M . Sinceα is classical we know that x ∈ FP (α) or x ∈ Z(α) and β(x) ∈ FP (α) orβ(x) ∈ Z(α). If x ∈ FP (α), by Lemma 6.3, β(x) ∈ Z(α) implies x ∈ Z(β)and(α β)(x) = 0 = (β α)(x). But β(x) ∈ FP (α) implies (α β)(x) = β(x) =(β α)(x).

If x ∈ Z(α) and β(x) ∈ FP (α), by Lemma 6.4, β(x) = 0 and (α β)(x) =0 = (β α)(x). If β(x) ∈ Z(α), then (α β)(x) = 0 = (β α)(x).

Suppose, now that α commutes with any measurement β. By contradic-tion, assume α(x) 6= 0 and α(x) 6= x. By Separability there is some measure-ment γ such that x ∈ FP (γ) and α(x) 6∈ FP (γ). But α and γ commute and:(α γ)(x) = (γ α)(x) = α(x). We see that α(x) ∈ FP (γ), a contradiction.

Note that a measurement α is classical (see Definition 6.4) iff Def(α) = X.

Lemma 6.29 If α is classical, so is ¬α. If α and β are classical, then so areα ∧ β, α ∨ β and α → β.

Proof. If α is classical, Def(α) = X and therefore Def(¬α) = X. For con-junction (α ∧ β)(x) = (α β)(x) = (β α)(x). If either α(x) or β(x) is 0 then(α ∧ β)(x) = 0, otherwise α(x) = x = β(x) and (α ∧ β)(x) = x. The definitionsof disjunction and implication in terms of negation and conjunction, then ensurethe claim.

Page 81: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 7

The Local Viewpoint:States as Logical Entities

7.1 What can logic do about quantum mechan-ics?

The question whether we need a ’new logic’ in order to reason properly inquantum theory is asked frequently. Do we have to depart from classical logicin building ’quantum logic’ and if so, how? The answer to this question givenby most physicists is that we do not. In fact, physicists put quantum mechanicsto good use in an unprecedently successful way, and in this do they not useclassical logic? Popper in [51] denies any need to depart from classical logic inorder to reason properly in quantum mechanics.

Why then did the question arise at all? As we already saw, the question of’the logic of quantum mechanics’ was, in the scientific literature, first raised byBirkhoff and von Neumann in their seminal 1936 paper. As discussed at lengthin Chapter 5, their motivation for trying to discover the ’logic of quantummechanics’ was the fact that they considered the novel features of quantummechanics such as the uncertainty relations to be logical in nature. Since thesefeatures are not reflected in classical logic there is, according to Birkhoff-vonNeumann, a need to construct a (logical) ’calculus’ in which they are actuallyrepresented.

Later on it was Putnam, Finkelstein and others who put forward a view ofquantum logic which for some time attracted considerable attention. Centralto this paradigm is the idea that logic may be ”empiricial”. Putnam and hisfollowers argued that the role of logic in quantum mechanics was similar to thatof geometry in the theory of relativity. In the theory of relativity Euclideangeometry, which in Newtonian physics was still considered a priori, had to berevised on empirical grounds. In quantum mechanics, Putnam argued, it is(classical) logic that needs revision on empirical grounds. Similar to the way

81

Page 82: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

82CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

the theory of relativity teaches us the ”real” geometry it is quantum mechanicsthat teaches us the ”real” logic. This is undoubtedly an attractive idea which,however we do not pursue in this book, at least not in the form it was putforward by Putnam and his followers. We will, however, come back to this inthe last chapter.

In this book we adopt a different attitude which seems already implicit in theBirkhoff-von Neumann paper. Let us recall what they write in the Introduction:”The object of the present paper is to discover what logical structure one mayhope to find in physical theories which, like quantum mechanics, do not conformto classical logic”.

In fact, this is the task we pose ourselves: searching for logical structuresin quantum mechanics. The procedure is this. We take a close look at Hilbertspace and, as a result, identify and study certain logical structures implicit inHilbert space. We then pursue the question whether these logical structuresrepresent essential features of the formalism of quantum mechanics. This is toserve a twofold purpose. First, as already pointed out, we then have a preciseframework at our disposal in which the somewhat vague intuitions that aresuggested by Chapter 8 can be reflected and stated in a precise way. Thislogical framework can then play the role of a platform of discourse on which wecan give a precise logical meaning to certain intuitions that arise naturally inview of the ’strange’ aspects of quantum reality described in Chapter 8.

Can these structures shed light on the formalism of quantum mechanics?We would like to make the point that they in fact can. So the answer to thequestion asked in the title of this section is that logic (as a science) can detectand study logical structures in the formalism of quantum mechanics which areessential for the understanding of the formalism itself.

Are there any guidelines that may help us in our search for these structures?Are there any traits of quantum mechanics itself that could suggest certaindirections of investigation. Let us speculate a bit about this.

As a good starting point we may look at the relationship between classicaland quantum mechanics. We may start by analysing the way how quantummechnics departs from classical mechanics. Given that quantum mechanics, asis often claimed more or less vaguely, does not conform to classical logic, thenit is reasonable to ask how the transition from classical to quantum mechanicsis reflected in the logical structures we are looking for.

There are various ways of viewing the relationship between classical andquantum mechanics. Since in classical mechanics we have no uncertainty rela-tions it is the uncertainty relations that are often regarded as constituting theessential difference. Another crucial difference concerns the role of measure-ment. In classical mechanics a measurement does not involve a change of thestate of the system measured. The fact that in quantum mechanics measure-ment does, in general, involve such a change of state is undoubtedly an essentialdifference between classical and quantum physics. Classical mechanics is oftenconsidered to be a limiting case of quantum mechanics as classical (Newtonian)mechanics is a limiting case of the theory of relativity. We may ask the questionhow these observations are reflected in the logical structures we find. What

Page 83: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.1. WHAT CAN LOGIC DO ABOUT QUANTUM MECHANICS? 83

are uncertainty relations from the logical point of view?. We already remarkedin chapter 2 that, logically, the presence of uncertainty relations is reflected asnon-monotonicity of the logical structures implicit in the formalism of quantummechanics. In Chapter 6 we took the fact that there may be a change of statein quantum measurement as an inspiration for the dynamic view of propositionsas acting on states rather than just being true or false in these states.

There is, however, a general feeling expressed in a vast body of literature,popular scientific and seriously philosophical alike, that the fairly obvious dif-ferences between classical and quantum mechanics mentioned above are not thewhole story. Rather the general impression seems to be that the way how quan-tum mechanics departs from classical mechanics touches on deeper ground. Inthe next chapter we will discuss the famous Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR)argument put forward in a paper entitled ”Can the quantum-mechanical de-scription of reality be considered complete?” see [13]. In the EPR argumentthe term ”element of reality” plays a crucial role. EPR take it for grantedthat (physical) reality is to be viewed as consisting of separate ”elements ofreality”. And, in fact, once this fragmented view of reality is accepted it ishard to avoid the EPR conclusion that quantum mechanics does not provide acomplete description of physical reality. Therefore, if quantum mechanics is infact a complete description of physical reality as seems to be generally assumednowadays, then something must be wrong with this view of reality. It seemsthat the way quantum mechanics departs from classical mechanics is of an evenmore profound nature than the way the (special) theory of relativity departsfrom lassical mechanics. In the latter case we ’just’ have to abandon our viewson space and time. In the case of quantum mechanics it seems that we haveto abandon our views on the very nature of reality. This is all pervading theliterature on the foundations of quantum mechanics be it popular scientific orseriously philosophical. It is the intuition of oneness, interconnectedness andwholeness, which is prevalent in Eastern thought for instance, that finds strongsupport in quantum mechanics. But this is the realm of intuition and metaphor,perhaps even of philosophy, and it is hard to make something scientific of thisat the level of ordinary discourse.

How can we reflect the shift in our perception of reality which is forced uponus in the transition from classical mechanics to quantum mechanics at the level oflogic? A possible answer is this. Classical mechanics and classical logic conformto each other and the view of reality that underlies classical mechanics alsounderlies classical logic. If, as seems to be the case, our ’classical’ view of realityis to be revised in quantum mechanics, we must ask the question whether logic,i.e. the quantum logic to be constructed, can account for quantum mechanicsif it does not reflect this shift. In this book we propose a way of departingfrom classical logic for the sake of constructing quantum logic which may beregarded as reflecting this intuition. This is one important feature of our wayof departing from classical logic.

Page 84: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

84CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

7.2 States as logical entities

The concept of a state of a physical system plays a fundamental role both inclassical and in quantum physics. In our study of M-algebras, which constituteour first abstraction from the Hilbertian formalism, we treated the concept ofa state of a physical system as a primitive notion. In this chapter we ask thequestion what is a state from the logical point of view. Can we view the statesof a physical system as logical entities themselves and if so, what is the natureof these logical entities?

In classical physics, the concept of a state is, from the logical point of view,unproblematic. Logically, in classical physics a state is a complete classicaltheory. It can be identified with the set of all physical statements true aboutthe system. In this sense the state of the system at a certain point in time fullycontains all the information about the system. What in classical mechanics isparticularly convenient is the fact that once we know the momenta and thepositions of the particles constituting the system, we know all relevant physicalproperties. Therefore, from the logical point of view, the state can be describedby a single proposition, namely by the proposition specifying all values of themomenta and positions at a given time. From this we can then compute (deduce)the values of all relevant physical quantities. This is what in classical mechanicsis known as phase space. So, the logical analogue of the concept of a state inclassical mechanics is that of a complete classical theory.

This simple concept of state is based on the view underlying classical me-chanics that a physical system possesses certain properties and does not possessothers. The propositions expressing the physical properties a physical systemcan possess accordung to classical mechanics may be viewed as having the formA = µ, where A denotes a physical quantity (observable) such as position, mo-mentum, energy... In any given state, for any observable A the propsition A = µis true for exactly one (real) value µ. For any value ρ 6= µ the proposition A = ρis false which is equivalent to ¬A = ρ.

For any physically meaningful property the system either possesses it or not.Any given proposition holds or does not hold at any given point in time. In thelatter case it is, by classical logic, the negation of the proposition that holds.Take for instance position Q and consider the propsition Q = µ, take moreovermomentum P and consider the proposition P = λ. Then according to classicalmechanics these propositions or their negations are true. We may for instancehave Q = µ is true and P = λ true. In this case we can deduce any otherproposition true about the system. We may for instance infer a proposition ofthe form ¬(E = ρ), where E denotes kinetic energy. Obviously, this concept ofa state rests on classical logic and in particular on the notion of truth underlyingclassical logic.

How can we, in classical physics, know if the system possesses a certainproperty, how can we know that, say A = µ is true? The answer is thatgiven this proposition we can at least in principle fnd out whether it is truevia measurement. A = µ is true if and only if a measurement of the physicalquantity A yields the value µ. Whenever we measure A we always get µ and no

Page 85: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.2. STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES 85

other value as a result of measurement.Now, what’s different in quantum mechanics? Why can’t we represent the

state of a quantum system analogously, namely by the set of those propositionsthat are true or false in this state? The reason is that, in quantum mechanics,the term ’is true’ is far less clear. In classical mechanics we said that ’to betrue’ may, roughly, be taken as ’be measured’ or at least ’to be measurable’.In quantum mechanics things aren’t that simple. Given a state x in quantummechanics and a proposition A = µ. Suppose we perform a measurement ofan observable A in x. Then the following three cases may occur. First, theprobability to measure µ is 1 in which case we may reasonably say that A = µis true (in state x). Second, the probability to get µ as a result of measurementmay be 0. In this case we may reasonably say that A = µ is false or, equivalently,¬(A = µ) is true. In quantum mechanics there is, however, a third case whichmarks the difference with classical mechanics. Namely, the probability to getµ may be greater than zero and smaller than one. Let us for the moment callthese propositions contingent with respect to x. It is then obviously insufficientto represent the state x by the set of those propositions of the form A = λthat are true or false in x because this does not give us any infomation aboutthe contingent propositions and their probabilities. It seems that a properrepresentation of a quantum state must specify probabilities. In a purely logicaltreatment of the concept of a physical state we should, however, try to avoidspecifying probabilities.

Let us now reflect on the problem of representing states within the frameworkof M-algebras. Given an M-algbra 〈X, M〉 and a state x ∈ X. Again, it isinsufficient to represent x as the set of those propositions α such that x ∈ FP (α)or x ∈ FP (¬α. In fact, there exist, generally, propositions such that neitherx ∈ FP (α) nor x ∈ FP (¬α). These propositions act on x in that they neitherleave it unchanged nor send it to zero. They are neither ’true’ nor ’false’.

We may think of the action of propositions on states in an M-algebra as asort of coming true rather than being true. We may say that α is true in xif x ∈ FP (α) and x is false in x if x ∈ FP (¬α. Otherwise, i.e. in case thatα(x) = y 6= x and α(x) 6= 0 we may say that α comes true in x. Thus α comestrue in x if it is true in α(x). Hence the representation of the state x mustgive us information not just on what is true or false in x but about what comestrue in x. Thus in an M-algebra it is the coming true of a proposition thatreplaces or generalises the being true of a proposition in classical logic. Thisis, in an M-algebra, the dynamic analogue of the static concept of being truein classical logic. However, coming true in x involves a different state whichin turn must be specified. Thus, intuitively, we must require the logical entityrepresenting a state x as also specifying other states, namely all those states inwhich a proposition may end up true when it comes true in state x.

Technically speaking, it’s as follows. The logical entity representing a statein classical logic, namely a complete theory, contains (encodes) all propositionstrue or false in this state. When, however, we are concerned with propositionsthat act on the state or, as we said, have the property of coming true ratherthan being true in state x, then the logical representation of x must encode

Page 86: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

86CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

all propositions that come true at x, in other words the logical representationof a state x must encode the action of the propositions on x. The action of aproposition on x however yields a new state y and therefore the state x mustencode other states. So we inevitably hit here on the phenomenon of encodednessof states in other states which will play a dominant role in our study of holisticlogics introduced in chapter 9. We will see that, there, a state is a logical entitythat encodes (almost) all other states including itself.

7.3 M-algebras and their languages

In this chapter we will study several special types of M-algebras. We will de-fine these M-algebras by introducing additional connectives between arbitrarymeasurements. Generally, we have only one connective in an M-algebra that isdefined for arbitrary measurements, namely negation. In this chapter we willconsider M-algebras which for instance have an implication defined between ar-bitrary measurements. We call these M-algebras Implication M-algebras. Wewill also consider M-algebras having a generally defined conjunction. We callthese algebras Conjunction M-algebras.

Let us now desccribe the proper (logical) languages suited to these M-algebras. Given an M-algebra A = 〈X, M〉. Then consider a set V arX ofvariables of the same cardinality as X. Suppose we have an M-algebra with ad-ditional connectives, say conjunction, i.e. a Conjunction M-algebra. The properlanguage of the M-algebra A denoted by L¬,∧ is then defined by the followingclauses.

• Every variable, i.e. an element of V arX is a formula of L¬,∧.

• If α is a formula of L¬,∧, sois¬α

• If α and β are formulas of L¬,∧, so is α ∧ β.

It is now obvious how to define the corresponding language L¬,;ofanM −algebraorthelanguageL¬,;,∧ of an M-algebra which is both an Implication M-algebra and a Conjunction M-algebra.

We can describe this somewhat informally as follows. A precise definition isroutine and will be given in the final version. Given an M-algebra A = 〈X, M〉.Assume we have certain connectives in A, say ¬, ∧, an implication ;... Notehat in an M-algebra connectives are algebraic operations, i.e. functions fromM × M to M . We need to construct a propositional lnguage suited to A.We can do this as follows. Choose a set of propositional variables V ar of thesame cardinality as M and let V : V ar → M be a bijection. Consider thepropositional language LM built up from V ar and the usual connectives asdescribed in chapter 2. The function V can then be extended to LM in uniqueway such that V (¬α)) = ¬V (α), V (α ∧ β) = V (α ∧ β)...Note that on the lefthand side the connectives are logical connectives in the usual sense, namely theconnectives of the propositional language LM whereas the connectives on the

Page 87: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.4. IMPLICATION M-ALGEBRAS 87

right hand side are the corresponding algebraic operations of the M-algebra.Since V is a bijection respecting the logical connectives we may identify α, i.e.a formula of LM with V (α) and denote V (α) again by α.

7.4 Implication M-algebras

In our study of M-algebras we dealt for the most part with what we call globalproperties. This also applies to the Birkhoff-von Neumann paper. What isa global property? A global property is a property concerned with sets ofstates. We for instance proved in Chapter 6 that in any M-algebra commutingpropositions obey classical logic. Since propositions are functions from the setof states into itself this property of an M-algebra is a global property.

In this section we focus on what we call local properties. This is what wemean by local viewpoint. By a local property we mean a property concernedwith a certain fixed state, properties of individual states so to speak rather thanproperties concerning sets of states. Some of the properties we already dealtwith in connection with M-algebras are local properties. Recall for instancethe axiom of Interference. The study of local properties of M-algebras gives usinsight into the logical nature of physical states.

However, the concept of an M-algebra as introduced and studied in chapter6 is still too general for an investigation of this sort. For this we need toconsider more special structures. We will call the structures suitable for suchan investigation Implication M-algebras.

In our study of M-algbras in Chapter 6 we admitted only one generallydefined connective, namely negation, i.e. for any proposition α its negation ¬αis defined. All the other connectives, conjunction, disjunction, implication aredefined for commuting propositions only. And, with this restriction, we provedthat they behave classically. This generalises the well known fact that a set ofmutually commuting projections in Hilbert space forms a Boolean algebra.

In an Implication M-algebras we allow for another connective defined be-tween arbitrary propositions, namely implication, which we will denote by ;.This connective has, in terms of measurement, the following intuitive meaning:α ; β means: ”If we measure α we (also) get β”. We will see that for commut-ing measurements this implication will coincide with the implication we alreadyhave in this case.

In Chapter 6 we proved the following.Let 〈X, M〉 be an M -algebra, x ∈ X and α, β ∈ M be two commuting

measurements. Then we have

x ∈ FP (α → β) iff α(x) ∈ FP (β)

Given an M-algebra 〈X, M〉 and consider a fixed state x ∈ X. We now definea binary relation |∼x between arbitrary measurements (propositions) as follows.

Definition 7.1 Let 〈X, M〉 be an M-algebra and x ∈ X. Then define the binaryrelation |∼x as follows. Given α, β ∈ M . Then we say α |∼x β if α(x) ∈ FP (β).

Page 88: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

88CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

We may, intuitively, think of these relations as consequence relations al-though in the general situation of M-algebras we cannot expect them to satisfythe minimal conditions of Chapter 2. But we will see in chapter 10 that inthe case of a Hilbert space these conditions are in fact satisfied and thus thesebinary relations may rightfully called consequence relations.

In the sequel we write |∼x α for > |∼x α.

Lemma 7.1 α |∼x β iff |∼α(x) β iff α(x) ∈ FP (β)

Proof. By definition. ¥

Let us now say what we mean by an Implication M-algebra.

Definition 7.2 We call an M-algebra 〈X, M〉 an Implication M-algebra if thereexists a function I : M × M → M such that for any x ∈ X, α |∼x β iffx ∈ FP (I(α, β)) ir equivalently α(x) ∈ FP (β).

Note that the function I is, if it exists, uniquely determined because a mea-surement is uniquely determined by its set of fixpoints. Call it the implicationof the M-algebra. As aleady mentioned we also write α ; β for I(α, β).

Recall that orthomodular spaces and in particular Hilbert spaces give rise toan M-algebra in a natural way. By Proposition 3.4 the implication I is givenby I(α, β = α⊥ ∨ (α ∧ β), i.e. the Sasaki hook. We will see shortly that this isnot accidental.

Lemma 7.2 If α and β commute we have α ; β = α → β.

Proof. By the definition of ; and Lemma ?. ¥

7.5 Conjunction M-algebras

Definition 7.3 We call an M-algebra 〈X,M〉 a Conjunction M-algebra if thereexists a function C : M × M → M such that for any α, β ∈ M we haveFP (C(α, β)) = FP (α) ∩ FP (β). We call such a function a conjunction. ForC(α, β) we also write α ∧ β.

Again, if an M-algebra admits a conjunction, this conjunction is uniquely deter-mined because measurements are uniquely determined by their set of fixpoints.

The following lemma follows from the definition of a conjunction and lemma6.14.

Lemma 7.3 Let A be an M-algebra and C a conjunction of A. Then for com-muting measurements C agrees with the conjunction (already) defined.

Theorem 7.1 Given a conjunction M-algebra A = 〈X, M〉 with conjunctionC. Then A admits a (unique) implication I. Namely we have I(α, β) = ¬α ∨(α ∧ β) = α → (α ∧ β).

Page 89: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.6. STRONGLY SEPARABLE M-ALGEBRAS 89

Note that for any α, β ∈ M ¬α ∨ (α ∧ β) is defined. Namely we haveFP (α) ⊂ FP (α∧β). Hence α and α∧β commute by Lemma 6.12 and thus byLemma 6.13 ¬α and α ∧ β commute. The theorem says that any conjunctionM-algebra is also an Implication M-algebra.

Proof. It suffices to prove that FP (α → β) = x | α(x) ∈ FP (β). ByLemma 6.21 we have FP (α → β) = x | α(x) ∈ FP (α∧ β). By the definitionof conjunction this set is equal to x | α(x) ∈ FPα) ∩ FP (β). Since α(x) ∈FP (α), it follows that FP (α → β) = x | α(x) ∈ FP (β). ¥

Recall from chapter 3 that the connective ; defined by α ; β = ¬α∨(α∧βis called the Sasaki hook.

The proof of the following lemma is an easy exercise in classical propositionallogic.

Lemma 7.4 The Sasaki hook is classically equivalent to material implication,i.e, ` (α ; β) ↔ (α → β)

7.6 Strongly separable M-algebras

Definition 7.4 Let 〈X, M〉 be an M-algebra and x 6= 0, x ∈ X. We say that ameasurement e is a pointer to x if FP (e) = x, 0

Again, note that given x then a pointer to x is uniquely determined. Wedenote it by ex.

Let 〈X, M〉 be an M-algebra, let ex be a pointer to x. Then for any x, y ∈ Xwe have ex(y) = 0 for x ∈ Z(ex), otherwise ex(y) = x.

Proof. The first claim expresses a familiar property of negation. For thesecond claim suppose that not y ∈ Z(ex). Then ex(y) 6= 0 and ex(y) ∈FP (ex).But, sinceFP(ex) = x, 0, it follows that ex(y) = x. ¥

Definition 7.5 We call an M-algebra 〈X,M〉 a srongly separable M-algebra ifevery x ∈ X has a pointer.

Proposition 7.1 A strongly separable M-algebra A = 〈X, M〉 is separable.

Proof. Given two ditinct x, y ∈ X. Then x ∈ FP (ex) and not ∈ FP (ey) andvice versa. It follows that A is separable. ¥

Lemma 7.5 Given a strongly separable M-algebra 〈X, M〉. Given x, y ∈ M .Then ex(y) = 0 implies ey(x) = 0

Definition 7.6 Let 〈X,M〉 be an strongly separable M-algebra. Let x, y ∈ X.Then wee say that x and y are orthogonal if ex(y) = 0.

By the above proposition the relation of orthogonality is symmetric.

Page 90: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

90CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

7.6.1 States encode each other

Proposition 7.2 Let 〈X,M〉 be a strongly separable Implication M-algebra andlet x, y be non-orthogonal states. Then |∼x α implies |∼y ex ; α, equivalentlyex |∼y α

Proof. Suppose |∼x α and let y ∈ X. We know that σx(y) = x or σx(y) = 0. Inthe first case we have |∼σx(y) α. Thus σx |∼y α. This is equivalent to |∼y σx ; αIn the second case we have |∼σx α since σx = 0 and thus σx |∼x α. ¥

Let us at this point recall our intuitive reflections on the logical nature of(physical) states. We there arrived at the conclusion that, logically, (quantum)states must be represented in such a way that they encode other states. Theabove may be viewed as one way of formally expressing this property. We willelaborate on this phenomenon of mutual encodedness in Chapter 9 (on holisticlogics.

7.6.2 Positive and Negative Introspection

Lemma 7.6 Given an M-algebra 〈X, M〉 and x ∈ X with pointer σx. Then themeasurements ex, ¬ex, >, ⊥ mutually commute. They form a Bolean algebrain a natural way.

Proof. is fairly obvious BUT DO IT ¥

Lemma 7.7 Let 〈X, M〉 be a strongly separable Implication M-algebra and x ∈X. Then we have for any measurement α

• |∼x α iff ex ; α = > and thus ¬(ex ; α = 0

• |6∼x α iff ex ; α = ¬ex and thus ¬(ex ; α) = ex

Proof. For (i) suppose |∼ α. Then we have by the above lemma that FP (ex ;

α) = X and thus ex ; α = >.For (ii) assume |6∼x α and let y be orthogonal to x. Then we have by the

argument used above that |∼y ex ; α. Now suppose that y is not orthogonal tox. Then we have ex(y) = x. Assume |∼y ex ; α. This implies |∼x α contrary tothe assumption. Thus FP (ex ; α = FP (¬ex). But this means ex ; α = ¬ex.

This proves the lemma. ¥

Corollary 7.1 • |∼x α iff |∼x ex ; α

• |6∼ α iff ex¬(ex ; α)

We may view the (object formulas) ex ; α and ¬(ex ; α) as expressingmetastatements. Namely, we may, if we think of |∼x as a consequence relation,view ex ; α as saying ’α is provable in |∼x’ and ’¬(ex ; α) as saying ’α is notprovable in |∼x.

Page 91: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.6. STRONGLY SEPARABLE M-ALGEBRAS 91

7.6.3 States as self-contained logical entities

Given a strongly separable Implication M-algebra 〈X, M〉. Given a fixed x ∈ X.Let us thunk of the relation |∼x as a consequence relation, although, as alreadymentioned, these relations do not necessarily satisfy the minimal cconditionsstated in Chapter 2. So, intuitively, we regard, logically, a stae x as a sort ofstate of provability. We then define a meta-language MLx in which we canmake statements about the state x, more precisely about provability in state x.Let us give some motivation for the way we define this language. What do weexpect it to be capable of expressing?

Given two propositions (measurements) α and β such that α |∼x β. Thissays in ordinary language: ”β follows from α” or synonymously ”β is derivablefrom α”. We want the metalanguage, which is to be a formal language, to beable to express this. We therefore need a meta-connective which we denoteby DER reminiscent of ”derivable” expressing this. Thus in the metalanguageDER(α, β) says that α |∼x β. Clearly, we want to combine statements of theform DER(α, β) by the usual propsitional connectives so that we may able toexpress say ”If β is derivable from α, then γ is not derivable from β.”

Another feature of the metalanguage is that it should not contain statementsof the object language, i.e. measurements. The meta-language is intended to beabout measurements. A measurement (proposition) itself is thus not a metas-tatement. The metalanguage will have to be constructed in such a way thatmeasurements, i.e. object formulas, are in the scope of the metaoperator DER.In the sequel we will identify measurements with formulas of a propositionallanguage which we call the object language.

Intuitively, DERx(α, β) means ‘β is derivable from α in |∼x’.

Definition 7.7 • (i) If α, β are wffs of the object language, then DERx(α, β) ∈MLx.

• If α is a wff of the object language and ϕ ∈ MLx, then DERx(α,ϕ) ∈MLx and DERx(ϕ, α) ∈ MLx.

• If ϕ,ψ ∈ MLx, then DERx(ϕ,ψ) ∈ MLx.

• If ϕ,ψ ∈ MLx, so are ¬ϕ, ϕ ∧ ψ, ϕ ∨ ψ, ϕ → ψ.

We use the following abbreviations:

PROVxα =: DERx(>, α)

CONxα =: ¬PROVx¬α

EQUIVx(α, β) =: DERx(α, β) ∧DERx(β, α)

We now define a natural translation of the meta-language MLx into theobject language.

Definition 7.8 We define for a given state x the translation ′ as follows.

Page 92: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

92CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

• (i) If ϕ = DERx(α, β) where α and β are wff of the object language,ϕ′ = ex ; (α ; β)

• (ii) If ϕ = DERx(α, ψ), where α is a wff of the object language andψ ∈ ML, then ϕ′ = ex ; (α ; ψ′); analogously for the case DERx(ψ, α)

• (iii) If ϕ = DERx(ψ, ρ), where ψ, ρ ∈ ML ϕ′ = ex ; (ψ′ ; ρ′)

• (iv) If ϕ = ¬ψ, ϕ′ = ¬(ex ; ψ′),

• (v) If ϕ = ψ ∧ ρ, ϕ′ = ψ′ ∧ ρ′; analogously for the other connectives.

We now define the the notion of truth for MLx in a natural way. Thisdefinition of truth is in the spirit of what Smullyan calls a self-referential inter-pretation in [59] and

We study truth as a local notion. So we assume a fixed state x.

Definition 7.9 • (i) If ϕ = DERx(α, β), where α, β are wffs of the objectlanguage, then TRUE ϕ iff α |∼x β

• (ii) If ϕ = DERx(α,ψ), where α is a wff of the object language, thenTRUE ϕ iff α |∼x ψ′; analogously for the case DERx(ψ, α)

• (iii) If ϕ = DERx(ψ, ρ) for ψ, ρ ∈ ML, then TRUE ϕ iff ψ′ |∼x ρ′.

• (iv) If ϕ = ¬ψ, then TRUE ϕ iff not TRUE ψ; analogously for the otherconnectives.

• TRUE ϕ ∧ ψ if TRUE ϕ and TRUE ψ

• TRUE ϕ ∨ ψ if TRUE ϕ or TRUE ψ

• TRUE ϕ → ψ if not TRUE ϕ or TRUE ψ

Theorem 7.2 Given a strongly separable Implication M-algebra 〈X,M〉, x ∈X. Then we have for any ϕMLx, ϕ is TRUE iff |∼x ϕ′

In the follwing proof we omit the subscript x wherever it should occur.

Proof. By induction on the construction of the formulas of ML.(i) Case ϕ = DER(α, β), where and β are wff of the object language. Bydefinition TRUE ϕ means α |∼ β. But this says |∼ α ; β, which is equivalentto |∼ σ ; (α ; β). But this says that |∼ ϕ′.(ii) Case ϕ = DER(α, ψ). Suppose TRUE ϕ. By definition this says α |∼ ψ′

or equivalently |∼ σ ; (α ; ψ′). But this is exactly what |∼ ϕ′ means.(iii) Case ϕ = DER(ψ, ρ). The proof is analogous to (ii).

(iv) Case ϕ = ¬ψ. This is the crucial case. TRUE ϕ means that not TRUEψ.By the induction hypothesis this is equivalent to not |∼ ψ′, which by ‘provabilityof unprovability’ says that |∼ ¬(σ ; ψ′). But this means |∼ ϕ′.(v) Case ϕ = ψ ∨ ρ. First note that ϕ′ = ψ′ ∨ ρ′. Suppose TRUE ϕ. It follows

Page 93: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.6. STRONGLY SEPARABLE M-ALGEBRAS 93

that TRUE ψ or TRUE ρ. Without loss of generality assume TRUE ψ. Bythe induction hypothesis we have |∼ ψ′ and thus |∼ ψ′ ∨ ρ′. But this says |∼ ϕ′.

For the other direction suppose |∼ ϕ′. We need to prove that TRUE ϕ.There is a problem here, namely that, generally, |∼ ψ′ ∨ ρ′ does not imply that|∼ ψ′ or |∼ ρ′. To overcome this obstacle we first observe by inspecting thedefinition of the translation that any formula occurring as a translation is of theform σ ; ... or ¬(σ ; ... or a Boolean combination of such formulas. It thenfollows by Lemma 3 that the formulas (measurements) [ψ′] and [ρ′] are of theform >, ⊥, σ, ¬σ. We can thus treat this case by checking all combinations.

Suppose for instance that ψ′ = > and ρ′ = ¬σ. Then |∼ ψ′∨ρ′ says |∼ >∨¬σ,which is equivalent to |∼ >, i.e. |∼ ψ′. It follows by the induction hypothesisthat TRUE ψ and thus TRUE ϕ.

The other combinations are checked analogously. ¥

7.6.4 Conjunction: the source of classical inconsistency inM-algebras

We already mentioned that in [33] Kochen and Specker made, as a byproduct oftheir work on the problem of hidden variables in Quntum Mechanics, an obser-vation that sheds an interesting light on the relationship between classical logicand Birkhoff-von Neumann quantum logic. They present a classical tautologyϕ in 117 propositional variables which under a certain valuation of its variablesas subspaces of three-dimensional Hilbert space represents the zero space.

In this section we study this phenomenon of classical inconsistency in thegeneral setting of M-algebras and prove that the phenomenon discoverd byKochen and Specker is not an accident. We prove a general theorem fromwhich, in the case of a finite-dimensional orthomodular space and thus in thecase of a finite -dimensional Hilbert space, we get the existence of a quantumtautology which is a classical contradiction. LOOSELY SPEAKING, WE WILLSEE THAT CONJUNCTION IS THE CULPRIT. However, a word of cautionis in order here. What the corollary to our theorem says is that for any finite-dimensional Hilbert space there exists a classical tautology representing the zerospace. And in fact such a formula can be readily presented explicitly. What wedo not get, however, is that this tautology has the additional property that theconnectives ∧ and ∨ combine commuting measurements only as is the case inthe Kochen-Specker tautology as well as Schutte’s tautology.

Does the phenomenon described above really come as a surprise? In viewof the follwing intuitive consideration it does not. Recall Birkhoff and vonNeumann’s view of the connectives of the logic of experimental propositions.Given two experimental propositions α and β mathematically represented bythe closed subspaces a and b respectively. Suppose the observation spaces forα and β are given by the observables A and B respectively. So α says some-thing like this: ”The observable A has a value in some some subset Sa of itsobservation space” and β says: ”The observable B has a value in some subsetSb of its observation space.” Now, according to Birkhoff and von Neumann, theclosed subspace a ∩ b again represents an experimental proposition, say γ. The

Page 94: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

94CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

point now is this. Assume α and β are compatible propositions then if γ andα and β have a common observation space coming from a certain observableC. α ∧ β says something like: ”The observable C has a value in Sa ∩ Sb. The’topic’ of the experimental propositions α and β remains the same so to speak,namely the observable C is the topic of both propositions. If, however, α andβ do not commute, i.e. are not compatible, then the observation space of theexperimental proposition γ may come from an observable D unrelated to theobservables A and B. It is thus not surprising that this ’change of topic’ in-volved in the conjunction of non-commuting propositions can cause the extremedeviation from classical logic described above.

In view of the fact that any Conjunction M-algebra admits an implicationour goal is the following theorem.

Lemma 7.8 Let A = 〈X, M〉 be a strongly separable Conjunction M-algebra.Given any x ∈ X with pointer ex. Suppose that Σg ∪ ex is consistent. Thenwe have for any α

Σg ∪ ex ` α iff |∼x α

Proof. First note that a conjunction M-algebra admits a unique implication;, namely α ; β = ¬α ∨ (α ∧ β). Further recall that α |∼x β iff |∼x α ; β.

Assume |∼x α. Then we have σx ; α ∈ Σg by ?. It follows that Σg ` ex ;

α. Since ; is classically equivalent to →, i.e. material implication, we haveΣg ` ex → α. By the Deduction Theorem (see chapter 2) we get Σg ∪ex ` α.Thus the direction from right to left is proved.

For the other direction suppose Σg ∪ ex ` α and |6∼x α. Then we haveΣg∪ex ` ex → α and by negative introspection (’provability of unprovability’)|∼ ¬(ex ; α). It follows by the direction already proved that Σg∪ex ` ¬(ex →α). But this contradicts the hypothesis that Σg ∪ ex is consistent. ¥

Lemma 7.9 Let the hypothesis be as in the above lemma. Suppose that x isnot classical. Then Σg ∪ ex is inconsistent.

Proof. Assume Σg ∪ ex is consistent. Since x is not classical there exists anα such that neither |∼x α nor |∼x ¬α. It follows that

(1) |∼x ¬(ex ; α

and

(2) α |6∼ ¬(ex ; α)

By the above lemma we then have

Σg ∪ ex ` ¬(ex → α)

By classical logic we get

Σg ∪ ex ` α → ¬(ex → α)

Page 95: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.6. STRONGLY SEPARABLE M-ALGEBRAS 95

Again by the above lemma we have

|∼x α ; ¬(ex ; α)

This means

α |∼x ¬(ex ; α)

But this contradicts (2). It follows that Σg ∪ ex is inconsistent. ¥

Definition 7.10 Let A = 〈X ,M〉 be a srongly separable M-algebra. Supposewe have a family of states (xi)i∈I such that no state is orthogonal to all xi’s,equivalently if

⋂FP (¬exi

) is empty. Then we call (xi)i∈I a basis of A. We callA finite-dimensional if it has a finite basis.

Definition 7.11 Let A = 〈X, M〉 be a Conjunction M-algebra. Then we call aformula ϕ a Kochen-Specker tautology (KS-tautology for short) for A if it is a(classical) tautology and FP (ϕ) = 0.Lemma 7.10 Let A be finite dimensional conjunction M-algebra. Let xi, i =1, ..., n be a (finite) basis. Then we have FP (¬∧¬σi) = X.

Proof. We need to see that FP (∧¬σi) =

⋂FP (¬σi) = 0. Assume tere

is a non-zero state y in that intersection. This would mean that y is to everyxi, i = 1, .., n contrary to the assumption that xi, i = 1, ..., n is a basis. ¥

Lemma 7.11 Σg is closed under conjunctions.

We can now put the above lemmata together for the proof of the followingtheorem.

Theorem 7.3 Let A) = 〈X ,M〉 be a finite-dimensional strongly separable Con-junction M-algebra without classical states. Then Σg, i.e. the global theory ofA, is (classically) inconsistent and there exists a Kochen-Specker tautology forA.

Corollary 7.2 Any finite dimensional orthomodular space and thus any finite-dimensional Hilbert space of dimension at least two admits a Kochen-Speckertautology.

Remark: We may view the above theorem as saying a bit more than justgiving a sufficient condition for the existence of a Kochen-Specker tautologyin certain M-algebras. We may look at this theorem as follows. Given anImplication M-algebra A satisfying the hyptheses of the theorem. We wouldthen like to define a conjunction in A such that implication becomes definableas indicated in terms of negation and conjunction as is the case in classical logic.The theorem then says that this cannot be done in a reasonable way in the sensethat any conjunction makes the global theory of A in the connectives ¬ and ∧inconsistent. So what the theorem essentially says is that M-algebras whoseglobal theory is classically consistent do not admit a ’classical’ implication.

Page 96: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

96CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

Proof. Let xi, i = 1, ...n be a basis of A. By lemma 7.10 we have

Σg ` ¬exifor i = 1, ..n.

Thus

Σg `∧¬exi

On the other hand we have by lemmma 7.10

¬∧¬exi ∈ Σg.

Therefore Σg is inconsistent. ¥

7.6.5 Phase M-algebras

We have already seen examples of M-algebras of the sort defined above in Chap-ter 6. Orthomodular spaces, in particular Hilbert spaces, give rise to Conjunc-tion M-algebras and thus to Implication M-algebras. Note that the fact that inthese examples implication is given by the Sasaki hook is in view of TheoremrefT:implication not accidental.

The following example is motivated by the concept of phase space in classicalmechanics. That’s why we call these M-algebras Phase M-algebras.

Definition 7.12 Let L be the language of propositional logic. We call an M-algebra A = 〈X ,M〉 a Phase M-algebra if

• X = X ′ ∪ 0, where X ′ is a set of complete classical theories and 0denotes the full language.

• M is (the language) L• L acts on X as follows. Let Σ ∈ X ′ and α ∈ M , then α(Σ) = Σ if α ∈ Σ,

else α(Σ) = 0.

Note that in the simplest case a Phase M-algebra has the form described inthe above definition where X = Σ and Σ is a complete classical theory.

But we still have to prove that Phase M-algebras are in fact M-algebras.

Lemma 7.12 Any Phase M-algebra is an M-algebra.

Proof. We need to verify the axioms of M-algebra. This is straightforward.Let us just sketch this for Interference. For this note the follwing two facts. Wehave Σ ∈ FP (β iff β ∈ Σ. More generally, we have α(Σ) ∈ FP (β) iff not α ∈ Σor β ∈ Σ. In order to prove Interference we need to verify that if α(Σ) ∈ FP (β)and α(β(Σ)) ∈ FP (β) then β(Σ) ∈ FP (α). The second of the above conditionssays that α(β(Σ))) ∈ FP (β). By the above remark this is equivalent to notα ∈ β(Σ) or β ∈ β(Σ). But β ∈ FP (β) is clearly true.

¥

Page 97: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

7.6. STRONGLY SEPARABLE M-ALGEBRAS 97

7.6.6 Limiting case theorems

Classical mechanics is a limiting case of quantum mechanics. In which sense?In which sense do we have to ’pass to the limit from quantum mechanics’ inorder to get classical mechanics as the limit? There are various ways of intu-itively viewing this process. One may for instance say that ’passing to the limit’means ’passing’ from the presence of uncertainty relations to the absence ofuncertainty relations. Another way of looking at this is to say that this processis from change of state in measurement to the absence of change in measure-ment Another version is to say that it is from non-commuting measurements tocommuting measurements. In this section we study the way these intuitions arereflected in our framework of M-algebras.

Definition 7.13 Let A = 〈X, M〉 be an M-algebra and given a state x. We callx classical if if for every measurement α we have α(x) = x or α(x) = 0. Wesay that A is commutative if all its measurements commute. We say that A isclassical if all its measurements are classical. We say that A is monotonic if|∼x is monotonic for evey x ∈ X.

Observe that, if all measurements are classical so are all states and the otherway round. So we may equivalently define an M-algebra to be classical by sayingthat all its states are classical.

Lemma 7.13 If x is classical then x ∈ FP (α ; β iff α(x) = 0 or β(x) = x.

Lemma 7.14 An M-algebra is classical iff it is a Phase M-algebra.

Theorem 7.4 If an M-algebra A = 〈X, M〉 is commutative, it is monotonic.

Theorem 7.5 Let 〈X,M〉 be a strongly separable Implication M-algebra andx ∈ X. Then |∼x is monotonic iff x is classical.

Theorem 7.6 Let A = 〈X,M, 〉 be a strongly separable Implication M-algebra.Then the following conditions are equivalent:

• (i) A is commutative.

• (ii) A is monotonic.

• (iii) A is classical.

If A is a Conjunction M-algebra the above conditions are equivalent to the fol-lowing condition

• (iv) A is a Phase M-algebra.

Proof. We first prove that (i) implies ii). Given any consequence relation |∼x.We need to show that it is monotonic. Assume |∼x β. This says β(x) = x. Letα be any measurement. We then have α(β(x)) = α(x). Since α and β commuteit follows that β(α(x)) = α(x). But this says that α |∼x β.

Page 98: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

98CHAPTER 7. THE LOCAL VIEWPOINT: STATES AS LOGICAL ENTITIES

That (ii) implies (iii) can be seen as follows. Given any state x and anymeasurement α. We need to prove that either α(x) = x or α(x) = 0. So assumeα(x) 6= x. It follows by ’provability of unprovaility’ that |∼x ¬(σx ; α. Bymonotonicity we have α |∼ ¬(σx ; α). Thus α(x) ∈ FP (¬(σx ; α)).

By lemma [?] we have FP (¬(σx ; α)) = x, 0 It follows that α(x) = 0.Clearly, (iii) implies (i).NOT YET BUT EASY ¥

7.6.7 The three faces of truth

This section is intended to be a sort of summarising reflection on chapter 7.We reflect on three notions of truth that arise naturally in connection with thematerial presented in chapter 7.

There is a natural notion of truth in M-algebras. Given a measurementα and a state x. Then we say hat α holds or synonymously is true in x ifx ∈ FP (α).

The dynamic view of propositions gives rise to what earlier in this chapterwe called coming true. A proposition α comes trueinxifitistrue in α(x).

The probabilities given by Born’s rule play the role of truth values for thecoming true of propositions. This is a connection between our approach and(infinite-valued) Lukasiewicz logic. The truth values in Lukasiewicz logic are infact values for the coming true of a proposition, ’coming truth values’ ratherthan truth values.

The third notion of truth that we naturally encounter within the frameworkof M-algebras is that of self-referential truth. This notion of truth concernsmetastatements. Given an Implication M-algebra 〈x, m〉 and a state x ∈ X.Then we know by lemma [?] that all metastatements are ’equivalent’ to one ofthe following measurements (propositions): ex, ¬ex, >, ⊥. Comment on thepeculiar action of these propositions! ELABORATE ON THIS! RESUME ITIN THE LAST CHAPTER!

Page 99: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 8

Aspects of QuantumReality

In writing this chapter the authors consulted Peat’s excellent book [49] ”Ein-stein’s Moon. Bell’s Theorem and the Curious Quest for Quantum reality”.It is possible that in this draft we used a few of Peat’s formulations verbatimwithout quoting. We will check this and quote correctly in the final version.

8.1 General Remarks

In this Chapter we primarily address those readers who haven’t had much con-tact with quntum mechanics yet. We report on certain typical features of thequantum world which, to these readers, may appear unfamiliar, even strange.Our intention is to convey the impression that Quantum Mechanics touches ondeep issues even beyond the realm of physics.

Quantum mechanics is, in chronological order, the second great revolution in20th century physics. The first of these two revolutions was of course Einstein’stheory of relativity. The theory of relativity forced upon us the revision of longcherished views on space and time. This was a truly profound revision. It seems,however, that Quantum mechanics touches on even deeper ground and that ithas an even more profound impact on the way we are forced to view the physicalworld. It seems that one of these issues is that of no less and no more than thenature of (physical) reality. This is the topic of a vast body of both seriouslyscientific and philosophical as well as popular scientific literature.

In fact it is the issue of reality that constitutes the main reason for includ-ing this chapter. This issue is of course of a philosophical, possibly even of ametaphysical nature, and, since this book is about logic and not about meta-physics, the reader may rightfully ask the question why we want to reflect on ametaphysical problem in a book on modern style logic.

Roughly, the reason is this. We said that we would be searching for thelogical structures underlying quantum mechanics. Note that the emphasis is

99

Page 100: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

100 CHAPTER 8. ASPECTS OF QUANTUM REALITY

on the term structure, and, as we said previously, we are not looking for anew deductive system that could replace classical logic as a tool of reasoningabout Quantum Mechanics. Recall what Birkhoff and von Neumann say inthe Introduction of [2]: ”The object of the present paper is to discover whatlogical structures one may hope to find in physical theories which, like quantummechanics, do not conform to classical logic”. This too is our aim in this book.There is, moreover, general agreement that the search for the logical structuresunderlying quantum mechanics can only be successful if we leave the realm ofclassical logic. Somehow we will have to depart from classical logic. And, infact, all previous attempts at constructing quantum logic departed in some wayor other from classical logic.

The logical structures we want to find in quantum mechanics must reflectthe way quantum mechanics departs from classical mechanics. We also saidhat these structures should make precise at the logical level in which senseclassical logic is a limiting case of quantum mechanics. The reader, however,can appreciate this only if he has an idea of the phenomena which, at the physicallevel, are characteristic of quantum mechanics and are typical of the way howquantum mechanics departs from classical mechanics. This is the purpose ofthis chapter.

Methodologically, the procedure is this. Taking a look at the ’strange’ phe-nomena of the quantum world we will describe in this chapter impresses upon uscertain intuitions concerning the nature of quantum mechanics and in particularthe issue of reality in quantum mechanics. These intuitions will also concern theway quantum mechanics departs from Classical Mechanics, and we expect thelogical structures we want to find to reflect these intuitions. They should notonly reflect our intutions concerning the nature of quantum mechanics but alsothose concerning the relationship between classical and quantum mechanics.

What is the difference between quantum mechanics and classical mechanics?How does quantum mechanics depart from classical mechanics? We reflectedon this at several points already. Essentially we said that classical mechanics isa limiting case of Quantum Mechanics. We for instance said that we may thetransition from Quantum Mechanics to Classical Mechanics in various ways. Wemay view it as the transition from the presence of uncertainty relations to theabsence of uncertainty relations, from change of state in measurement to theabsence of cange of state and so on. This chapter serves to prepare the reader foranother more profound way of ’passing to the limit’. This view of the transitionfrom quantum Mechanics to classical Mechanics is concerned with the differentviews of reality underlying Quantum and Classical Mechanics resectively.

This is a controversial question, and it should be clear from what was saidabove that for our purposes we do not need to answer at it this point. Butlet us just make a few remarks about what it is definitely not. Take classicalmechanics and relativistic mechanics. According to classical mechanics the massof a particle, say an electron, does not change with its velocity. According to thetheory of relativity it does. In this and other issues of such a sort the theoriesdiffer. But there is full agreement in both theories for instance that electronsare certain particles possessing certain properties and behaving in a certain way

Page 101: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

8.2. THE WAVE PARTICLE DUALISM 101

under certain conditions. There is also agreement that the properties of anelectron such as its position or its velocity can, at least in principle, be knownthrough measurement. Classical and relativistic mechanics do not essentiallydiffer with respect to their view of physical reality. They differ in their claimsabout the laws governing this very reality, and in this the theory of relativityconstitutes a progress in comparison to classical mechanics.

As already said, the relationship between quantum mechanics and classicalmechanics is of a profound nature in that it on a deep issue, namely on theissue of the very nature of (physical) reality. This insight, we hope, will leadthe reader to appreciate the particular logical structures called holistic logics)which we will introduce in the next chapter.

So far, the ways of departure chosen in building ’quantum logics’ consisted inabandoning or modifying certain axioms or rules of classical logic. A prominentexample of this is the so called orthomodular logic where the distributive lawsof classical logic are abandoned. Semantically motivated approaches attemptedto view the propositional connectives of Birkhoff-von Neumann style quantumlogic as intensional connectives. However, in all these attempts basic featuresof classical logic are retained. It seems that the ’changes’ made in these modesof departing from classical logic hardly reflect the radical character of the wayhow quantum mechanics departs from classical mechanics.

For instance these attempts do not differ from classical logic in their styleof semantics and the concept of truth. In this respect they are as committedto ’classical reality’ as is classical logic. It seems that even in these attempts itis taken for granted that the language of the logic ’talks’ about some externalreality and the concept of truth of a formula is conceived as correspondenceto some external reality. In any case we can say that in these attempts atconstructing quantum logic the profound nature of the way quantum mechanicsdeparts from classical physics is in no way reflected.

The nature of the relationship between syntax and semantics of a logic werein these attempts left untouched in the sense that it was always assumed thatthere exist semantic structures external to the logic itself which for instanceallow the definition of truth for the logic. However different these semanticstructures vary in these attempts, the dualism between syntactic and semanticrepresentation or, roughly speaking, the dualistic relationship betweean ’logicand reality’ as such is untouched. And these logics were as strongly committedto ’classical’ reality as was classical mechanics. By introducing the conceptof a holistic logic in the Chapter 9 we advocate a different way of departingfrom classical logic in this book. This way of departing from classical logic ismotivated by considerations on the relationship between logic and reality. Wewill elaborate on this in Chapter 11.

8.2 The wave particle dualism

The first observation to shake our classical view of physical reality was deBroglies discovery of the wave-particle dualism. Elementary particles have wave

Page 102: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

102 CHAPTER 8. ASPECTS OF QUANTUM REALITY

nature. An electron for instance can behave like a particle, as we would expectfrom classical physics, but also as a wave, which is unfamiliar from classicalphysics. Sometimes the electron behaves particle-like and sometimes it behaveswave-like. De Broglie even discovered a precise mathematical connection be-tween the momentum of the electron when it is a particle and its wavelengthwhen it is a wave. De Broglie even discovered a precise mathematical connectionbetween the momentum of the electron when it is a particle and its wavelengthwhen it is a wave. This is the famous de Broglie relation:

λ = h/p

where λ is the wavelength in case of wavelike behaviour and p is the momentumin the case of particle behaviour.

Our ’classical world view’ suggests the question: Is the electron a particleor a wave? The answer is that this depends on the the particular experimentperformed in order to observe the electron. There are experiments in whichit behaves wave-like and there are experiments in which it behaves particle-like. It thus depends not only on the electron iteself what it ’is’ but also onthe observer. This is what led Bohr to the notion of complementarity. Onthis view the wave nature and the particle nature are mutually exclusive butcomplementary properties of one and the same physical entity. The reader willprobably agree that this phenomenon is hardly reconcilable with our traditionalway of looking at physical reality.

8.3 Measurement as an unseparable whole: TheCopenhagen interpretation

There is a problem in quantum mechanics with ascribing definite properties tophysical systems. Assume we have a quantum system in a certain state and wewant to measure a physical quantity or observable E, as is the term in quantummechanics, say its (total) energy. Then, according to quantum mechanics, thisobservable may not be sharp. This means that as a result of measurement wemay get various values each with a certain probability. Generally, there is adiscrete spectrum of values λ1, λ2, ... that E can assume with correspondingprobabilities p1, p2, ... such that pi = 1

It is important to note that these probabilities do not describe our ignoranceconcerning an ensemble from which we ’pick’ a property at random. Rather,according to quantum mechanics, the observable E does not have definite valuesand it is only in the process of measurement that it assumes a certain value witha certain probability.

How can we account for this? Obviously this fact is incompatible with theview that there exists an objective physical reality having definite preexistingproperties. Acording to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanicsthis is an expression of the fact that the quantum world consists of a set ofpotentialities rather than facts. These potentialities can be actualised in the

Page 103: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

8.3. MEASUREMENT AS AN UNSEPARABLE WHOLE: THE COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION103

process of measurement. Heisenberg, one of the chief representatives of theCopenhagen Interpretation puts it this way: ”The atoms or the elementaryparticles are not as real; they form a world of potentialities or possibilitiesrather than one of things or facts.”

Describe here some more tenets of the Copenhagen interpretation.

Bohr pointed out that the process of gathering information about the mi-croworld must, at some point, involve making an experiment in which a labora-tory instrument is used. Now, the representatives of the Copenhagen inerpreta-tion hold the view that this interaction is an indivisible whole and that it is nolonger possible to analyse the parts of the two agents involved, the system to bemeasured and the measuring instrument in the sense that their contributiontothe outcome of the interaction can be described. In Bohrs words, observer andobserved system form an ”indivisible, unanalysable whole” in the process ofobservation. The following is a quotation from Peat ”Einstein’s Moon” Thisholistic view of the nature of the atomic world was the key to the Copenhageninterpretation. It was something totally new in physics, although similar ideashad long been part of Eastern thought and religion. For more than two thousandyears, Eastern philosophers had put forward similar views about the unity thatlies between the observer and the observed. They had pointed to the illusion ofbreaking apart a thought from the mind that thinks the thought. Now a similarholism was entering physics.

What then is an electron, a proton or an atom? What properties does aparticle have if it only manifests itself in an unanalysable interaction with apiece of apparatus? What does it mean to say that the electron has a certainvelocity or position if every attempt to measure these proprties represent anirreducible act of interference? Indeed it becomes a major problem to speakof the electron as ”having” or possessing (definite)properties. And if all theproperties of a quantum object become ambiguous, then what sort of realitydoes it have?

Where then is atomic reality? Heisenberg suggested that the reality nowlies in the mathematics. The formalism of matrix mechanics or wave mechanicsworks perfectly. If you want to know where atomic reality lies, then Heisenbergpoints to the equations; there is no hope for finding it anywhere else.

: Obviously Heisenberg wants to ascribe physical reality to, say, Hilbertspace. This seems dubious to us. But what seems to us more natural is toascribe physical reality to Hilbert space logics, i.e. to logical structures of whichwe may think as being ’implemented’. But this cannot be understood at thispoint.

Does this mean that here is no reality outside the mathemtics? about thisBohr is at his most uncompromising. ” There is no quantum world”, he says.”There is only an abstract quantum mechanical description.” The above is prob-ably quoted verbatim from Peat’s book ”Einstein’s Moon”

Page 104: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

104 CHAPTER 8. ASPECTS OF QUANTUM REALITY

8.4 Are there ”elements of reality”? EPR andnon-locality

Here we try to give the gist of the EPR-paradox in an informal way.We give here a rough description of the EPR paradox. In 1935 Einstein,

Podolsky and Rosen published a now famous paper entitled ”Can the quantummechanical description of physical reality be considered complete?”[13]. In thispaper an ingenious thought experiment is presented which seemed to shakethe newly established edifice of quantum mechanics. This was after the greatintellectual struggle between Einstein and Bohr over the foundations of quantummechanics. In that struggle Bohr was generally considered winner. But now,after the EPR paper, Einstein had reappearsd on the stage with a seeminglydevastating argument against quantum mechanics. And, in fact, it took Bohrsome time to recover from this blow until he managed to produce a defenceagainst the attack.

We try to present the EPR argument in a nutshell. In this we are aware ofthe fact that we cannot, in this context, do justice to all its subtleties, let aloneBohr’s reply.

Imagine a particle at rest, i.e. with momentum zero, being split into electronsmoving away in opposite directions. Now, assume electron 1 and electron 2 arefar apart from each other and there is no physical interaction between them.We now assume that the position of electron 1 is measured. Once position ofelectron 1 is known, the position of electron 2 is known too. So, if we want toknow the position of electron 2, it suffices to measure the position of electron1. Now it is reasonable to assume that performing a measurement on electron1 does not in any way disturb electron 2. The term used by EPR is ”withoutin any way disturbing”. So we can measure the position of electron 2 ”withoutin any way disturbing” it. Put differently, we can predict with certainty theposition of electron 2 without in any way desturbing it. Now, EPR say thatif a quantity of a system can be predicted with certainty without in any waydisturbing it, then this quantity constitutes an ”element of reality”. So theposition of particle 2 constitutes an ”element of reality”.

The point of the argument is now this. Instead of measuring position ofelectron 2 by performing a measurement of momntum on electron 1 we maymeasure momentum of electron 2 by performing a measurement of momentumon electron 1. So, again we can predict the momentum of electron 2 withoutin any way disturbing it. Therefore the momentum of electron 2 constitutesan ”element of reality”. But now note that according to quantum mechanicsa physical system cannot simultaneously possess both a sharp position and asharp momentum, which according to EPR are both elements of reality Theconclusion EPR now draw is that Quantum Mechanics does not provide a com-plete description of reality in that it does not capture all elements of reality. Wecannot now go into a detailed discussion of the EPR thought experiment with allits subtleties. But it is obvious from the above that the EPR argument containsat least two tacit assumptions. The first assumptions concerns the existence of

Page 105: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

8.5. BOHM ON WHOLENESS AND HIS EXPERIMENT WITH LANGUAGE105

separate elements of reality, and the second assumption is implicit in the term”without in any way disturbing”. The first assumption reflects a picture of afragmented reality, which consists of separate elements, and the second assump-tion is what is nowadays called nonlocality. If, therefore, quantum mechanics isa correct description of reality, which is widely believed nowadays, then eitherone or even both of these assumptions must be false. Both assumptions concernthe nature of reality. So we can say that if Quantum Mechanics does providea complete description of physical reality and the EPR argument is thus false,then the EPR argument is false because it rests on a wrong view of reality.

But is there any way of proving that this view of reality is wrong? Theanswer is yes. It is given by Bell’s Theorem. Bell’s theorem provides us withthe means of experimentally testing whether physical reality is local or not.This test has been performed in several ingenious experiments by Aspect. Andthe experimental finding is: Physical reality is non-local. Bell’s theorem thuspermitted us to unveil a feature of physical reality which was undreamed of untilit was, on the basis of Bell’s theorem, discovered experimentally. This is thereason why Henry Stapp, reputed American physicist and leading expert on thefoundations of quantum mechanics, called Bell’s Theorem the greatest scientificdiscovery ever.

What is Bell’s theorem? We need not go into the details in order to un-derstand how it opened up the possibility of experimentally testing whetherreality is local or not. Bell’s Theorem is a statement of the form: ”If realityis local, then A”. The point is that statement A can be experimentally tested.Experiment yields: Not A. We conclude: Reality is not local. But there is moreto Bell’s Theorem. Namely, experiment not only yields NOT A, but it yieldsB. Again, B can be experimentally verified, and B is what quantum mechanicspredicts. A triumph of quantum mechanics!

Here we will, in the final version, give a more detailed account of Bell’sTheorem.

What was Bohr’a answer to EPR ? Certainly he did not know Bell’s theoremyet. But, essentially, Bohr argued that the EPR argument suffered from afundamental flaw, namely that is was based on a wrong view of (physical) reality.In Bohm’s words: ”He (Bohr) argued that in the quantum domain the procedureby which we analyse classical systems into interacting parts breaks down, forwhenever two entities combine to form a single system (even if only for a limitedperiod of time) the process by which they do this is not divisible” The gist ofBohr’s reply is that the two electrons form an indivisible whole to which ourmethod of ’fragmenting’ is not applicable.

8.5 Bohm on wholeness and his experiment withlanguage

David Bohms creative life was in its many facets devoted to the puzzle of quan-tum mechanics. The chain of his thinking contains brilliant ideas all of which

Page 106: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

106 CHAPTER 8. ASPECTS OF QUANTUM REALITY

became highly significant and form essential parts of the literature on the foun-dations of quantum mechanics.

His views on physical reality with which he had come up after almost half acentury of dedicated intellectual work on the problem of understanding quan-tum mechanics culminated in his book ”Wholeness and the Implicate Order”.In this book Bohm consistently argues for a holistic world view in order to ac-count for the puzzles of quantum reality. This holistic world view which shouldreplace the fragnentary world view typical of Western thought and of modernWestern science such as classical physics. In the first chapter entitled ”Frag-mentation and Wholeness” he describes the act of observation (measurement)in quantum mechanics as follows: ”One can no longer maintain the division be-tween the observer and the observed (which is implicit in the atomistic view thatregards each of these as separate aggregates of atoms). Rather, both observerand observed are merging and interpenetrating aspects of one reality, which isindivisible and unanalysable.” Another quotation:” ...relativity and quantumtheory agree in that they both imply the need to look on the world as an un-divided whole, in whih all parts of the universe, including the observer andhis instruments merge and unite in one totality. In this totality, the atomisticform of insight is a simplification and an abstraction, valid only in some limitedcontext.” Bohm then suggests to view reality as an ”Undivided Wholeness inFlowing Movement”. This view put forward by an outstanding representative ofmodern Western science is undoubtedly reminiscent not only of Eastern thoughtbut also of Heraclitus philosophy of the world as being in in permanent flux.The idea that our language, i.e. the language we use in everyday life and also inclassical physics, may not be the appropriate language for the quantum worldhas already been put forward by Heisenberg in his ”Physics and Philosophy”.Heisenberg holds that the puzzling nature of quantum mechanics is due to thefact that the structure of our languge does not fit in the pattern of quantumreality. He does not, however, make any attempt to actually describe the lin-guistic structures that might conform to quantum mechanics. It is in particularthe subject-predicate structure noun phrase - verb phrase) of the sentence thatreflects the fragmented nature of our world view. The noun phrase, in particularthe definite noun phrase ’denote’ objects of an external world, verb phrases ’de-note’ properties, predicates, transitive verbs ’denote’ relations between objectsetc.

The metaphor Bohm uses in ”Wholeness and the implicate order” is thatof the of a hologram. The word being of Greek origin denotes an instrument’writing the whole’.

In order to understand the metaphor of the hologram in Bohm’s thinking weneed to know a bit about the nature of a hologram without, however, having togo into the technical details of actually constructing such an optical instrument.Let us just say this. A hologram is commonly known as a three-dimensionalphotograph made with the the help of a laser. Using laser light, an interferencepattern on a photographic plate is created. The developed film is then illumi-nated again by laser light. Then a three-dimensional image of the photographedobject appears. It is not the impression of three-dimensionality, however, that

Page 107: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

8.5. BOHM ON WHOLENESS AND HIS EXPERIMENT WITH LANGUAGE107

is most striking about a hologram. Rather it is the following. When we illumi-nate just a part of the photographic plate, however small, it is, though smaller,still the (whole) image of the whole object that appears. So every part of thehologram encodes the whole information possessed by the whole object. Tech-nically, this effect is explained by the wave nature of light and the particularinterference effect creating the pattern on the photographic plate.

The main difference between the hologram and the familiar instrument ofa lens is this. A lens is an optical instrument creating an image of an objectin such a way that that the parts of the objects correspond to the parts of theimage in a one-to-one way. But, due to the wave properties of light, even thisis true only approximately. Bohm remarks that thus the case of the lens maybe regarded as the limiting case of the hologram. Fragmentation is so to speakthe limiting case of wholeness. This intuition is reflected in the precise logicalframework of Chapter as the Limiting case Theorem.

One of the characteristic feature of the hologram is that it is mirrored (en-coded) in all its parts. Our view of reality should, according to Bohm, be holisticin the sense that there is no fragmentation. Rather, the ’parts’ are to reflectand encode the ’whole’. This is also strikingly reminiscent of what Leibniz saysabout the monads, his incorporeal ’atoms of reality’. These monads, Leibnizsays, ’mirror’ each other. The whole world is thus mirrored in each of its parts.

But for Bohm this is not just a good metaphor. Rather, in the second chapterof ”Woleness and the Implicate Order” entitled ”The rheomode- an experimentwith language and thought” he takes this picture seriously as the basis for con-structing new linguistic structures which he thinks are more appropriate to thetype of reality suggested by quantum mechanics. What is the rheomode? If ourlanguage with is typical subject predicate sentence structure is not the languageappropriate for the quantum world, what then does the proper language looklike? It would, as Bohm correctly points out, not be practicable to constructa new language having an entirely new structure appropriate for the quantumworld. Instead, Bohm proposes a new mode of language similar to that of in-dicative, imperative, subjunctive He says:”... will now consider a mode in whichmovement is to be taken as primary in our thinking and in which this motionwill be incorporated into the language structure by allowing the verb rather thanthe noun to play a primary role... For the sake of convenience we shall give thismode a name, i.e. the rheomode (rheo is from a Greek verb, meaning to flow).At least in the first instance the rheomode will be an experiment with language,concerned mainly with trying to find out whether it is possible to create a newstructure that is not so prone towards fragmentation as is the present one.”

In order to give a flavour of Bohm’s rheomode experiment let us take alook at his discussion of terms like ’relevance’, ’relevant’...Bohm introduces therheomode with a discussion of the issue of relevance.

Here Bohm proposes to consider verbs such as ’to levate’ or ’relevate’, whichare not part of language so far or any longer, because they may have droppedout of language , as basic. Why does he choose the notion of relevance as thestarting point for hisinqiry into the rheomode? When using the term ’relevant’we focus on a whole bunch of things. First, clearly, we focus on something wec

Page 108: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

108 CHAPTER 8. ASPECTS OF QUANTUM REALITY

consider relevant, say a sentence uttered in a discussion. But we also focus onthe process of thought or perception as a result of which this sentence appearsrelevant. Moreover, its relevance depends on the context, which can changeand does change. So, in making statements about relevance we refer to anintegrated whole involving language, perception extralinguistic contexts, andthis whole is in flux. The boundaries between relevance and irrelevance arenot sharp as the structure of language with the dominating nouns’relevance’and ’irrelevance’ would suggest. This, says Bohm, is a case for the rheomode.heproposes to introduce the verb ’to relevate’ into the language Which he saysshould mean ” to lift a certain context into attention again, for a particularcontext as indicated by thought and language”. ’re-levant’ then denotes thestate of being ’re-levated’. Note that ’re’ means again. ”It implies time andsimilarity (as well as difference)”

”So when relevance or irrelevance is communicated, one has to understandthat this is not a hard and fast division between opposing categories but rather,an expression of an ever-changing perception, in which it is possible, for themoment, to see a fit or non-fit between the content lifted into attention and thecontext to which it refers”

8.6 Informal reflections

The above remarks were concerned with the issue of reality in quantum me-chanics. As already mentioned, this could not be in any way exhaustive. Wescratched the surface only. We hope, however, that we succeeded in conveyingthe impression to the reader that understanding the ”mystery of quantum me-chanics” demands a revision of our views on the nature of (physical) reality. Inthis endeavour, we will have to depart from the world view that underlies notonly everyday life but also Newtonian and relativistic physics. What we comeacross all the time when discussing the issue of reality in quantum mechanicis isthe need to revise our familiar view of a fragmented world that can be separatedinto ”elements of reality” in favour of a more holistic view of reality. This is aprofound revision.

In this book we try to cast light on the ”mystery of quantum mechanics” fromthe point of view of logic. In this we will have to depart from classical logic. Thequestion is what this way of departure will have to look like. The dilemma is,roughly, this. Modern logic, in particular the modern version of classical logic,with all its merits and great achievements, is still based, in particular with regardto its semantics, on the fragmented view of reality which underlies classicalphysics and which, in whatever sense, needs revision in quantum mechanics.We therefore must ask ourselves the question whether any way of departingfrom classical logic that does not in some way reflect this profound revision canbe successful. It was the purpose of this chapter to impress onto the reader theidea that in order to make logic fruitful for the enterprise of trying to understandquantum mechanics a profound revision is necessary. This revision must concernthe issue of reality in logic in the same way as quantum mechanics forces us to

Page 109: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

8.6. INFORMAL REFLECTIONS 109

revise our view of physical reality of classical mechanics. We will in our way ofdeparting from classical logic be guided by this idea.

This book takes at least part of its inspiration from Bohm’s book. As alreadypointed out we view the logical structures we set out to discover in this bookas a sort of mirrors of quantum reality. In Bohm’s experiment it is a modeof language in which the dynamic and holistic aspects of quantum reality arereflected. In our approach it is logic, more precisely certain logical structuresthat are to play this role. Recall our treatment of propositions in M-algebras.There, propositions are viewed dynamically rather than statically, in accordancewith Bohm’s picture of a world in flux. In Chapter 9 on holistic logics it is theintuition of wholeness and interconnectedness which is reflected in a similar way.

Page 110: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

110 CHAPTER 8. ASPECTS OF QUANTUM REALITY

Page 111: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 9

Holistic Logics

In this chapter we introduce, as in chapter 6, certain structures which are ab-stractions from Hilbert space. In Chapter 6 the focus was on propositions. Thestructures we introduced, namely M-algebras, were designed to capture the wayhow propositions act on states. States were, there, primitive notions. In chapter7 we went one step further. We focused on the nature of the states themselves.In all this, however, we did not leave the framework of M-algebras. In thischapter we also abstract from this. The central concept we introduce in thischapter is that of a holistic logic. Our motivation for choosing this term is givenby our intuitive reflections on the concept of a state in a dynamic logical frame-work, see Chapter 6. We saw that states in such a framework must encodeother states. This intuition is perfectly reflected in the logical structures wecall holistic logics. Loosely speaking, in such systems ”everything is encoded in(almost) everything”.

Throughout this chapter we assume a language Fml of propositional logicas introduced in Chapter 2.

9.1 Consequence Revision Systems

9.1.1 Formal Motivation: the Lindenbaum algebra viewedas an operator algebra

In order to motivate the concepts we are going to introduce we start with anobservation from classical logic. Recall that ` denotes the consequence relationof classical logic. Given a formula α, we may form a new consequence relation`α as follows: β `α γ iff α ∧ β ` γ. We get a class of consequence relationsC = `α| α ∈ Fml. By the Deduction Theorem of classical logic (see theChapter 2) we have β `α γ iff `α β → γ for all `α∈ C. We say that →, i.e.material implication, is an internalising connective for C. Again, given α ∈ Fmland `β∈ C, we may form the consequence relation `α∧β . Thus every α ∈ Fmlinduces an operator α : C → C. We have α = β iff α and β are classically

111

Page 112: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

112 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

equivalent. It is readily verified that the class of operators is partially orderedby: α ≤ β iff α ` β. Moreover, it is routine to verify that this structure formsa Boolean algebra isomorphic to the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra of classicallogic. Observe that βα = α iff α ` β. This is our motivating example of whatwe will call a consequence revision system. Its main ingredients are a class ofconsequence relations C , a function F : Fml × C → C and a connective, whichin this case is material implication, which is an internalising connective for allconsequence relations of C, i.e. we have `α β → γ iff β `α γ for any α. Thestructure of interest is the triple L = 〈C,F, →〉.

There is a straightforward generalisation of the above consideration. Wecould have started with some consistent set of formulas Σ and the consequencerelation `Σ defined by: α `Σ β iff Σ∪α ` β and would by the same procedureas above have arrived at the structure LΣ = 〈CΣ,FΣ,→〉. Note that, by the De-duction Theorem of classical logic, material implication is still the internalisingconnective in this more general case.

9.1.2 Consequence relations

We shall, in this chapter, be concerned with classes of consequence relations andmust therefore consider conditions these consequence relations are supposed tosatisfy. These conditions go beyond those stated in Chapter 2. But one shouldnote that all these conditions do hold in Hilbert space, as we will see in the nextchapter. Moreover, we assume in this chapter a language with all the usualpropositional connectives, i.e. ¬, ∧, ∨, →.

We denote the universal (inconsistent) universal consequence relation by 0.We assume that for the consequence relations we consider this is equivalent tothe existence of a formula α such that |∼ α and |∼ ¬α. Any class of consequencerelations considered is assumed to contain 0. That means we assume for any|∼6= 0 that for no α ∈ Fml we have |∼ α and |∼ ¬α.

Given a class C of consequence relations. Then we write α |∼C β iff α |∼ βfor every |∼∈ C. We say α ≡C β if α |∼C β and β |∼C α.

Minimal Conditions 1

Let us for the sake of convenience again mention here the minimal conditionsof Chapter 2 which are generally imposed on consequence relations.

Reflexivityα |∼ α

Cutα ∧ β |∼ γ, α |∼ βα |∼ γ

Restricted Monotonicityα |∼ β, α |∼ γα ∧ β |∼ γ

Page 113: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.1. CONSEQUENCE REVISION SYSTEMS 113

In the paper by Kraus–Lehmann–Magidor [34] these three conditions are, assuggested by Gabbay in [?], considered to be the minimal conditions a conse-quence relation should satisfy.

For a given consequence relation |∼ define

α ≡ β iff α |∼ β and β |∼ α

Minimal Conditions 2

Moreover, we impose the following conditions on the special consequence rela-tions studied in this book.

α ≡ ¬¬α

> ≡ α ∨ ¬α

⊥ ≡ α ∧ ¬α

α ∧ β |∼ α

α ∧ β |∼ β

α |∼ α ∨ β

β |∼ α ∨ β

|∼ α ∨ ¬α

α |∼ >⊥ |∼ α

¬(α ∧ β) ≡ ¬α ∨ ¬β

¬(α ∨ β) ≡ ¬α ∧ ¬β

The conditions we imposed so far are ’local’ in nature in the sense that theyare imposed separately on every single consequence relation belonging to theclass considered. We, moreover, impose the following conditions which have aglobal character in the sense that they are related to the class C as a whole.

α |∼C γ, β |∼C γα ∨ β |∼C γ

α |∼C β¬β |∼C ¬α

The reason for imposing these conditions is that we want to have the alge-braic structures arising from these logical structures to have certain desirableproperties that are actually fulfilled in the case of the concrete structures arisingin connection with Quantum Mechanics. So, in contrast to the last two chapterwe want the relevant algebraic structures to be lattices. This brings us closerto Hilbert space where the algebraic structures relevant from the logial point ofview are in fact lattices.

Page 114: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

114 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

9.1.3 The Concept of a Consequence Revision System

Definition 9.1 Let Fml be a class of formulas as described above and let C bea class of consequence relations over Fml satisfying the conditions described.Let F be a function

F : Fml × C → C.Then we say that F is an action on C iff for every |∼∈ C and α, β ∈ Fml thefollowing conditions are satisfied.

(i) F (>, |∼) =|∼

(ii) F (α, |∼) = 0 iff |∼ ¬α

(iii) F (β, F (α, |∼)) = F (α, |∼) iff α |∼ β

If F is an action on C, we call the pair 〈C, F 〉 a consequence revision system(CRS).

Note that by |∼ α we mean > |∼ α. For a given class C of consequencerelations call the formulas α and β C-equivalent, in symbols α ≡C β, if for every|∼∈ C we have α |∼ β and β |∼ α.Remark: We are aware of the fact that the way we use the term revision inthe above definition does not fully capture the way it is used in traditionalrevision theory. If at all, the action of formulas on consequence relations asdefined above represents a simple type of revision. Condition (ii) above saysthat given a consequence relation |∼ and a formula α which is inconsistentwith |∼ then the result of ’revising’ |∼ by α is the inconsistent consequencerelation. The corresponding case in traditional revision thory is that of a theoryT and a formula α inconsistent with T . The result of revising T by α usuallydenoted by T ∗ α is then, according to according to traditional revision theory,not necessarily the inconsistent theory. Since, however, in our most importantexamples, namely those arising from Hilbert spaces, we are concerned with aprocess which, in the intuitive sense, deserves to be called revision, we freelyuse the term revision. Every α ∈ Fml induces a (revision) operator on C

α : C → C

viaα |∼=: F (α, |∼)

For α |∼ we will also write |∼α.Denote the class of these operators by Fml. We have α = β iff α ≡C β.Fml has the structure of a (multiplicative) semigroup the multiplication

beingαβ = α β

Lemma 9.1 For any α ∈ Fml we have α α = α.

Page 115: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.1. CONSEQUENCE REVISION SYSTEMS 115

Proof. By Reflexivity we have α |∼ α for every |∼∈ C. Thus the claim followsby conditions (iii) of the definition of an action.

We have a natural partial ordering on Fml, namely α ≤ β : iff βα = α

Lemma 9.2 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS. Then for any |∼∈ C the following conditionsare equivalent

• (i) |∼ α

• (ii) |∼α=|∼• (iii) There exists a |∼1∈ C such that |∼1,α=|∼

Proof. For the equivalence of (i) and (ii) observe first that |∼>,α=|∼α. Bycondition (iii) of the definition of an action we have that > |∼ α iff |∼α=|∼>,α=|∼>=|∼. Clearly, (ii) implies (iii). In order to show that (iii) implies (ii)suppose |∼1,α=|∼. Note that by Reflexivity we have α |∼1 α. Then it follows bycondition (iii) of the definition of an action that |∼α=|∼.

Lemma 9.3 α |∼ β iff |∼α β,

Proof. Suppose α |∼ β. By condition (iii) of the defininition of an action thisis equivalent to |∼α,β=|∼α. By (i) of the above lemma this means that |∼α β.

It follows by the above two lemmas that |∼α=|∼β implies α ≡ β, i.e. α |∼ βand β |∼ α. We see that α = β iff α ≡C β.

Definition 9.2 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS. Then define the proposition [α] as follows.

[α] =: |∼ | |∼ α

We denote the class of propositions of 〈C, F 〉 by Prop.

It is routine to verify the statements made in the following lemma.

Lemma 9.4 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS. Then

α ≤ β iff [α] ⊂ [β]

α = β iff [α] = [β]

α |∼C β iff [α] ⊂ [β]

α ≡C β iff [α] = [β]

α ≤ β iff ¬β ≤ ¬α

[α] ⊂ [β] iff [¬β] ⊂ [¬α]

Page 116: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

116 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

The conditions we imposed on the consequence relations guarantee that thefollowing holds. IN THE FINAL VERSION WE WILL MAKE THIS EX-PLICIT.

Lemma 9.5 For any CRS both 〈Fml,≤〉 and 〈Prop,⊂〉 are lattices. Forα, β ∈ Fml and [α], [β] ∈ Prop the greatest lower bounds are α ∧ β and [α ∧ β]respectively.The lowest upper bounds are given by α ∨ β and [α∨β] respectively.

Proof. The proof is routine. We will give it in full in the final version

Given a CRS 〈C, F 〉. Then define unary operations∗ : Fml → Fml and ∗ : Prop → Prop as follows.

α∗ =: ¬α

and[α]∗ =: [¬α]

Note that in view of Lemma 11 these operations are well defined. Moreover, wedefine a mapping ψ : Fml → Prop by

ψ(α) = [α]

again, by Lemma ? this mapping is well defined. It is routine to verify thefollowing theorem which bears an analogy to the well known fact that in Hilbertspace the lattice of projectors and the lattices of closed subspaces are isomorphic(orthomodular) lattices.

Theorem 9.1 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS. Then

• 〈Fml,≤,∗ 〉 and 〈Prop,⊂,∗ 〉 are ortholattices.

• ψ is an isomorphism between ortholattices.

Proof. This is one of the several proofs which are routine and are not yetincluded in this draft. In the final version they will be given in full.

9.1.4 The Concept of an Internalsing Connective

We now define the concept of an internalising connective which, essentially, isalready familiar from Chapter 7 in the context of Consequence Revision Systems.From the logical point of view the concept of an internalising connective is thelink between the object level and the meta level. Note that whenever we usethe term connective we mean a connective definable by the usual propositionalconnectives in the following sense. We say that αβ is definable if there existsa formula of propositional logic ϕ(p, q) with exactly two propositional variablessuch that the formula α ; β is the result of uniformly substituting α in ϕ forp and β for q. We say that ϕ defines ;. Given two connectives ;1 and ;2

Page 117: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.1. CONSEQUENCE REVISION SYSTEMS 117

defined by ϕ1 and ϕ2 respectively. Then we say that ;1 and ;2 are classicallyequivalent if ϕ1 and ϕ2 are classically equivalent.

As already said, material implication is internalising for the classical conse-quence relation `. This follows from the Deduction Theorem of classical logic.So the fact that a given consequence relation -classical (monotonic) or non-classical (non-monotonic)- admits an internalising connective may be viewed asa sort of generaliseed Deduction Theorem.

Consider for instance the Sasaki hook ;s which is defined by ϕ(p, q) =:¬p ∨ (p ∧ q). This says that α ;s β is just short for ¬α ∨ (α ∧ β). Obviouslythe Sasaki hook is classically equivalent to material implication.

Definition 9.3 Let |∼ be a consequence relation and ; a connective such thatα |∼ β iff |∼ α ; β we say that ; is an internalising connective for |∼. Givena CRS 〈C, F 〉. Then we say that ; is an connective. Then we say that ; isan internalising connective for 〈C, F 〉 iff ; is an internalising connective for all|∼∈ C.Lemma 9.6 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS and let ; be an internalising connective for〈C, F 〉. Then the following holds.

• (i) α |∼ (β ; γ) iff β |∼α γ

• (ii)|∼| α |∼ β is a proposition, namely [α ; β]

Proof. By ?? we have α |∼ (β ; γ) iff |∼α (β ; γ). Since ; is internalising,this is equivalent to β |∼α γ. This proves (i).(ii) follows from the fact that ; is internalising.

Note that in case we have an internalising connective ; the process of re-vision can be described very simply as follows. Revise the consequence relation|∼ by α so as to get |∼α. Then γ can be proved from β in |∼α iff β ; γ can beproved from α in |∼.

Given a class of consequence relations C and two connectives ;1 and ;2.We then say that ;1 and ;2 are C-equivalent iff for all formulas α, β ∈ Fmlwe have α ;1 β ≡C α ;2 β.

Lemma 9.7 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS. Then any two internalising connectives for〈C, F 〉 are C-equivalent.

Proof. Let ;1 and ;2 be two internalising connectives for 〈C, F 〉. By sym-metry it suffices to prove that α ;1 β |∼C α ;2 β. So let |∼ be any element ofC such that |∼ α ;1 β. Since ;1 is internalising, we have α |∼ β and, since ;2

is internalising, |∼ α ;2 β.

The above lemma says that the action ’determines’ the internalising connec-tive modulo C-equivalence. The next lemma states a sort of converse for this,namely that the internalising connective ’determines’ the action.

Lemma 9.8 Let 〈C, F1〉 and 〈C, F2〉 be CRS and let ; be a connective whichis internalising for both. Then we have F1 = F2.

Page 118: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

118 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

Let us now come to a crucial point. In principle, the concept of an action offormulas on a class of consequence relations can serve a useful purpose. It mayserve as a vehicle for studying the interplay between properties of the operatoralgebra on the one hand and properties of the class of consequence relationson the other. Generally, properties of the former type are algebraic in nature,whereas properties of the latter type are logical in nature. The orthocomple-mented lattice of operators and thus the lattice of propositions may have thealgebraic property of being orthomodular and we may ask the question what isthe ’logical’ counterpart of that algebraic property. The situation we have is,by the way, familiar from various branches of mathematics. It is for instance afamiliar technique to study the algebraic structure of certain groups via theiraction on certain spaces making use of geometrical or topological properties ofthese spaces. As to the concept of an orthomodular lattice note that this is adominant concept in virtually all approaches to quantum logic. It is so to speakthe quantum logical counterpart of the concept of a Boolean algebra in classi-cal logic. The most prominent examples are the lattices of closed subspaces oforthomodular spaces and in particular Hilbert spaces.

As already mentioned the following connective ;s is called Sasaki hook

α ;s β =: ¬α ∨ (α ∧ β)

Theorem 9.2 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS such that for any |∼∈ C, |∼ (α ;s β)implies α |∼ β and let ; be an internalising connective for 〈C, F 〉. Then 〈Fml,≤,∗ 〉 and thus 〈Prop,⊂,∗ 〉 are orthomodular lattices and ; is C-equivalent to ;s.If ;s is C-equivalent to →, i.e. material implication, then the above lattices areBoolean algebras.

Proof. In view of 9.1 it suffices to prove orthomodularity. We first show thatfor any |∼∈ C

(1) α ∧ (α ; β) |∼ β

By Lemma ? it suffices to show that |∼α∧(α;β) β. By Lemma ? we have |∼α∧(α;β) α∧ (α ; β) and thus |∼α∧(α;β) α and |∼α∧(α;β) α ; β. Moreover,since ; is internalising, we have |∼α∧(α;β),α β. But |∼α∧(α;β),α=|∼α∧(α;β),since |∼α∧(α;β) α. Now (1) is proved.It follows that

(2) α ∧ α ; β ≤ β

We now prove that the operator α ; β has the following property.

(3) α ∧ β ≤ γ implies α ;s β ≤ α ; γ.

For this we have to use that every |∼∈ C satisfies Cut. Assume α ∧ β ≤ γ andlet |∼∈ C be such that |∼ α ; β. We then have α ∧ β |∼ γ and, since ; isinternalising, α |∼ β. Then we get, using Cut, that α |∼ γ and again, since ; isinternalising, |∼ (α ; γ). Thus α ; β ≤ α ; γ.

Page 119: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.1. CONSEQUENCE REVISION SYSTEMS 119

Now, by the hypothesis, |∼ (α ;s β implies α |∼ β and thus, since ; is inter-nalising, |∼ (α ; β). This means α ;s β ≤ α ; β. By transitivity we haveα ;s β ≤ α ; γ.We have thus proved that, if α ∧ β ≤ γ, then |∼ α ;s β implies |∼ α ; γfor any |∼∈ C, which means α ;s β ≤ α ; γ. We now get by (2), (3) andMittelstaedt’s Theorem (see Chapter 3) that 〈Fml,≤,∗ 〉 and thus 〈Prop,⊂,∗ 〉are orthomodular and, moreover, α ; β = α∗ ∨ (α ∧ β). From this it followsthat ; and ;s are C-equivalent.That the lattices under consideration are Boolean if ;s is C-equivalent to ma-terial implication, again, follows by Mittelstaedt’s theorem.. This completes theproof.

Remark: It should be pointed out that in the above proof two ’logical’ prop-erties of the class C play a crucial role in establishing the fact that the lattices〈Fml,≤,∗ 〉 and 〈Prop,⊂ ∗〉 have the algebraic property of being orthomodular.The first ‘logical’ property is that an internalising connective having a certainproperty exists for the action 〈C, F 〉. This property of an action can, as we shallsee, be viewed as a generalisation of the property that the Deduction Theoremholds. The second crucial property is that all consequence relations of C satisfyCut.For the purposes of this paper we introduce the following notion of a logic.

Definition 9.4 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS and ; an internalising connective for〈C, F 〉. Then call the triple L = 〈C, F, ;〉 a logic.

We may thus interpret the above theorem as essentially saying that for aCRS to become a logic (with ;s as its internalising connective), it is necessarythat the lattice of operators 〈Fml,≤,∗ 〉 and thus the lattice of propositions〈Prop,⊂,∗ 〉 have the algebraic property of being orthomodular.Given a consequence relation |∼, then define C(|∼) =: α ||∼ α. We have the

Proposition 9.1 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a logic. Given |∼1, |∼2∈ C. Then C(|∼1

) = C(|∼2) iff |∼1=|∼2.

Proof. Suppose C(|∼1) = C(|∼2) and let α |∼1 β. It follows, since ; isinternalising that |∼1 (α ; β) and thus by the hypothesis |∼2 (α ; β). Again,since ; is internalising, we get α |∼2 β, thus |∼1⊂|∼2. By symmetry we alsoget the other inclusion.

9.1.5 Classical Logic Revisited

Let us now return to our motivating example from classical logic and look at itfrom the point of view of the framework developed in the last subsection. Let `denote classical consequence and let Σ ⊂ Fml be any consistent set of formulas.Define the class CΣ,α of consequence relations as follows. For a given formula α,define `Σ,α by:

β `Σ,α γ iff Σ ∪ α ∧ β ` γ

Page 120: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

120 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

Moreover, define CΣ,L = `Σ,α| α ∈ Fml and the function FΣ,L : Fml×CΣ,L →CΣ,L by FΣ,L(α,`Σ,α) =`Σ,α∧β . It is immediately verified, using familiar factsof classical logic such as the Deduction Theorem, that consequence relations asdefined above satisfy all the conditions we imposed and that 〈CΣ,L,FΣ,L〉 is aCRS. We have

`Σ,α=`Σ,β iff Σ ` α ↔ β

Theorem 9.3 LL,Σ = 〈CL,Σ,FL,Σ,→〉 is a logic. The lattice of operators OLL,Σ

and thus the lattice of propositions PLL,Σ are Boolean algebras isomorphic to theLindenbaum-Tarski algebra B(Σ).

Proof. For the first part of our claim we need to prove that→ is an internalisingconnective for 〈CL,Σ,FL,Σ〉. But this is exactly what the Deduction Theoremsays:

Σ ∪ α ` (β → γ) iff Σ ∪ α ∧ β ` γ

It follows from the fact that → is internalising and Theorem ? that the latticesunder consideration are Boolean algebras. Moreover, it is straightforward toprove that the following function ϕ : OLL,Σ → B(Σ) is well defined and is anisomorphism

ϕ(α) = αΣ,

where αΣ denotes the (unique) element of the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra B(Σ)to which α belongs.

It is interesting to note that we have established the well known fact that theLindenbaum algebra is Boolean (see Chapter 2), in a way, however, which isradically different from the method usually applied.

Note that in case that Σ is a complete theory all the algebras we con-sider, namely OLL,Σ , PL,Σ and the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra B(Σ) are trivialBoolean algebras, i.e. consisting of 0 and 1 only.In view of Theorem ? we have the follwing

Proposition 9.2 Let B be any Boolean algebra. Then there exists a class ofconsequence relations C and a function F such that L = 〈C, F,→〉 is a logic withmaterial implication as its internalising connective and B is isomorphic to itsoperator algebra OL.

The above fact gives rise to the following question:Is it true that for every orthomodular latticeO there exists a logic L = 〈C, F, ;s〉with the Sasaki hook as its internalising connective such that O is isomorphicto OL ?

Page 121: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.1. CONSEQUENCE REVISION SYSTEMS 121

9.1.6 The Semantics of Consequence Revision Systems

The Concept of an H-Model

In most of the traditional approaches to logic, a logic can, syntactically, beviewed as a class of formulas and, semantically, the corresponding class of modelsis a class of models for formulas. In our approach, the analogue of the classof formulas in the traditional approaches is given by a class of consequencerelations. It would, therefore, be natural that the class of models should bea class of models for consequence relations rather than a class of models forformulas. For quite some time in the history of logic it was not clear what sucha thing could be. As already mentioned, however, such a type of model wasput forward in the seminal paper by Kraus-Lehmann-Magidor [34] . We shalluse KLM as an abbreviation for these three names. The models we use in thispaper are GKLM (Generalised Kraus–Lehmann–Magidor) models as defined inChapter 2.

We now propose the following concept of a model for a CRS.

Definition 9.5 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS and H = 〈H, h,F , l, g〉 a structure suchthat

• H is a non-empty set

• h : H → C is a surjective function

• F : Fml × H → H is a function inducing F on Fml × C via h, i.e.F (α, h(x)) = h(F(α, x))

• l is a function assigning to every x ∈ H a set of Scott-models.

• g is an injective function assigning to every x ∈ H a binary relation≤x⊂ H ×H such that Mx = 〈H,≤x, l〉 is a GKLM model for h(x).

Then we say that H is an H-model for 〈C, F 〉. We say that H is an H-modelfor the logic 〈C, F, ;〉 if H is an H-model for 〈C, F 〉. For x ∈ H and α ∈ Fmldefine

〈H, x〉 |= α iff s(α) = 1 for all s ∈ l(x).

We say : α is true at x in H.

Remark: Note that we say that a formula is true at x iff it is provable in h(x).The following Propositions serve to illustrate the nature of H-models. Theproofs are obvious from the definition of an H-model.

Proposition 9.3 Let 〈C, F 〉 be a CRS and H be an H-model for C, F 〉. Let |∼∈C and x ∈ H such that h(x) =|∼. Then the following conditions are equivalent.

(i) α |∼ β

(ii) Mx |= α |∼ β

Page 122: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

122 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

(iii) MF(α,x) |=|∼ β

(iv) (H,F(α, x)) |= β

(v) |∼α β

Proposition 9.4 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a logic and H an H-model for 〈C, F 〉.Let x ∈ H. Then the following conditions are equivalent

(i) α `Mx (β ; γ)

(ii) 〈H,F(α, x)〉 |= β ; γ

(iii) 〈H, x〉 |= α ; (β ; γ)

(iv) β `MF (α,x) γ

(v) β |∼ γ, where |∼= F (α, h(x)).

(v) α |∼ (β ; γ) with |∼= h(x)

The Fibred Mode of Evaluation in H-Models

The notion of an H-model serves a double purpose. First, it makes sense tospeak of the truth of a formula in such a model as we are used to from tradi-tional logics and their model theory.Second, these models reflect the following feature of our logics. To see this, recallwhat intuitively the function of an internalising connective is. An internalisingconnective serves to reflect the metaconcept of consequence at the object level.So, intuitively, formulas containing the internalising connective ’talk’ about con-sequence. H-models account for this in that they not only model the truth ofsuch formulas but also explicitly model the statements about consequence theseformulas make. This means that in the process of evaluation of a formula in anH-model the internalising connective is evaluated in a GKLM model.Given an H-model H, x ∈ H and a formula of the form α ; β. We then havetwo ways of evaluating the internalising connective ;. The first way of doingthis is to check whether 〈H, x〉) |= (α ; β) according to the definition of truthgiven above. The second way of evaluating the connective ; is to look at theGKLM model Mx and check whether α `Mx β. If so, we have, since Mx is aGKLM model for h(x) =:|∼, α |∼ β. We have α `Mx β iff 〈H, x〉 |= (α ; β).This is how the H-model reflects the fact that ; is an internalising connective.Let us now look at a more complex formula. Consider a formula of the form

ϕ = (α ; (β ; (γ ; δ)))

We may now proceed as follows.We evaluate ϕ in the GKLM model Mx.We have

α `Mx (β ; (γ ; δ)

Page 123: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.1. CONSEQUENCE REVISION SYSTEMS 123

iff β `MF (α,x) (γ ; δ)

iff γ `MF(β,(F(α,x)) δ

We have

〈H, x〉 |= ϕ iff γ `MF(β,F(α,x)) δ

The characteristic feature of the second mode of evaluation is that the con-nective ; is evaluated in GKLM models as consequence. At each stage inthe process of evaluation we have to switch from one GKLM model to anotherusing the ’fibring function’

F∗ : Fml ×M→M, where M =: Mx | x ∈ Hdefined by

F∗(α,Mx) = MF(α,x)

Note that this ’fibring function’ is well defined since by the last clause of thedefinition of an H-model we have Mx = Mx′ iff x = x′. The mode of evaluationjust presented is in the spirit of what was put forward by Gabbay in severalpapers and his books [18] and [?]. as fibred semantics.

9.1.7 H-Models and Classical Logic

We shall now show that the concept of an H-model arises in a natural wayin connection with the logics LL,Σ = 〈CL,Σ,FL,Σ,→〉, i.e. classical logic. InChapyer 8 we will see how this concept occurs naturally in connection with thelogics arising in connection with Hilbert spaces.

Definition 9.6 Let Σ be a set of formulas consistent in classical logic. Considerthe structure HL,Σ =: 〈CL,Σ, h,FL,Σ, lΨ, g〉 such that

• h is the identity function.

• The function l is defined as follow. l(`Σ,α) = sα, where sα(β) = 1 iff`Σ,α β, else 0.

• The function g is defined as follows. Given x =`Σ,α∈ CL,Σ, then defineg(x) =:≤α as follows: `Σ,β≤α`Σ,γ is defined only if `Σ,β α. Then, if`Σ,γ α, `Σ,β≤α`Σ,γ iff `Σ,γ β. If not `Σ,γ α, then `Σ,β≤α`Σ,γ

Note that in the above definition the function l and g are well defined. This isreadily seen using familiar facts of classical logic.

Note that we use the notation [α] in two different contexts, namely in thecontext of a CRS and in the context of a GKLM model. In the present situationthe notions coincide, since we have `Σ,α β iff sα(β) = 1

Lemma 9.9 If `Σ,β≤α`Σ,γ and `Σ,γ≤α`Σ,β, then `Σ,β=`Σ,γ .

Page 124: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

124 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

Proof. Assume that `Σ,β≤α`Σ,γ and `Σ,γ≤α`Σ,β . Then we observe, inspect-ing the definition of ≤α, that we have both `Σ,β α and `Σ,γ α. But in this case,again by the definition of ≤α, the above is only possible if `Σ,β γ and `Σ,γ β.From this it follows by classical logic that `Σ,β=`Σ,γ .

Lemma 9.10 `Σ,α∧β is the unique ≤α-minimal element in [β], where [β] de-notes the proposition represented by β in the logic LL,Σ.

Proof. First note that `Σ,α∧β∈ [β], since `Σ,α∧β β. Clearly, `Σ,α∧β α. Let`Σ,γ∈ [β]. If not `Σ,γ α then `Σ,α∧β≤α`Σ,γ . If `Σ,γ α then, since `Σ,γ β,`Σ,γ α ∧ β. But this means `Σ,α∧β≤α`Σ,γ for every `Σ,γ∈ [β]. From this andthe last lemma it follows that `Σ,α∧β a ≤α-minimal element in [β]. To see thatit is unique, let `Σ,δ be any ≤α-minimal element of [β]. We have `Σ,α∧β≤α`Σ,δ.Since `Σ,δ is ≤α-minimal in [β] we get `Σ,δ=`Σ,α∧β .

Theorem 9.4 HL,Σ is an H-model for LL,Σ.

Proof. We need to prove that for every x =`Σ,α∈ CΣ,L, Mx = 〈CΣ,L,≤x, l〉 isa GKLM model for x. We have smoothness by Lemma 17

Suppose β `Σ,α γ. By definition this means Σ ∪ α ∧ β ` γ, which isequivalent to `Σ,α∧β∈ [γ] and our claim follows from Lemma ? and Definition?.

9.2 The Concept of a Holistic Logic

We now have the technical equipment to present the logical structure that cor-respond to the intuitions discussed earlier in this chapter.

Let us start from our motivating example. In that example the consequencerelations cannot be ’characterised’ by a single formula, i.e. given any `α, thenthere exists no formula β such that β is provable in `α and only in `α. We takethis observation as a motivation for studying logics in which every consequencerelation has a ’characterising’ formula.

Definition 9.7 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a logic with the following properties.

• For any non-zero |∼0∈ C there exists a formula σ|∼0 such that |∼ σ|∼0 iff|∼=|∼0. We call σ a pointer to |∼.

• For every |∼∈ C there exist a formula α such that neither |∼ α nor |∼ ¬α.

We call L a (non-degenerate) holistic logic if both of the above conditions aresatisfied. We call L degenerate holistic if the first condition is satisfied burnot necessarily the second one. We call L totally degenerate if no consequencerelation satisfies the second condition.

Page 125: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.2. THE CONCEPT OF A HOLISTIC LOGIC 125

Remarks: Any two pointers σ1 and σ2 to the same consequence relation are(globally) equivalent, i.e. [σ1] = [σ2] We assume the consequence relation re-ferred to later to be consistent without expplicit mentioning.

Intuitively, the second condition says that every consequence relation |∼mustbe genuinely revisable, i.e. we assume that there exiats a formula α such that|∼α is consistent and distinct from |∼. Assume we have consequence relationsin a CRS that are not genuinely revisable. Then we can ’take them out’ ofthe revision system and restrict ’proper’ revision to the rest so as to get a non-degenerate system. It follows that a (non degenerate) holistic logic has at leasttwo consequence relations. We will always use the term ’holistic’ in the sense of’non degenerate holistic’ except in the theorem which we call the Limiting CaseTheorem. In the case of a totally degenerate holistic logic there is no genuinerevision at all.

In the next subsections we state some salient properties of holistic logics.

9.2.1 Orthogonality, Encodedness, Dimension

Definition 9.8 Let L be a holistic logic and let |∼1 and |∼2 be two consequencerelations L with pointers σ1 and σ2 respectively. Then we say that |∼1 and |∼2

are orthogonal if |∼1 ¬σ2 and |∼2 ¬σ1.

Actually it suffices to require one of the two conditions. It can then be proved,using the global condition ?, that the relation thus defined is symmetric

The following Lemma follows from the definition of a pointer and that of aconsequence revision systems.

Lemma 9.11 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic, |∼1, |∼2∈ C. If |∼1 and 2

are not orthogonal, then |∼1σ2=|∼2 and vice versa. If they are orthogonal we

have |∼1σ2= 0 and vice versa.

Lemma 9.12 Let L be a holistic logic and |∼1 and |∼2 two non-orthogonalconsequence relations. Then we have α |∼1 β iff σ1 |∼2 (α ; β) and vice versa.

Proof. Recall that |∼1 and |∼2 are non-orthogonal iff |∼2σ1=|∼1 and vice

versa. We have α |∼2 β iff |∼2 α ; β, since ; is internalising. α |∼2 β isthus equivalent to |∼2σ1

α ; β. But this is by Lemmas ? and ? the case iffσ1 |∼2 α ; β.

The above lemma says that non-orthogonal consequence relations are ’encoded’in each other. This fact is the motivation for calling these structures ’holistic’.

Definition 9.9 Let L be a holistic logic. We call a family |∼i(i∈I) of pairwiseorthogonal consequence relations a basis of L if for any |∼ of L there exists a basisconsequence relation |∼j not orthogonal to |∼. We call L finite- dimensional iffit admits a finite basis. If L is finite-dimensional we say it has dimension n ifit admits a basis of n elements and no basis of fewer elements.

Page 126: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

126 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

Remark: We may view the basis consequence relations |∼i as containing allthe ’information’ of the logic L in the sense that every consequence relation isencoded in at least one basis consequence relation.

Lemma 9.13 Let L = 〈C,F , ;〉 be a holistic logic and |∼∈ C with pointer σ.Then we have

• (i) |∼ α iff [σ ; α] = [>] and thus [¬(σ ; α)] = [⊥]

• (ii) |6∼ α iff [σ ; α] = [¬σ] and thus [¬(σ ; α)] = [σ]

Proof. (i) For the direction from left to right suppose |∼ α and note that forany |∼1 orthogonal to |∼1 we have |∼1 σ ; α. If |6∼1 non-orthogonal to |∼ wehave by ’encodedness’ that |∼ σ ; α. Thus [σ ; α] = C = [>]. The otherdirection is obvious.(ii) Suppose that |6∼ α. Then, again, we have for every |∼1 orthogonal to |∼ that|∼1 σ ; α. But if |∼1 is not orthogonal to |∼, |∼1 σ ; α cannot hold, since thiswould imply |∼ α contrary to the hypothesis. Thus [σ ; α] = [¬σ]. The otherdirection is obvious.

Remark: Thus the propositions corresponding to formulas which are transla-tions of metastatements have the form [σ], [¬σ], [>], [⊥]. They form a Booleanalgebra in a natural way.

9.2.2 Selfreferential Soundness and Completeness

In this section we introduce the notion of self-referential completeness in connec-tion with consequence relations. This notion was first introduced by Smullyanin [59] for modal systems. We shall prove that the consequence relations of aholistic logic are self-referentially sound and complete and, with a certain trivialexception, non-monotonic.

We now define a meta-language in which we can talk about provability.Intuitively, DER(α, β) means ”β is derivable from α in |∼”.

Definition 9.10 • (i) If α, β are wffs of the object language, then DER(α, β) ∈ML.

• If α is a wff of the object language and ϕ ∈ ML, then DER(α, ϕ) ∈ MLand DER(ϕ, α) ∈ ML.

• If ϕ,ψ ∈ ML, then DER(ϕ,ψ) ∈ ML.

• If ϕ,ψ ∈ ML, so are ¬ϕ, ϕ ∧ ψ, ϕ ∨ ψ, ϕ → ψ.

We use the following abbreviations:

PROV α =: DER(>, α)

CONα =: ¬PROV ¬α

EQUIV (α, β) =: DER(α, β) ∧DER(β, α)

Page 127: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.2. THE CONCEPT OF A HOLISTIC LOGIC 127

We now define a natural translation of the meta-language ML into the ob-ject language. We assume that we have a logic L = 〈C, F, ;〉. The followingdefinitions are relative to a fixed |∼∈ C having a pointer σ to itself.

Definition 9.11 Let σ be a pointer to |∼. Define the translation ′ as follows.

• (i) If ϕ = DER(α, β) where α and β are formulas of the object language,ϕ′ = σ ; (α ; β)

• (ii) If ϕ = DER(α, ψ), where α is a formula of the object language andψ ∈ ML, then ϕ′ = σ ; (α ; ψ′); analogously for the case DER(ψ, α)

• (iii) If ϕ = DER(ψ, ρ), where ψ, ρ ∈ ML ϕ′ = σ ; (ψ′ ; ρ′)

• (iv) If ϕ = ¬ψ, ϕ′ = ¬(σ ; ψ′),

• (v) If ϕ = ψ ∧ ρ, ϕ′ = ψ′ ∧ ρ′; analogously for the other connectives.

We now define the notion of truth for ML in a natural way. This definition oftruth is in the spirit of what Smullyan calls a self-referential interpretation inthe above mentioned books.

Just recall the essential feature of the definition of self-referential truth.Given a modal system M . Then we say that a formula of the form 2A is(self-referentially) true with respect to M iff A is provable in M .

Definition 9.12 • (i) If ϕ = DER(α, β), where α, β are formulas of theobject language, then TRUE ϕ iff α |∼ β

• (ii) If ϕ = DER(α, ψ), where α is a wff of the object language, then TRUEϕ iff α |∼ ψ′; analogously for the case DER(ψ, α)

• (iii) If ϕ = DER(ψ, ρ) for ψ, ρ ∈ ML, then TRUE ϕ iff ψ′ |∼ ρ′.

• (iv) If ϕ = ¬ψ, then TRUE ϕ iff not TRUE ψ; analogously for the otherconnectives.

Definition 9.13 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic, |∼∈ C and σ a pointerto |∼. We say that |∼ is self-referentially sound if for all ϕ ∈ ML we have:

|∼ ϕ′ implies TRUE ϕ.

We say that |∼ is self-referentially complete if

TRUE ϕ implies |∼ ϕ′

Lemma 9.14 Given a non-zero |∼0, |∼∈ C, with pointer σ such that |6∼ ¬σ.Then

(i) α |∼0 β iff |∼ σ ; (α ; β)

Moreover, we have

Page 128: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

128 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

• (ii) |∼ α iff [σ ; α] = [>] and thus [¬(σ ; α)] = [⊥]

• (iii) |6∼ α iff [σ ; α] = [¬σ] and thus [¬(σ ; α)] = [σ]

Remark: We may view the formula ¬(σ ; α) as expressing the unprovabilityof α at the object level. It thus follows from (iii) of the above lemma that, if αis not provable, then its unprovabilty can be proved. This is a remarkable factunfamiliar from classical logic which has far-reaching consequences concerningself-referential completeness and non-monotonicity.

Theorem 9.5 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic, |∼∈ C with pointer σ.Then|∼ is self-referentially sound and complete.

Proof. By induction on the construction of the formulas of ML.(i) Case ϕ = DER(α, β). By definition TRUE ϕ means α |∼ β. But this means|∼ α ; β, which is equivalent to |∼ σ ; (α ; β). But this says that |∼ ϕ′.(ii) Case ϕ = DER(α, ψ). Suppose TRUE ϕ. By definition this says α |∼ ψ′

or equivalently |∼ σ ; (α ; ψ′). But this is exactly what |∼ ϕ′ means.(iii) Case ϕ = DER(ψ, ρ). The proof is analogous to (ii).

(iv) Case ϕ = ¬ψ. TRUE ϕ means that not TRUEψ. By the inductionhypothesis this is equivalent to not |∼ ψ′, which by ‘provability of unprovability’says that |∼ ¬(σ ; ψ′). But this means |∼ ϕ′.(v) Case ϕ = ψ ∨ ρ. First note that ϕ′ = ψ′ ∨ ρ′. Suppose TRUE ϕ. It followsthat TRUE ψ or TRUE ρ. Without loss of generality assume TRUE ψ. Bythe induction hypothesis we have |∼ ψ′ and thus |∼ ψ′ ∨ ρ′. But this says |∼ ϕ′.

For the other direction suppose |∼ ϕ′. We need to prove that TRUE ϕ.There is a problem here, namely that, generally, |∼ ψ′ ∨ ρ′ does not imply that|∼ ψ′ or |∼ ρ′. To overcome this obstacle we first observe by inspecting thedefinition of the translation that any formula occurring as a translation is of theform σ ; ... or ¬(σ ; ... or a Boolean combination of such formulas. It thenfollows by Lemma ?? that the propositions [ψ′] and [ρ′] are of the form [>],[⊥], [σ], [¬σ]. We can thus treat this case by checking all combinations.

Suppose for instance that [ψ′] = [>] and [ρ′] = [¬σ]. Then |∼ ψ′ ∨ ρ′ says|∼ > ∨ ¬σ, which is equivalent to |∼ >, i.e. |∼ ψ′. It follows by the inductionhypothesis that TRUE ψ and thus TRUE ϕ.

The other combinations can be checked in an analogous manner. The sameapplies to the other cases.

Remark: Inspecting the translation of the metalanguage into the objectlanguage, we may view the metalanguage as a ‘sublanguage’ of the object lan-guage. The peculiar feature of this ‘sublanguage’ is that it contains a ’proofoperator’, namely σ ;, as opposed to ’proof predicates’ which we have in otherlanguages. Our notion of self-referentiality thus becomes fully analogous to thatintroduced by Smullyan in connection with self-application of modal systems,where the modal operator 2 plays the role of a proof operator.Example: Let us consider an example and and let us for the sake of illustrationverify the truth of the claim made in the above theorem directly. Let α be anobject formula and consider the following metastatement

Page 129: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.2. THE CONCEPT OF A HOLISTIC LOGIC 129

ϕ = PROV α → CONα

Its translation is

ϕ′ = (σ ; (> ; α)) → ¬(σ ; (σ ; (> ; ¬α)))

Let us first verify that TRUE ϕ implies |∼ ϕ′. Assume that not TRUE PROV α.This means TRUE¬PROV α, which says that |6∼ α. By Lemma ?? we have[¬(σ ; (> ; α))] = [σ]. Thus [ϕ′] = [σ ∨ ...] and we have |∼ ϕ′.Now assume TRUE CONα, i.e. |6∼ ¬α and thus |6∼ > ; ¬α, hence |6∼ σ ;

(> ; ¬α). In this case we have by Lemma 20 [¬(σ ; (σ ; (> ; ¬α)))] = [σ].Thus [ϕ′] = [... ∨ σ] and we have |∼ ϕ′.Let us now verify that |∼ ϕ′ implies TRUE ϕ. So assume |∼ ϕ′. [¬(σ ; (σ ;

(> ; α)))] equals either [⊥] or [σ]. In the first case we have |∼ α. Since |∼is assumed to be consistent, we have |6∼ ¬α, which means TRUE CONα. Butthis says that TRUE ϕ.In the second case we have |6∼ α and thus not TRUE PROV α in which caseagain TRUE ϕ.

Here are a few examples of self-referentially true and thus provable metafor-mulas.We have TRUEϕ for the following metastatements.

• ϕ = ¬EQUIV (α,¬PROV α)

• ϕ = CONα → ¬DER(α,¬PROV α)

• ϕ = PROV α ↔ EQUIV (α,¬PROV⊥)

By self-referential completeness we have in all three cases |∼ ϕ′. Note that forthe first of the examples this means that the consequence relation ‘knows’ thatit has no Godel fixed points. We will elaborate on this later.

9.2.3 Connection with the Modal System D

The last subsection gives rise to the consideration of a certain modal systemknown in modal logic as the system D. More precisely, we shall be interestedonly in the letterless (deictic) fragment of D. This means that we are onlyconcerned with those theorems of D containing no propositional symbols otherthan > and ⊥. Such formulas are also called modal sentences.The system D is obtained from the modal system K by adding the followingaxiom.

2p → ¬2¬p

Having the provability interpretation of the box in mind, we may view the axiomas just stating consistency.

Note that we are only interested in the letterless form of the above axiomand, more generally, in all letterless formulas which are theorems of the systemD. Call this fragment MC.

Page 130: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

130 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

We also might have chosen the following way of introducing MC. We couldhave confined ourselves to the letterless fragment of the language and couldhave stipulated the following.

(i) All letterless substitutional instances of classical tautologies are theoremsof MC.

(ii) The rules of inference for MC are necessitation and modus ponens.It can then be proved that D is a conservative extension of the system MC thusintroduced.

Lemma 9.15 For any modal sentence A we have

• (i) `MC A or `MC ¬A

• (ii) `MC 2A iff `MC A

Proof. (i) For the modal sentences > and ⊥ the claim is obvious.Consider the case A = 2B. Assume that not `MC A. We need to prove that`MC ¬A. We have that not `MC B, since otherwise necessitation would giveus `MC A, contrary to the assumption. By the induction hypothesis we have`MC ¬B and by necessitation `MC 2¬B. Now, since `MC 2¬B → ¬2B, weget by modus ponens `MC ¬2B, which means `MC ¬A. The case of Booleancombinations is straightforward.(ii) Assume `MC 2A and not `MC A. By (i) we then have that `MC ¬A andthus by necessitation `MC 2¬A. Since `MC 2¬A → ¬2A, modus ponens givesus `MC ¬2A, which contradicts the consistency of the system D.

As an immediate corollary of the above theorem we get, using necessitation,that not ` A implies ` ¬2A. This can be viewed as the ‘modal version’ of‘provability of unprovability’. We could of course have established the aboveresult semantically using the fact that the system D is complete for the class ofKripke frames such that for any possible world there exists a world accessiblefrom it.For the next theorem we use the terms ‘self-referentially sound’ and ‘self-referentiallycomplete’ as defined by Smullyan in ’Forever Undecided’. Recall that the mainclause in the definition of self-referential truth is

TRUE 2A iff `MC A

Theorem 9.6 MC is self-referentially sound and complete. In particular itcan prove its own consistency.

Proof. For self-referential correctness it suffices to prove that the axioms aretrue. Let us check the axiom 2> → ¬2⊥. Since `MC >, 2> is true and weneed to show that ¬2⊥ is true. But this is the case iff the system is consistent,which is well known from modal logic.

Page 131: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.2. THE CONCEPT OF A HOLISTIC LOGIC 131

For self-referential completeness we need to prove that for any A the truth of Aimplies ` A. Again, the only cases not completely obvious are the cases A = 2Band A = ¬B. Suppose A = 2B is true. This means ` B. By necessitation wehave ` 2B and thus ` A. Suppose A = ¬B is true. This says that B is nottrue and thus by the induction hypothesis not ` B. By the above lemma thismeans ` ¬B and thus ` A.

Since the system D is consistent, we have TRUE ¬2⊥ and thus by self-referential completeness `MC ¬2⊥. It is in this sense that we can say thatD can prove its own consistency. Recall that the famous modal system G forinstance does not have this property, because by Solovay’s completeness theoremthis would contradict Godel’s incompleteness theorem.

Notice at this point that the modal operator is trivial for MC.Let us now describe the connection between the considerations of the last

section and the system MC. Consider the fragment MLP of the metalanguageML consisting of those formulas in which only PROV occurs. More precisely,it is the following (meta-) language. It is the smallest set such that

• If α is a wfff of the object language, then PROV α ∈ MLP .

• If ϕ ∈ MLP , then PROV ϕ ∈ MLP .

• If ϕ,ψ ∈ MLP , so are ¬ϕ,ϕ ∧ ψ, ϕ ∨ ψ,ϕ → ψ.

Let |∼ be a consequence relation, α a wff of the object language. We say that αhas truth value > with respect to |∼, if |∼ α, otherwise we say that α has truthvalue ⊥ with respect to |∼. Now, given a formula ϕ ∈ MLP and a consequencerelation |∼ having a pointer to itself. Then we define ϕd to be the modal sentenceresulting from ϕ by replacing every occurrence of PROV by the modal operator2 and all occurrences of wffs of the object language by their truth values withrespect to |∼. Then we have the

Theorem 9.7 Let |∼ have a pointer to itself, let ϕ ∈ MLP . Then the followingstatements are equivalent.

• (i) TRUE ϕ

• (ii) |∼ ϕ′

• (iii) `MC ϕd

• (iv) TRUE ϕd

Remark: Note that in (i) TRUE is self-referential truth in the sense of theorem13, whereas in (iv) TRUE means self-referential truth in the modal sense.

Proof. The equivalence between (i) and (ii) is given by selfreferential com-pleteness of |∼, the equivalence of (iii) and (iv) is given by self-referential com-pleteness of the modal system D.We need to prove that (i) and (iii) are equivalent. Case ϕ = PROV α. Assume

Page 132: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

132 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

TRUE ϕ. This means |∼ α and thus ϕd = 2> and, clearly, `MC ϕd. For theother direction note that either ϕd = 2> or ϕ = 2⊥. Since `MC ϕd we haveϕd = 2>. It follows that the truth value of α must be > and thus |∼ α. Butthis means TRUE PROV α.Case ϕ = PROV ψ. Assume TRUE ϕ. This means |∼ ψ′. We have ϕd = 2ψd

and by the induction hypothesis `MC ψd. Hence `MC 2ψd, which says `MC ϕd.For the other direction let `MC ϕd, i.e. `MC 2ψd. By Lemma 22 this is quiva-lent to ϕ `MC ψd. The induction hypthesis yields |∼ ψ′. But this says TRUEϕ.The other cases are straightforward.

As a corollary we get a reduction theorem for PROV regarded as a modality.Given any |∼ of a holistic logic. Then any sequence of modalitis reduces toone containing only one 2, i.e. every modality is equivalent with tespect to |∼to either 2 or ¬2. Use this point of view in the formulation of the limitingcase theorem! In the limit the proof operator becomes completely trivial. It isseemimgly no longer there. Talking about provability then looks like talking aboutthe (external) world.

9.2.4 No Godel fixed points

Proposition 9.5 Let L, 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic. |∼∈ C with pointer σ.Then |∼ does not admit Godelian fixed points, i.e. (consistent) formulas equiv-alent to their own unprovability. This means that there exists no (consistent)formula such that

(i) α |∼ ¬(σ ; α).

(ii) ¬(σ ; α) |∼ α

Proof. Assume there exists a Godelian fixed point α. Suppose |∼ α. Then itfollows from (i) that |∼ ¬(σ ; α). By ’provability of unprovability we wouldhave |6∼ α, contrary to the hypothesis. Now suppose |6∼ α. Then, again by prov-ability of unprovability |∼ ¬(σ ; α) and thus by (ii) |∼ α, again contradictingthe hypothesis. .

9.2.5 Justifying logical rules

In justifying logical rules we normally invoke the notion of truth. Consider forexample modus ponens:

If |∼ α and |∼ α → β, then |∼ β

We accept this rule in classical logic because it preserves truth. If α is trueand α → β is true, then so is β. In classical logic, the concept of truth is ameta concept. So we justify logical rules at the meta level. Classical logic itselfcannot justify its rules. This is different in the case of a holistic logic. Take theabove example of modus ponens. In a holistic logic we do have modus ponens ifwe restrict the language to (translations) of metastements. The metastatementexpressing modus ponens is

Page 133: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.3. NO WINDOWS THEOREMS 133

ϕ = (PROV α ∧DER(α, β)) → PROV β

Since ϕ is true, we have by self-referential completeness, |∼ ϕ′. It is in this sensethat we may say that the logic justifies (proves) the rule of modus ponens.

9.2.6 The case of a complete classical theory

Recall the definition of LΣ = 〈CΣ,FΣ,→〉 from the motivating example. Wehave the

Proposition 9.6 Let Σ be a consistent set of formulas. Then LΣ = 〈CΣ,FΣ,→〉 is holistic iff Σ is a complete classical theory. In this case LΣ is (totally)degenerate. It has dimension 1 and we have C = `Σ, 0andFΣ(α,`Σ) =`Σ ifα ∈ Σ, else 0.

Proof. Observe that for any α such that neither Σ ` ¬α nor Σ ` α, `Σ is aproper subset of `Σ, α). So in this case `Σ cannot have a pointer. It followsthat `Σ can have a pointer only if for every α either Σ ` α or Σ ` ¬α, i.e. Σis a complete theory. In fact, in this case any formula α such that Σ ` α is apointer to `Σ

9.3 No Windows Theorems

9.3.1 The Local No Windows Theorem

Given a holistic logic L = 〈C, F, ;〉 and |∼∈ C with pointer σ. Then we defineΣσ =: α ||∼ α, to be the local theory of |∼. We denote by Σg its global theory,i.e. Σg =: α ||∼ α for all |∼∈ C.Lemma 9.16 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic and |∼∈ C with pointer σ.Suppose |∼ α. Then σ ; α ∈ Σg.

Proof. Let |∼1∈ C. Suppose |∼1 is orthogonal to |∼. Then |∼1) σ = 0 Then,clearly, σ |∼1 α and thus |∼1 σ ; α. Suppose |∼1 is not orthogonal to |∼. Inthis case we have |∼1σ =|∼. Thus |∼1σα. It follows that σ |∼1 α which means|∼1 σ ; α. We have proved that σ ; α ∈ Σg

Lemma 9.17 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic and |∼∈ C with pointer σ.Suppose ; is classically equivalent to →, i.e. material implication. Assumethat Σg ∪ σ is classically consistent. Then we have |∼ α iff Σg ∪ σ ` α.

Proof. For the direction from left to right note that |∼ α implies by lemma? that σ ; α ∈ Σg and, since ; is assumed to be classically equivalent to→, we have Σg ∪ σ ` α. For the other direction suppose Σg ∪ σ ` α andassume |6∼ α. We have Σg ∪ σ ` σ → α. On the other hand we have by

Page 134: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

134 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

’provability of unprovability’ |∼ ¬(σ ; α) and thus, by the direction alreadyproved, Σg ∪ σ ` ¬(σ ; α) and thus, since ; is classically equivalent to →Σg ∪ σ ` ¬(σ → α)

Σg ∪ σ would thus be classically inconsistent contrary to the hypothesis.It follows that |∼ α.

We call the following theorem the (local) No Windows Theorem because it isreminiscent of what Leibniz in his ”Monadology” says about the monads: ”Themonads have no windows”.

Theorem 9.8 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a non-degenerate holistic logic. Suppose; is classically equivalent to material implication. Let σ be any pointer. ThenΣg ∪ σ is classically inconsistent. Thus, Σσ is classically inconsistent

Proof. Let σ be any pointer with corresponding |∼∈ C. Assume that Σg ∪σis classically consistent. Let α be such that |6∼ ¬α and |6∼ α. By the hypoth-esis of non-degeneracy such a formula exists. Then we have by ’provability ofunprovability’ and non-monotonicity

(1)|∼ ¬(σ ; α)

(2) α |6∼ ¬(σ ; α)

We have by Lemma ?

(3) Σg ∪ σ ` ¬(σ ; α)

and thus by classical logic

(4) Σg ∪ σ ` α → ¬(σ ; α)

Since ; is classically equivalent to →, it follows that

(5) Σg ∪ σ ` α ; ¬(σ ; α)

Again, by Lemma 27 we get

(6) |∼ α ; ¬(σ ; α)

and thus

(7) α |∼ ¬(σ ; α)

But (7) contradicts (2). It follows that Σg ∪ σ is classically inconsistent.

Page 135: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.3. NO WINDOWS THEOREMS 135

9.3.2 The Global No Windows Theorem

We now restrict ourselves to the case of a finite-dimensional holistic logic. Inthis case we can sharpen the no windows theorem so as to get a Kochen-Speckertype result as a special case.

Lemma 9.18 Let L be any logic and α such that |6∼ α for every |∼6= 0. Thenα ; ⊥ ∈ Σg.

Proof. Given any |∼∈ C. We claim that |∼α= 0. For otherwise we would have|∼α α with |∼α 6= 0 contrary to the hypothesis. Thus |∼α ⊥, which means α |∼ ⊥and thus |∼ α ; ⊥. We have proved that α ; ⊥ ∈ Σg.

The following theorem is a summary of previous results and, moreover, con-tains the strengthened version of the no windows theorem.

Theorem 9.9 Let L = 〈C,F , ;〉 be a non-degenerate holistic logic. Supposethat ; is classically equivalent to →, i.e. material implication. Then we havethe following

• (i) Every consistent |∼∈ C is non-monotonic.

• (ii) For any |∼∈ C, Σσ is classically inconsistent.

• (iii) If L is finite dimensional, then Σg is classically inconsistent. In fact,it contains a classical contradiction.

Proof. (i) and (ii) summarise results proved earlier.As to (iii) let (|∼i), i = 1, .., n a basis with pointers σi. We have by Theorem

24

Σg ` ¬σi, i = 1, ..., n.

Therefore

Σg `∧¬σi

For any |∼6= 0 we have by the definition of a basis

|6∼ ∧¬σi

For otherwise |∼ would be orthogonal to all elements of the basis contrary tothe definition of a basis. It follows by Lemma ? that

∧¬σi ; ⊥ ∈ Σg

Thus

Σg `∧¬σi ; ⊥

and, since ; is classically equivalent to →,

Page 136: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

136 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

Σg `∧¬σi → ⊥

It follows that

Σg ` ⊥Thus Σg is classically inconsistent. Then there exists a finite set α1, ..., αn ⊂Σg which is classically inconsistent. Since Σg is closed under conjunctions wehave

∧αi ∈ Σg

But this conjunction is a classical contradiction.

We do not have the following yet in the book. It’s in the section ”Kochen-Specker-Schuette revisited” But the results are correct.

Corollary 9.1 Let Hbe a finite dimensional orthomodular space and dimH ≥2. Let LH,ψ be a logic presented by H. Then Σg is classically inconsistent.

Corollary 9.2 Under the above hypotheses there exists a classical tautology φsuch that for all x ∈ H we have `x ¬φ.

We may strengthen the above resuls a bit. Namely note that in a Hilbert spaceH at least 2 we have the following. For any x ∈ H there exists y ∈ H such thatneither x ∈ 〈y〉 nor x ∈ 〈y〉⊥ Analysing the proof of the no windows theoremwe then get

Corollary 9.3 Let H be a Hilbert space logic of dimension at least 2. Let Σp

be the set of formulas of Σg built up from pointers only. Then Σp is classicallyinconsistent. Thus there exists a classical tautology φ built up from pointerssuch that `x ¬φ for all x ∈ H.

For the corollaries observe that logics presented by finite dimensional ortho-modular spaces and thus by finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces are holistic andthe internalising connective is the Sasaki hook, which is classically equivalent tomaterial implication. Corollary 2 is the result by Kochen-Specker saying thatthere exists a classical contradiction which under a suitable interpretation of thevariables as closed subspaces of a finite-dimensional Hilbert space represents thefull space. It is even a generalisation, since the Kochen-Specker-Schuette tau-tology is in Hilbert space.

9.4 Limiting case theorem

The special theory of relativity has classical mechanics as a limiting case in thesense that classical mechanics holds for ’small velocities’. For ’small velocities’relativistic effects are negligible.

Similarly, quantum mechanics may be regarded as having classical mechanicsas a limiting case. We investigate here the logical analogue of this fact withinthe framework of holistic logics.

Page 137: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.4. LIMITING CASE THEOREM 137

9.4.1 Non-commuting operators in consequence revisionsytems

Proposition 9.7 Given a consequence revision system 〈C, F 〉. Suppose that allrevision operators commute. Then every |∼ is monotonic.

Proof. Assume that all revision operators commute and let |∼∈ C. Assume|∼ β. This means |∼β=|∼. Now let α be any formula. Note that |∼α,β β.The above notation means that |∼ is first revised by α and then by β. Since therevision operators coresponding to α and β commute, we have |∼β,α=|∼α,β . But|∼β,α=|∼α. It follows that |∼α β but this says that α |∼ β.Thus |∼ is monotonic.

Note that from the above proposition it follows that in a consequence re-vision system containing non-monotonic consequence relations we have non-commuting revision operators.

Let us now point out certain analogies between uncertainty relations and theprojection postulate in quantum mechanics on the one hand and non commut-ing revision operators and non-monotonic consequence relations in consequencerevision systems on the other.

Consider two observables A and B in quantum mechanics with non-commutingoperators, say position and momentum. For such observables we have an un-certainty relation. Roughly, this means the following. Assume the quantumsystem is in a state x in which observable A is not sharp. In other words, if wemeasure A in state x, we get the values A which can assume only with a certainprobabilities. Now, assume we perform a measurement of observable A and getas a result of measurement a certain value λ, i.e. the result of the measurementis a proposition of the form ”A = λ”. Now, according to quantum mechanics,the system has changed its state in such a way that in the new state y observableA is sharp and any subsequent measurement yields as a result the proposition”A = λ”. This is the projection postulate of quantum mechanics. Note the anal-ogy with revision! The state y, however, needn’t be a state in which observableBy is sharp. Assume we now perform a measurement of B. We then end up in astate z in which B is sharp with proposition ”B = µ”. However, it may happenthat in state z observable A is no longer sharp, i.e. the proposition ”A = λ”no longer ’holds’. This phenomenon is due to the uncertainty relation holdingbetween A and B. Note the analogy with non-monotonicity of consequencerelations and revision!

We said that in quantum mechanics the passage to the limit, i.e. classicalmechanics, is from uncertainty relations to the absence of uncertainty relations.What is, in view of the above intuitive consideration, the analogue of this processof passing to the limit at the level of logic? It should be the passage from non-monotonicity to monotonicity. Let’s see what we get.

9.4.2 The Limiting Case Theorem

We call the following theorem the Limiting Case Theorem for holistic logics.

Page 138: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

138 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

Theorem 9.10 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic such that every |∼∈ C ismonotonic. Then L is totally degenerate, i.e. every |∼∈ C has the form `Σ forsome (consistent) complete classical theory Σ.

Proof. Suppose that |∼∈ C is monotonic. Let α be such that |6∼ α. Then wehave by ‘provability of unprovability’ that |∼ ¬(σ ; α) and by monotonicityα |∼ ¬(σ ; α). Since [¬(σ ; α)] = |∼, 0, we have |∼ ¬α. Thus for any α wehave either |∼ α or |∼ ¬α. We say that |∼ is complete as a consequence relation.

Put Σ =: α ||∼ α. We now observe that Σ has the following properties:

(i) α ∧ β ∈ Σ iff α ∈ Σ and β ∈ Σ

(ii) α ∨ β ∈ Σ iff α ∈ Σ or β ∈ Σ

(iii) ¬α ∈ Σ iff αΣ

It is then a fact of classical logic that Σ is classically consistent and complete.

(i) follows from the conditions we require a class of consequence relationsto satisfy. We get (ii) as follows. |∼ α ∨ β implies |∼ ¬(¬α ∧ ¬β). This is oneof the general conditions we impose on consequence relations in this book. Bycompleteness of |∼ we have that |6∼ (¬α ∧ ¬β). It follows that |6∼ ¬α or |6∼ ¬βand thus again by completeness of |∼, |∼ α or |∼ β. (iii) expresses completenessof |∼

From the above it follows that α |∼ β iff |∼ ¬α or |∼ β. Namely, we haveα |∼ β iff |∼α β. Moreover, |∼α=|∼ iff α ∈ Σ iffr |∼α= 0 iff ¬α ∈ Σ. It followsthat ¬α ∈ Σ or β ∈ Σ or equivalently (α → β) ∈ Σ. But this means that → isinternalising. We have proved that |∼=`Σ

The following is another description of the ’limiting case’.

Theorem 9.11 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic. Then the following con-ditions are equivalent.

• Every |∼∈ C is monotonic.

• L is totally degenerate, i.e, every |∼∈ C is of the form |∼=`Σ for somecomplete classical theory Σ

• All revision operators commute

• L is one-dimensional.

Another equivalent condition is that L is a one-dimensional Hilbert spacelogic. But at this stage we do not have this concept yet see Chapter 8).

Note that ’in the limit’ we have monotonicity , classical consistency and thusmodels, a ’reality outside the logic’.

Page 139: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.5. REFLECTING ON SELF-REFERENTIAL COMPLETENESS 139

9.5 Reflecting on Self-Referential Completeness

Let us at this point reflect a bit on the salient features of holistic logics and theirinterplay. We are especially interested in the role of self-referential completeness.

What we, for the purposes of this and the next chapter of this book, calleda logic is a triple of the form 〈C, F, ;〉. It has its motivation in a structurearising in a natural way in connection with classical logic (see section 9.1) Thefirst ingredient of such a logic is a set C of logical entities called consequencerelations. A consequence relation may, traditionally, be viewed as a logic inits own right. So, according to traditional terminology a logic in this sense isa set of logics. The intuition here is, however, that these various logics thatconstitute a holistic logic should not form too heterogeneous a collection. Wemay interpret the requirement that all these various consequence relations havea common internalising connective ; as expressing the intuition that C is nottoo heterogeneous. The third ingredient is that of an action F on C. Formulasact on C, and in general, this action is proper, i.e. given a formula α and some|∼∈ C we have in general that |∼α=: F (α, |∼) 6=|∼.

Now, what are the salient features of holistic logics?We have seen that the consequence relations of a holistic logic are non-

monotonic and self-referentially sound and and complete. Moreover, we havethe No Windows Theorems for holistic logics. Intuitively, this says that in asense, the consequence relations of a holistic logic are completely self-containedlogical entities, logical monads so to speak. This is a remarkable phenomenonwhich - to the authors- is unfamiliar from other branches of logic. We, moreover,consider it remarkable that it is in connection with logical investigations intoquantum mechanics that we hit upon this phenomenon.

Another salient feature of holistic logics is non-monotonicity: all their con-sequence relations are-in the non-denerate case- non-monotonic.

9.5.1 How an agent with full introspection can be consis-tent

Start here with remrks on Smullyan ”Forever Undecided” In his two mater-pieces of logical writing ?? and ?? Smullyan introduces the concept of a self-referential system in connection with systems of modal logic. Given a modalsystem M with the modal operator 2 and let `M denote deducibility in thesystem M . Call a system M self-referentially sound if `M 2α implies `M α.Call it selfreferentiallycompleteif`M α implies `M 2α. Smullyan presentsseveral systems of modal logic that are self-referentially sound, but he does notpresent a self-referentially complete modal system.

Make remarks here about the system G and the system D, which is in factself-refrentially complete. But emphasise that Smullyan is dealing with the deic-tic parts of the system and the system D is the limiting classical case where themodal operator is trivial (invisible). We would like to make the point that it isnon-monotonicity that plays a vital role in making (consistent) self-referentiallycomplete systems possible.

Page 140: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

140 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

The simple statement below -formulated as a theorem- expresses an elemen-tary fact which, however, sheds light on the interplay between non-monotonicity,self-referential completeness and revision in holistic logics.

Technically, we use the term proof operator in the next theorem. For thisrecall that, in a holistic logic, we may view the meta language of a consequencerelation as defined in [?] as a sublanguage of the object language. If we use 2αas an abbreviation for σ ; α, then 2 plays the role of a proof operator.

Definition 9.14 Given a consequence relation |∼. Suppose the language con-tains a connective (primitive or definable by other connectives) such that wehave

• |∼ α iff |∼ 2α

• |6∼ α iff |∼ ¬2α

Then we call 2 a proof operator for |∼.

The reader should note that in our previous investigations the existence of aproof operator was the source of self-referential completeness. Recall that givena holistic logic L = 〈C, F, ;〉 and |∼∈ C with pointer σ. Then the proof operator2 is given by 2α =: σ ; α.

Theorem 9.12 Given a consequence relation |∼. Suppose |∼ admits an inter-nalising connective ; and a proof operator 2. Then |∼ has no proper consistentextension with ; as an internalising connective 2 as a proof operator.

Corollary 9.4 Given a logic 〈C, F, ;〉, let |∼∈ C. Suppose |∼ admits a con-tingent proposition α, i.e. there exists a formula α such that |6∼ α and |6∼ ¬α.Then |∼α admits a proof operator only if there exists a formula β such that |∼ βand not |∼α β.

Note that the above theorem also holds in the limiting case of a consequencerelation of the form `Σ where Σ is a complete classical theory. The reason isthat a complete classical theory is also maximal (see Chapter 2). Note that thecorollary expresses non-monotonicity. The reader may view the argument inthe proof ot theorem 9.12 given below as a formalisation of the argument wegave for the claim that an autoepistemic reasoner with positive and negativeintrospection must be non-monotonic.

Proof.Let |∼ be as in the theorem. Suppose there exists some |∼0 which is consistent

and has ; as an internalising connective and 2 as a proof operator and whichproperly extends |∼, i.e. we have |∼⊂|∼0 and this inclusion is proper. This meansthat there exist formulas α and β such that α |6∼ β and α |∼ β and α |∼0 β.It follows that |6∼ α ; β and |∼0 α ; β. We then have that |∼ ¬2(α ; β)and since |∼0 is an extension of |∼ that |∼0 ¬2(α ; β. But on the other handwe have, since 2 is assumed to be a proof operator for |∼0, that |∼ 2(α ; β),which contradicts the consistency of |∼0.

Page 141: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

9.5. REFLECTING ON SELF-REFERENTIAL COMPLETENESS 141

We get the corollary as follows. Since |6∼ ¬α we have |∼α 6= 0, i.e. |∼α isconsistent. We have |∼α α. Thus |∼6=|∼α. Assume |∼α admits a proof operator.Then, by the above theorem, |∼α is not an extension of |∼. This means thatthere exists a formula β such that |∼ β and not |∼α β.

Let us now think of the formal logial entity of a consequence relation as asort of state (of mind) of some agent and view the proof operator as an epistemicoperator. Think of 2α as saying ”I know α” and ¬2α as saying ”I don’t knowα”. Now consider a state of the agent in which he is undecided about someproposition α, i.e. he neither knows that α nor that ¬α. In this case thereasoner can assign a ’truth value’ neither to α nor to ¬α, i.e his knowledge isincomplete. But let us assume that the agent has the possibility of learning thatα, i.e. of ’completing’ his knowledge. As a result of completing his knowledge bylearning α he would, clearly, end up in a new state of mind, since he now knowsα which in his previous ste he had not known. What the above considerationsshow is that this process of learning cannot be cumulative in the sense that henow knows more than he knew before. Rather the change of state must be suchthat he must have ’forgotten’ something. There must be a proposition β he hadknown before but does not know in his new state of knowledge or of mind ifyou like. The transition of states in the process of learnin α must have beennon-monotonic. It is the non-monotonic nature of the transition of states thatsaved his consistency.

9.5.2 The invisible proof operator in classical logic andclassical mechanics

Let us now revisit the structures we considered in ?. Given a consistent set offormula Σ

Proposition 9.8 Let Σ be consistent. Then `Σ admits a (definable) proof op-erator iff Σ is complete (and thus maximal consistent). In this case the proofoperator is trivial, namely 2α = > → α.

Proof. Suppose `Σ admits a definable proof operator 2. Then we have by thedefinition of a proof operator and by lassical logic that for any α `Σ 2α ↔ αand thus `Σ ¬2α → ¬α. Suppose that not Σ ` α which says that not `Σ α. Itfollows that `Σ ¬2α and by the above remark `Σ ¬α. This says that Σ ` ¬α.Σ is complete and by lemma a maximal consistent set. It is obvious that >αdefines a (trivial) proof operator.

Intuitively, we may view the simple facts stated above in the following light.As we saw several times earlier in the book, families of the form `Σi i∈I , Σi is acomplete classical theory arise as limiting cases of genuine holistic logics havinga non-trivial proof operator. In the limiting case the proof operator applied to aformula α, i.e. the formula 2α ’collaoses’ to α. In the limiting case the statement

Page 142: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

142 CHAPTER 9. HOLISTIC LOGICS

”α is provableor, say, ”α is measurablecollapsessimplycollapsestotheassertionofα.Provability or measurability becomes just truth. The proof operator in the lim-iting case becomes invisible so to speak.

The gist of the above simple consideration is this. Suppose we want to thebuild a logic C, F, ; such that all the elements of C are ’logical monads’, i.e.logical entities which are self- referentially complete and display the ’no windowsphenomenon’. Then the above says that, first, α must act properly, i.e. it must’change’ |∼. Moreover, this change is non-monotonic in the sense that at leastone formula will be ’lost’ in that even if it was provable ’before the change’ itis no longer provable ’after the change’. This is strikingly reminiscent of theuncertainty relations in Quantum Mechanics where things are as follows. Givena state of a physical system in which the physical quantity A is not sharp. Thenmeasure A. As a result we end up in a state in which A is sharp, say A = µ.But this has a price. There must be some physical quantity B which was sharpbefore measurement and which is no longer sharp after measurement. Notethat, logically in view of the above consideration the source of this phenomenonis the existence of a proof operator, which essentially amounts to self-referentialcompleteness.

REFLECT HERE ON THE NOTION OF STATE.

9.5.3 Feynman on the uncertainty principle: the logicaltightrope

The Feynman lectures are unique among the textbooks on physics in many re-spects. Let us see what Feynman says about Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle.Here are some quotations. ”Let us show for one particular case that the kind ofrelation given by Heisenberg must be true in order to keep from getting into trou-ble.” What does he mean by ’getting into troble? To get a clearer picture, hereis another quotation: ”The uncertainty principle protects quantum mechanics.”What does the uncertainty principle ’protect’ quantum mechanics from? Againa quotation: ...ifawaytobeattheuncertaintyrelationwereeverdiscovered, wouldgiveinconsistentresultsandwouldhavetobediscardedasavalidtheoryofnature”.Aleaestiacta!Thekeywordhasbeengiven :inconsistency!Theuncertaintyprincipleprotectsquantummechanicsfrominconsistency.Inconsistencyisalogicalterm.Feynmanis, asfaraswesee, theonlyauthorofatextbookwhomakesaconnectionbetweentheuncertaintyprincipleandlogic.Alastquotation :”Thisisthelogicaltightropeonwhichwemustwalkifwewishtodescribenaturesuccessfully”.Quantummechanics, accordingtoFeynman, isawayofdescribingnaturewhichcanbeconsistentonlyiftheuncertaintyprincipleholds.TheuncertaintyprincipleortheuncertaintyrelationsingeneralarebuiltintothesystemofQMandthuspartofthesystem.Butatthesametime−accordingtoFeynman− guaranteetheconsistencyofthesystem.

Page 143: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 10

Towards Hilbert Space

Let us at this point come back to the general idea underlying the enterpriseof this book. In Chapter 7 we asked ourselves the question what logic coulddo about Quantum Mechanics. We arrived at the conclusion that it wouldnot be our aim to find a new deductive system especially suited for reasoningabout Quantum Mechanics. Rather we said that we should look for logicalstructures implicit in the formalism of Quantum Mechanics which could proveuseful in the task of trying to understand this very formalism. We isolatedtwo types of (related) structures: M-algebras and holistic logics. Both areabstractions from structures we find in Hilbert space. In this we go further. Weask the question ”Can we characterise the core concept of the formalism, namelythat of a Hilbert space in terms of these structures?” This is part of what inthe literture on the foundations of Quntum Mechanics is sometimes called therepresentation enterprise, and theorems of this sort are regarded as ’derivations’of the formalism of Quantum Mechanics from first principles. What we offer inthis Chapter is such derivation. Its peculiarity is that the first principles fromwhich we start are purely logical in nature.

10.1 Presenting Holistic Logics

10.1.1 Orthomodular Holistic logics

Let H be an orthomodular space. Recall that Sub(H) denote the the set ofclosed subspaces of H. We know known that 〈Sub(H),⊂,⊥ 〉 is an orthomodularlattice. Recall that that ⊥ means orthogonal complement formation. We shalluse capital letters A,B, ... for subspaces and, if there is no danger of confusion,for the corresponding projectors. Moreover, we use the symbols for Booleanconnectives in connection with closed subspaces, i.e we write A ∧ B for A ∩ Band we denote the smallest closed subspace containing the closed subspaces Aand B by A ∨B.Let Fml be a propositional anguage, i.e. closed under ¬, ∧ and containing >and ⊥ and let Ψ : Fml → Sub(H) be a surjective function such that Ψ(α∧β)) =

143

Page 144: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

144 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

Ψ(α) ∧ Ψ(β) and Ψ(¬α) = Ψ(α)⊥ . Denote the projectiom corresponding toΨ(α) by A. Let x ∈ H. Then we define the consequence relation `x by

α `x,Ψ β iff Ax ∈ Ψ(β).

We shall simply write `x if Ψ is clear from the context. Note that `x dependsonly on the ray of x, i.e. `x1=`x2 iff the one dimensional subspace 〈x1〉 gener-ated by x1is equal to the one dimensional subspace 〈x2〉 generated by x2.Given an orthomodular space H and a function Ψ as described above, we define

CH,Ψ =: `x| x ∈ H.Let us now define a function that will turn out to be an action on CH,Ψ. DefineFH,Ψ : Fml × CH,Ψ → CH,Ψ by

FH,Ψ(α,`x) =:`Ax.

Note that FH,Ψ is well defined, since 〈x1〉 = 〈x2〉 implies 〈Ax1〉 = 〈Ax2〉.Recall that the Sasaki hook ;s is the connective defined as follows: α ; β =¬α ∨ (α ∧ β.

Theorem 10.1 Let H be an orthomodular space and Ψ a surjective functionas described above. Then LH,Ψ =: 〈CH,Ψ,FH,Ψ, ;s〉 is a holistic logic. Allconsequence relations satisfy conditions 1 and 2 in chapter with the possibleexception of Cut and Cautious Monotonicity. In case H is a Hilbert space allconditions are satisfied.

The following proof is in case that H is a Hilbert space. Cut and CautiousMonotonicity work in the Hilbert space case only

Proof. We first need to verify the conditions imposed on the elements of C.This is routine for the most part.Reflexivity is a consequence of the fact that for x ∈ Ψ(α) we have Ax = x.Let us first verify Cut. So let x ∈ H and assume α∧β `x γ and α `x β. α `x βsays that Ψ(α)x ∈ Ψ(β). Moreover, from the above assumptions it follows thatΨ(α ∧ β)x = Ψ(α)x. By the hypothesis we have Ψ(α ∧ β)x ∈ Ψ(γ) and thusΨ(α)x ∈ Ψ(γ). But this means that α `x γ. Thus, Cut is verified.We now verify Restricted Monotonicity. Assume α `x β and α `x γ. It followsthat Ψ(α)x = Ψ(α ∧ β)x and, since by the hypothesis we have Ψ(α)x ∈ Ψ(γ),we see that Ψ(α ∧ β)x ∈ Ψ(γ), which says that α `x γ. Thus Restricted Mono-tonicity is verified.In order to verify the other conditions use that by definition we have Ψ(α∧β) =Ψ(α) ∧Ψ(β) and Ψ(¬α) = Ψ(α)⊥ and elementary Hilbert space theory.Verify here the ‘global’ conditions for C and make the properties of orthomodularspaces used explicit, pwrkaps in a previous lemma

For the first global condition for instance suppose α |∼CH,Ψ γ and β |∼CH,Ψ γ.This means Ψ(α) ⊂ Ψ(γ) and Ψ(β) ⊂ Ψ(γ). It is then elementary Hilbert spacetheory that Ψ(α ∨ β) ⊂ Ψ(γ). But this says that α ∨ β |∼CH,Ψ γ.

Page 145: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.1. PRESENTING HOLISTIC LOGICS 145

We now prove that FH,Ψ is an action on C. Condition (i) in the definitionof an action is obvious. Consider condition (ii) in Definition ?. Suppose `x ¬α.This is equivalent to x ∈ Ψ(α)⊥, which is the case iff Ax = 0. But this means`Ax= FH,Ψ(α,`x) = 0.Consider condition (iii) in the definition of an action. Let FH,Ψ(β, (FH,Ψ(α,`x

)) = FH,Ψ(α),`x). This is the case iff BAx = Ax, which is equivalent toAx ∈ Ψ(β). But this says that α `x β.

We still need to prove that ;s is internalising for C. Suppose α `x β.By definition this means that Ax ∈ Ψ(β). By Lemma ? this is the case iffx ∈ ¬A ∨ (A ∧B). But this says `x α ;s β.

We call a logic of the above form an orthomodular logic. In case case H is aclassical Hilbert space (see Chapter 3) we call LH,Ψ a Hilbert space logic.

Note that in the context of an orthomodular logic the rays of the underlyingorthomodular space H have a precise logical meaning, namely as representingconsequence relations, which, metaphorically speaking, can be viewed as ’statesof provability’.

10.1.2 The Canonical H-Model for a Hilbert Space Logic

Definition 10.1 Let H be a Hilbert space, Ψ a function as described in the lastsection and x ∈ H. Define the binary relation ≤x on H as follows

x1 ≤x x2 iff: d(x, x1) ≤ d(x, x2)

Moreover, define the structure

Mx,Ψ = 〈H,≤x, lΨ〉 ,

as follows. Let x ∈ H, then lΨ(x) = sx is the singleton consisting of thefollowing Scott-model sx: For α ∈ Fml put sx(α) = 1, if x ∈ Ψ(α), elsesx(α) = 0.

Lemma 10.1 Let LH,Ψ be a Hilbert space logic. Then for every x ∈ H, Mx,Ψ

is a GKLM model for `x,Ψ.

Proof. We first have to verify the smoothness condition. For this observethat for any α we have [α] = Ψ(α). Note that the notation [α] is in the senseof definition of a (GKLM). It suffices to show that every [α] has a unique≤x-minimal element. But this is what Proposition 10 says, namely Ax is thatunique minimal element.It remains to be shown that `x,Ψ=`Mx,Ψ . So let α `x,Ψ β. By definition thismeans Ax ∈ [β]. But this is equivalent to α `x,Ψ β, since Ax is the minimalelement of [β].

We now define an H-structure for a given Hilbert space logic LH,Ψ.

Definition 10.2 Given the Hilbert space logic LH,Ψ = 〈CH,Ψ,FH,Ψ, ;s〉. Con-sider the structure HH,Ψ = 〈H, h,F , lΨ, g〉 such that

Page 146: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

146 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

• h(x) =`x

• F(α, x) = Ax

• The function lΨ is defined as follows: lΨ(x) = sx, where sx(α) = 1 ifx ∈ Ψ(α), 0 else.

• g(x) =≤x as defined in Definition 9.

Theorem 10.2 Given a Hilbert space logic LH,Ψ = 〈CH,Ψ,FH,Ψ,;s〉. ThenHH,Ψ as defined above is an H-model for LH,Ψ.

10.1.3 Hilbert space logics as holistic logics: some prop-erties

Lemma 10.2 Let LH,Ψ be a Hilbert space logic and x ∈ H non zero. Then

• (i) For every x′ not orthogonal to x we have σx `x′ α ;s β iff α `x β

• (ii) `x α iff Ψ(σx ;s α) = H and thus Ψ(¬(σx ;s α)) = 0• (iii) not `x α iff Ψ(σx ;s α) = 〈x〉⊥ and thus Ψ(¬(σx ;s α)) = 〈x〉

Proof. (i) We have by elementary Hilbert space theory that σx `x′=`x if x′

is not orthogonal to x, else σx `x′= 0. Suppose that x′ is not orthogonal to xand σx `x′ α ;s β. By the above remark this is equivalent to `x α ;s β and,since ;s is internalising, this is the case iff α `x β. This proves (i).(ii) Recall that Ψ(σx ;s α) = 〈x〉⊥∨(〈x〉∧Ψ(α)). `x α means that 〈x〉∧Ψ(α) =〈x〉. We thus have Ψ(σx ;s α) = 〈x〉⊥ ∨ 〈x〉 = H.(iii) not `x α means that 〈x〉 ∧Ψ(α) = 0 and thus Ψ(σx ;s α) = 〈x〉⊥.

We call α x-consistent iff not `x ¬α.

Theorem 10.3 Let LH,Ψ be a Hilbert space logic and x ∈ H non zero. Thenwe have

(i) `x α iff `x σx ;s α

(ii) not `x α iff `x ¬(σx ;s α)

(iii) α is x-consistent iff `x ¬(σx ;s ¬α)

Let α be x-consistent.Then we have

(iv) `x α iff α `x ¬(σx ;s ¬α)

Proof. (i) and (ii) follow immediately from Lemma 10. As to (iii) note thatthe x-consistency of α means that not `x ¬α and thus (ii) implies (iii).For (iv) suppose `x α. This means that Ax = x. Since α is x-consistent,we have Ψ(¬(σx ;s ¬α)) = 〈x〉 and thus Ax ∈ Ψ¬(σx ;s ¬α)), which bydefinition means α `x ¬(σx ;s ¬α).

Page 147: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.2. KOCHEN-SPECKER-SCHUTTE REVISITED 147

For the other direction assume α `x ¬(σx ;s ¬α). Since α is x-consistent, Wehave Ax 6= 0. Moreover, since ¬(σx ;s ¬α) = 〈x〉, x is an eigenvalue of A.Using the fact that the only eigenvalues of the projector A are 1 and 0, we getthat Ax = x and thus `x α.

10.2 Kochen-Specker-Schutte revisited

10.2.1 Classical inconsistency in Hilbert space logics

In this section wecome back to the phenomenon first observed by Kochen,Schutte and Specker, namely that Birkoff-von Neumann quantum logic is ’clas-sically inconsistent’.

We start with the following observation. We denote by Hn n-dimensionalHilbert space. Let x1, x2 be non-orthogonal and non-collinear vectors of H2..Let Fml be the language of propositional logic and consider a Hilbert space logicLH2,Ψ0 such that for the propositional variables p1, p2 we have Ψ0(pi) = 〈xi〉,i = 1, 2. Consider the formula φ = φ1 ∧ φ2 ∧ φ3 ∧ φ4 such that

φ1 = p1 ∨ p2

φ2 = ¬p1 ∨ p2

φ3 = p1 ∨ ¬p2

φ4 = ¬p1 ∨ ¬p2

It is easily seen that φ is a classical contradiction which is provable in all con-sequence relations of LH,Ψ0 .

Proposition 10.1 φ is a classical contradiction and for all consequence rela-tions |∼ of LH2,Ψ0 we have |∼ φ

In the case of three dimensional Hilbert space H the above result is muchmore difficult to establish. In [3] Kochen and Specker gave a classical tautologythe negation of which is provable in all consequence relations of a Hilbert spacelogic presented by three dimensional Hilbert space. It has 117 propositionalvariables.

Proposition 10.2 (Kochen-Specker) There exists a classical contradictionα and a Hilbert space logic LH3,Ψ such that |∼ α for all |∼ of L.

Here apply the sharpened no windows theorem and derive the above as acorollary. Comment on this!

This is no accident. It is a spcial case of the following thorem which in turn isan immediate consequence of the No Windows Theorem.

Theorem 10.4 Let H be a finite-dimensional orthomudalar space of dimensionat least 2. Then there exists a classical tautology which under a certain valuationof its variables as closed subspaces of H represents the zero space.

Page 148: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

148 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

Proof. USE THE GLOBAL NO WINDOWS THEOREM

10.2.2 Birkhoff-von Neumann revisited

von Neumann’s letter to Birkhoff

The following has already been said.”Your general remarks I think are very true: I, too, think that our paper

will not be very exhaustive or conclusive, but that we should not attempt tomake it such: The subject is obviously only at the beginning of a development,and we want to suggest the direction of this development much more, than toreach final results. I, for one, do not even believe that the right formal framefor quantum mechanics is already found.”

Birkhoff’ s conditional

The following should probably be said in connection with Implication M-algebras.von Neumann to Birkhoff: ”Last spring you observed: Why not introduce

a logical operation ab for any two (not necessarily simultaneously decidable)properties a and b, meaning this: If you first measure a you find that it ispresent, if you next measure b, you find that it is present too.

This ab cannot be described by any operator, and in particular not by a pro-jection (= linear subspace). The only answer I could then find was this: Thereis no state in which the property ab is certainly present, nor is any in which it iscertainly absent (assuming that a,b are sufficiently non-simultaneously definable= that their projection operators E,F have no common proper-functions not =0 at all).

Of course, for this reason ab is no physical quantity relatively to the themachinery of quantum -mechanics. But how can one motivate this, how canone find a criterion of what is a physical quality and what not, if not by the’causality’ criterion: A statement describes if and only if the states in which itcan be decided with certainty form a complete set.

I wanted to avoid this rather touchy and complicated question, and with-draw to the safe - although perhaps narrow- position of dealing with ’causal’statements’ only. Do you propose to discuss the question fully? It might becometoo philosophical, but I would not say that I object absolutely to it. But it isdangerous ground-except you have a new idea , which settles the question moresatisfactorily.”

Let us take a closer look at this letter. In this letters JvN refers to a ’logicaloperation’ proposed by Birkhoff in an earlier letter (spring 1935?). What doesBirkhoff mean by ’logical operation’? A oonnective probably, so ”ab” is aconditional in our sense. The conditional proposed by Birkhoff is similar to butdifferent from ours. Our conditional says: ”If you measure A, you end up in astate in which B is sharp.” Think of ”sharp” as ”provable”. So given a state x.Then after masuring A we are in state Ax. The requirement that in this state B

Page 149: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.3. SYMMETRY AND HILBERT SPACE PRESENTABILITY: THE REPRESENTATION THEOREM149

is sharp says that BAx = Ax. In this terminology, Birkhoff’s conditional says:”If you first measure A and then measure B, you end up in a state in which Ais still sharp.”. Mathematically this means: ABAx = BAx.

Now JvN is not satisfied with this arguing that this ’operation’ is not rep-resentable by a projection (subspace). The following is a reconstruction of hisargument. Let A,B such that A∪B = 0, not B ⊂ A⊥ and not B ⊂ ASuch aconstellation exists in every Hilbert space of dimension at least 3.

His first observation is : ”There is no state in which the property ab iscertainly present” What does this mean? For A, B as above, ABAx = BAximplies BAx = 0 or equivalently Ax ∈ B⊥

In our terminology, the consequence relation has no internalising connectivedefinable by

Think about this.We will come back to this Chapter later in ”Birkhoff-von Neumann Revis-

ited”, where we we will establish the precise connection betweeen Birkhoff-vonNeumann and the approach put forward in this book

10.3 Symmetry and Hilbert Space Presentabil-ity: The Representation Theorem

Note that the proof of the Representation Theorem given below can be simplifiedusing our theorem characterising classical Hilbert lattices

In the previous sections we investigated some of the properties displayed byHilbert space logics. In this section we are looking for properties characterisingHilbert space logics. To pose the problem more precisely, let us introduce thefollowing terminology. Given a logic L = 〈C, F, ;〉, a Hilbert space H and afunction Ψ → Sub(H) such that L = LH,Ψ. Then we say that L is presented byH via Ψ. We say that L is presentable by H if there exists a function Ψ such thatL is presented by H via Ψ. It is our aim to characterise the logics presentable bysome Hilbert space H. In other words, we are looking for necessary and sufficientconditions for a logic L to be presentable by some Hilbert space H. We shall seethat, besides some natural logical conditions, there are two properties essentialfor the characterisation we have in mind. The first property is what in section? we called holicity. The second essential property, which we haven’t comeacross yet, is a symmetry property. We shall call it the symmetry property. Weshall see that, essentially, these two properties, namely holicity and symmetry,characterise Hilbert space logics. To be more precise, they characterise thoselogics which are presentable by infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces, i.e. thosestructures playing a dominant role in quantum mechanics. Mathematically, themain pillar of our reasoning is Soler’s celebrated result on the characterisationof (infinite-dimensional) Hilbert spaces.

10.3.1 More about Holistic Logics

Several of the following things are treated earlier in the book or need to be treated

Page 150: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

150 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

earlier.

Lemma 10.3 Let L be a logic. Then any two pointers are C-equivalent For apointer σ to |∼0 we have for any |∼∈ C that |∼σ=|∼0 if |6∼ ¬σ, otherwise |∼σ= 0.

Given two consequence relations |∼1 and |∼2 with pointers σ1 and σ2 respec-tively. We say that |∼1 is orthogonal to |∼2 iff |∼1 ¬σ2. This relation is symmetricand we say that the two consequence relations are orthogonal.

The above lemma belongs to section?

Lemma 10.4 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic, |∼0∈ C having pointerσ to itself. Then

• (i) For any |∼∈ C not orthogonal to |∼0 we have σ |∼ (α ; β) iff α |∼0 β

• (ii) [σ] = |∼0, 0• (iii) σ |∼C (α ; β) iff α |∼0 β for any |∼ not orthogonal to |∼0.

• (iv) For any non zero |∼1, |∼2∈ C, |∼1⊂|∼2 implies |∼1=|∼2

Proposition 10.3 Hilbert space logics are holistic logics.

This follows from the fact that Hilbert spaces are orthomodular spaces andthe logics presented by orthomodular spaces are are holistic. This must in thefinal version be section ”Presenting holistic logics”

The following proof is for Hilbert space logics.

Proof. Recall that, given a Hilbert Space H and A 6= H, 0 a closed subspace,then there exists an x ∈ H such that xA and not xA⊥. From this it followsthat Hilbert space logics are non trivial.

Let LH,Ψ be any Hilbert space logic. For any non zero elements x, x′ of Hwe need to show that σx `x′=`x or σx `x′= 0. But this is equivalent to thefollowing fact of elementary Hilbert space theory. Denote by Ix the projectionoperator corresponding to the ray 〈x〉. Then Ix(〈x′〉) = 〈x〉 if x and x′ are notorthogonal and Ix(〈x′〉) = 0 otherwise.

Lemma 10.5 Let L = 〈C, F, ;s〉 be a holistic logic. Then 〈Fml,≤,∗ 〉 and thus〈Prop,⊂,∗ 〉 are orthomodular, atomic and irreducible lattices.

Proof. We have orthomodularity by the fact that L is a logic with the Sasakihook as its internalising connective and Theorem 18. As to atomicity observethat the atoms of 〈Prop,⊂,∗ 〉 are of the form [σ|∼].

For irreducibility we need to prove that the center of that lattice consists oftruth and falsity only. For this it suffices to prove that for every proposition[α] not representing truth or falsity there exists an atom [σ|∼] such that [α] and[σ|∼] are not compatible. In the special case of a pointer σ|∼ and a formulaα compatibility says that [σ|∼] ⊂ [α] or [σ|∼] ⊂ [¬α]. Since L is non trivial,

Page 151: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.3. SYMMETRY AND HILBERT SPACE PRESENTABILITY: THE REPRESENTATION THEOREM151

for a given formula α there exists a |∼o ∈ C such that neither [σ|∼0 ] ⊂ [α] nor[σ|∼0

] ⊂ [¬α] and thus [α] and [σ|∼0] are not compatible.

The following theorem gives a connection between local and global conse-quence in holistic logics. Its proof is routine.

Theorem 10.5 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a holistic logic. Let |∼∈ C. Then thefollowing statements are equivalent.

• (i) |∼ α

• (ii) σ|∼ |∼C α

• (iii) |∼C (σ|∼ ; α)

Definition 10.3 Let L = 〈C, F, ;〉 be a logic.

• We say that L has the upward finiteness property, in brief the uf-property,iff the following holds: Given a set Σ of formulas. Then there exists aformula ψ such that σ |∼C ψ for every σ ∈ Σ and the following conditionis satisfied. For any formula ρ such that σ |∼C ρ for every σ ∈ Σ, we haveψ |∼C ρ.

• We say that L has the downward finiteness property, in brief the df-property iff the following holds:

Given a set Σ of formulas. Then there exists a formula χ such that χ |∼C σfor every σ ∈ Σ and the following condition is satisfied. For any formulaρ such that ρ |∼C σ for every σ ∈ Σ, we have ρ |∼C χ.

• In the case that L is holistic we say that L has the covering property iffthe following condition is satisfied. Given a formula α and |∼∈ C suchthat |6∼ α. Then for any formula ρ such that α |∼C ρ and ρ |∼C α ∨ σ|∼ wehave ρ ≡C α ∨ σ|∼ or ρ ≡C α

Intuitively we may think of the formulas ψ and χ in the above definition ofplaying the role of ‘infinite disjunction’ and ‘infinite conjunction’ of the formulasof Σ. The properties defined above are such that the following lemma holds.

Lemma 10.6 Let L = 〈C, F, ;s〉 be a holistic logic having the df, uf and thecovering properties. Then the lattices 〈Fml,≤,∗ 〉 and thus 〈Prop,⊂,∗ 〉 are or-thomodular, atomic, irreducible, complete lattices having the covering property.

10.3.2 Symmetry and Hilbert Space Logics

Let us start with the following observation. Let H be a Hilbert space and let(xi)i∈I be a complete orthonormal system of H. Then any permutation of thesystem (xi)i∈I , more precisely any permutation of the index set I, induces aunique unitary transformation on H and thus an automorphism of the latticeSub(H). This fact reflects a symmetry property of Hilbert spaces and in view

Page 152: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

152 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

of Soler’s theorem seems to be at the heart of the concept of a Hilbert space. Itis the above fact that serves us as a motivation for the concept of a symmetriclogic which we will study in the sequel.

Definition 10.4 Let L be a holistic logic having the properties in the last lemma.Let ∆ = (|∼i)i∈I be an infinite family of consequence relations of L with the fol-lowing properties

• (i) For i 6= j, |∼i and |∼j are orthogonal.

• (ii) For any consequence relation |∼ of L there exists an i0 ∈ I such that|∼ and |∼i0 are not orthogonal.

Then we call ∆ a basis for L.

Remark: Intuitively, we may think of a basis ∆ of a holistic logic L as follows.Given any consequence relation |∼ of L. Then there exists a member of ∆ inwhich |∼ is encoded via the internalising connective. The system ∆ may thusbe viewed as containing the whole information of L.

Definition 10.5 Let L be a logic as in the last definition and let ∆ = (|∼i)i∈Ibe a basis for L. We say that L satisfies the symmetry condition with respect to∆ iff the following holds. Let f : I → I be any permutation of the index set I.Then there exists an automorphism ϕf of the algebra of propositions of L (andthus of the algebra of operators) such that

• ϕf ([σi]) = [σf(i)], where (σi)i∈I ia any family such that σi is a pointer to|∼i.

• If the subset J ⊂ I of those elements of I that are left fixed by f is nonempty, then ϕf induces the identity on [0, A], where A is the smallestproposition containing [σj ] for all j ∈ J .

We say that L satisfies the symmetry condition (synonymously: is symmetric)iff there exists a basis ∆ for L such that L is symmetric with respect to ∆.

Recall the notation [0, A]. It is the set of all propositions smaller than or equal toA eqiuipped with a lattice structure in a natural way. In the following theoremwe assume the ’presenting’ function Ψ to be surjective.

Theorem 10.6 Let L = 〈C, F, ;s〉 be a logic. Then the following conditionsare equivalent.

• (i) L is symmetric.

• (ii) There exists an infinite-dimensional classical Hilbert Space H present-ing L.

Page 153: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.3. SYMMETRY AND HILBERT SPACE PRESENTABILITY: THE REPRESENTATION THEOREM153

Proof. For the direction from (ii) to (i) assume that there exists an infinite-dimensional classical Hilbert space H and a (surjective) function Ψ such thatL = LH,Ψ. We need to verify the symmetry property. Let (xi)i∈I be a completeorthonormal system of H. Then ∆ = (`xi

)i∈I is a basis for L. Now observe thatthe lattice of propositions of L and Sub(H) are isomorphic in a canonical way,namely via [α] 7→ Ψ(α). Thus, for the proof of symmetry it suffices to establishthe following. For any permutation f : I → I there exists an automorphism ρf

of Sub(H) with the following properties:

• ρ(〈xi〉) = 〈xf(i)〉• If the set J = i | f(i) = i is non-empty, then ρf induces the identi-

cal map on [0, X], where X denotes the smallest closed subspace of Hcontaining 〈xj〉 for all j ∈ J .

To verify the above, recall that any for any x ∈ H we have x =∑

i∈I〈x, xi〉xi.Define the map ϕf as follows. For x =

∑i∈I〈x, xi〉xi put ϕf (x) =

∑i∈I〈x, xf−1(i)〉xi.

ϕf is well defined. We have for any i ∈ I that ϕf (xi) = xf(i). Moreover, ϕf isunitary, since for any x, y ∈ H we have 〈ϕf (x), ϕf (y)〉 =

∑i∈I〈x, xf−1(i)〉〈y, xf−1(i)〉 =∑

i∈I〈x, xi〉〈y, xi〉 = 〈x, y〉. Now assume that the set J of those elements whichare left fixed by f is not empty. Denote by X the smallest closed subspace ofH containing xj for all j ∈ J . X is the smallest closed subspace containing〈xj〉 | j ∈ J and ϕf induces the identity on X. For the latter claim observethat ϕf induces the identity on the subspace spanned by xj | j ∈ J and X isthe (topological) closure of that subspace. By continuity ϕf induces the identityon X too. Now, ϕf induces an ortholattice automorphism ρf on Sub(H) suchthat for any i ∈ I, ρf (〈xi〉) = 〈xf(i)〉. It is also evident that ρf induces theidentical map on [0, X]. Thus the symmetry condition is verified.For the other direction note that the existence of a basis guarantees that thelattice of propositions denoted by PropL has infinite height and observe thatby Theorem 32 there exists an orthomodular space H and an isomorphismΦ : PropL → Sub(H). We now exploit the symmetry property of L to provethat H must be a classical (infinite-dimensional) Hilbert space. Let ∆ be a ba-sis for L with respect to which L is symmetric. Let (σi)i∈I be a correspondingfamily of pointers. We look at the family Φ([σi)])i∈I . Put 〈xi〉 = Φ([σi]). Thisis an infinite pairwise orthogonal family of one dimensional subspaces (rays) ofH. We will construct a family (yi)i∈I of pairwise orthogonal elements of Hsuch that for any i, j ∈ I we have 〈yi, yi〉 = 〈yj , yj〉. Then it follows by Soler’stheorem that H is a classical Hilbert space.

Let i0 ∈ I be fixed. Then for every j ∈ I, j 6= i0 consider the permutationfj of I defined as follows.

fj(i0) = j and fj(j) = i0, fj(i) = i else.

The symmetry condition then guarantees that for every j ∈ I, j 6= i0 thereexists an automorhism ϕj of Sub(H) such that

ϕj(〈xi0〉) = 〈xj〉

Page 154: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

154 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

and, moreover, induces the identity on [0, X], where X is the smallest closedsubspace of H containing 〈xi〉 for i 6= i0, j. Clearly X has dimension greaterthan 2. In fact, it is infinite-dimensional. Mayet’s theorem then yields that ϕj

is induced by some unitary operator ρj of H. For j 6= i0 put yj = ρj(xi0) andyi0 = xi0 . Since ρj is unitary and the 〈xi〉’s are pairwise orthogonal, the family(yj)j∈I is as required in Soler’s theorem and H must be an infinite-dimensionalclassical Hilbert space.

We still need to prove that H presents L. For this we first need to definethe function Ψ. Define Ψ : Fml → Sub(H) by Ψ(α) = Φ([α]). It is routinelyverified that Ψ satisfies the conditions required.We need to show

• 1. C = CH,Ψ

• 2. If |∼=`x, then for any α, |∼α= FH,Ψ(α,`x)

For 1. let |∼∈ C be given. We need to find a `x∈ CH,Ψ such that |∼=`x. Letσ be a pointer to |∼ and 〈x〉 = Φ([σ]) = Ψ(σ). We have α |∼ β iff σ |∼ α ;s βiff [σ] ⊂ [α ;s β] . This is equivalent to 〈x〉 ⊂ Ψ(α ;s β) which says α `x β.Thus |∼=`x. For a given `x the same reasoning applies to find a |∼∈ C suchthat `x=|∼.For 2. let |∼=`x. Note that β |∼α γ iff α |∼ (β ;s γ) iff α `x (β ;s γ) iffβ `Ax γ. But `Ax= FH,Ψ(α,`x).

Remark: The reader may have noticed that in he above proof we did notuse the second condition of the definition of a basis. In fact the argumentworks without that condition. If we omit the second condition we can no longersay that ∆ contains ‘the whole information’ of L. Instead, its intuitive functionwould be to guarantee that L is ‘rich in information’ in that it contains infinitelymany non orthogonal consequence relations, which thus are not encoded in eachother.1

10.3.3 Reflecting on the Representation Theorem

Let us now reflect on the intuitive meaning the technical result we called therepresentation theorem might have. In a sense this book describes a journey. We

1The authors cannot refrain from putting themselves in a mystic’s boots for a moment.What’s the intuitive content of the combination of holicity and symmetry which obviouslyis at the heart of the logics presentable by infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces? A mysticmight say that these properties represent the inherent ‘unity’ of a Hilbert space logic. Givena holistic logic L, let ∆ be a basis for L and let L be symmetric with respect to ∆. Thenwe know that every consequence relation |∼0 of L is encoded in some member |∼1 of ∆ viathe internalising connective and vice versa. So, |∼0 and |∼1 aren’t essentially different. Thisis holicity. But what about different elements |∼0, |∼1∈ ∆? Aren’t they essentially different?Well, the mystic might say, symmetry expresses a sort of indistinguishability of the basicconsequence relations, the sort of indistinguishability we encounter so often at the level ofquantum mechanics, for instance in connection with the symmetry of the wave function ofmany particle systems. This time, the symmetry is at the logical level. So, the mystic mightsay, there is some ’hidden unity’ behind the apparent diversity and variety of the consequencerelations of a Hilbert space logic.

Page 155: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.3. SYMMETRY AND HILBERT SPACE PRESENTABILITY: THE REPRESENTATION THEOREM155

said at the beginning that we would aim at finding logical structures in Hilbertspace. This is in full accordance with with what Birkhoff and von Neumannhad in mind. Our first deviation from Birkhoff and von Neumann was that inour treatment of propositions we focused on projections in Hilbert space ratherclosed subspaces. This led us to what we called the dynamic viewpoint. Weelaborated on this technicaly by introducing and studying structures we calledM-algebras, which are abstractions from the lattice of projections in Hilbertspace.

Our second deviation from Birkhoff and von Neumann is what we called thelocal viewpoint. In the Birkhoff-von Neumann paper as well as in our study ofM-algebras the concept of a state was a a primitive notion. We then set out toenquire into the logical nature of the concept of a physical state. Finally, wewere led to the concept of a holistic logic. These structures constitute a sort ofsynthesis of both viewpoints. The dynamic nature of propositions is transparentin these structures and states are represented as precisely defined logical entities.Moreover the framework of holistic logics turns out to be a precise framework inwhich certain natural vague intuitions arising in connection with he phenomenadescribed in Chapter 8 such as wholeness, interconnectedness etc. have a precisemeaning. In a sense, essential features of quantum reality are mirrored on thisplatform in a surprising way.

We found that the natural vehicles for presenting holistic logics are certainvector spaces called orthomodular spaces, in particular Hilbert spaces. We thenasked the question how to characterise those holistic logics that are presentableby a Hilbert space. We gave a positive answer to this question in the Representa-tion Theorem. It is remarkable that the crucial condition in this characterisationis a symmetry condition.

Hilbert spaces, i.e. the structures constituting the core of the formalism ofquantum mechanics, are special orthomodular spaces and thus present holisticlogics. We called the logics presentable by Hilbert spaces Hilbert space logics. Inthe above representation theorem we characterised Hilbert space logics amongholistic logics. The crucial condition in that characterisation was a symmetryproperty. This is remarkable. It means that not only does symmetry play anenormous role inside the formalism of quantum mechanics but that it is also atthe heart of the formalism itself.

Let us reflect at this point. What was the course of the experiment this bookis about so far? Where did the journey on which we embarked lead us so far?

Let us summarise: At the beginning of the journey there was an epistemo-logical issue, namely the issue of reality in quantum mechanics. We then tried togive this philosophical problem a scientific twist by translating it into a problemof logic. The problem was: Construct logical monads! Our intuition was thatthese logical monads should be constructed as keeping their commitment to thestructure of reality at a minimum. Our aim was to construct logical systemswhich constitute their own semantic structures.

This was the starting point of the journey. We arrived at the concept oflogical structures which we called holistic logics. Their salient properties areself-referential soundness and completeness and the properties expressed in the

Page 156: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

156 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

no windows theorems and the limiting case theorem. These properties reflecttheir monadic nature so to speak.

We then asked the question how these structures can be presented and insearching for an answer we hit upon the concept of an orthomodular space and,in particular, the concept of a Hilbert space. So our journey so far led us fromthe intuition of logical monadology to Hilbert space, which constitutes the coreof the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics.

10.4 Formal Reflections on the Connectives inHilbert Space Logics

This Section is still incomplete in this draft. But it is also not necessary forunderstanding the subsequent chapters

Quantum logic, however it may be defined, is certainly one of those branchesof logic in which the connectives are least understood. In this section we take acloser look at the problem of the connectives in quantum logic. This is anotherapplication of the ’local viewpoint’. Given a Hilbert space H and some x ∈ H wemay look at the consequence relation or, more generally, the inference operationcorresponding to x for a language without connectives, i.e just a set of atomicpropositions. We may then look at various languages containing connectives,and we can study conservative extensions of the inference operation to theselanguages. In this section, which is of a purely technical nature, we study suchextensions.

In this we combine two approaches, namely the approach to quantum logictaken by Engesser and Gabbay in [14] and the approach to introducing andstudying connectives in a general logical setting taken by Lehmann in [40] and[41]. The approach adopted in [?] permits us to start with a language withoutconnectives. In fact, several interesting properties of the inference operationsinduced by quantum states can be studied in the absence of connectives. This isin contrast to approaches in the spirit of the Birkhoff and von Neumann paper[2] which start with the connectives as presented by the lattice operations of thelattice of closed subspaces of a Hilbert space.

We start with a quantum inference operation as introduced and studiedin [40] in a poor language without connectives as described. We then studypossible conservative extensions to richer languages containing connectives. Wewill investigate several such extensions and discuss their properties from variouspoints of view.

10.4.1 Quantum Consequence Relations and Inference Op-erations

Given a non-empty set P which we regard as a set of atomic propositions. Thusthe language with which we start has no connectives. Given a Hilbert space H,an element x of H and a function Ψ : P → Sub(H), where Sub(H) denotes the

Page 157: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.4. FORMAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONNECTIVES IN HILBERT SPACE LOGICS157

set of all closed subspaces of H. As usual we write A for Ψ(α) as well as forthe projector corresponding to Ψ(α). We then have the consequence relation`x over P presented by Ψ:

α `x β iff Ax ∈ B

As observed by Lehmann, this definition can be extended to the definitionof an (infinitary) inference operation as follows. Let A be any set of (atomic)formulas. We may then define what it means to say that β is a consequence ofA. Namely, consider A =:

⋂Ψ(α) | α ∈ A. Note that that A is again a closedsubspace of H so that we may define β to be a consequence of A, i.e. β ∈ C(A),iff Ax ∈ B.Denote the set of x-consequences of A by Cx(A). Context permitting we omitthe subscript x. These inference operations called quantum inference operationshave certain nice properties. They for instance satisfy the following conditionsas is routinely checked.

For any A ⊂ P we have A ⊂ C(A) Inclusion

and

A ⊂ B ⊂ C(A) implies C(A) = C(B) Cumulativity

In [40] inference operations satisfying the above conditions are called C-logics. C-logics admit a particularly smooth characterisation in terms of a rep-resentation theorem (see [40]) and are worth studying in their own right. Keepin mind that quantum consequence operations are C-logics.

Let us now consider the closure L of P under the unary connective ¬ andthe binary connective ∧, i.e. the smallest language L containing P and closedunder ¬ and ∧ and let us consider extensions of Ψ to L. We shall now con-sider conservative extensions of quantum consequence relations and inferenceoperations to the richer language L.

Lehmann considers three conditions the connectives ∧ and ¬ should satisy.

∧-R C(A, α ∧ β) = C(A, α, β)

¬ R1 C(A,α,¬α) = L¬ R2 if C(A,¬α) = L, then α ∈ C(A).

Call a set A of formulas a theory if C(A) = A. Call A consistent if C(A) isnot the full language.

10.4.2 The Birkhoff-von Neumann Extension

We first consider the following extension of Ψ to L.

Ψ(α ∧ β) = Ψ(α) ∩Ψ(β)

Page 158: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

158 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

Ψ(¬α) = Ψ(α)⊥, where Ψ(α) alpha denotes the orthogonal complement ofΨ(α).

Note that Ψ goes into Sub(H) and and the extended consequence relation andinference operation is defined analogously to the case above by (1).

This extension is in the spirit of [2] in that we invoke orthogonal comple-ment formation in Hilbert space in order to present negation. We refer to itas the Birkhoff-von Neumann extension . Recall that have proved that theseconsequence relations have the Sasaki hook as an internalising connective.

10.4.3 The Lehmann Extension

In [40] Lehmann proved the following remarkable result.

Theorem 10.7 (Lehmann) Let C be a C-logic over P. Then there exists aC-logic C′ over L that satisfies ∧ − R, ¬R1, ¬R2, such that, for any A ⊂ P,C(A) = P ∩ C′(A)

Since the inference operations Cx are C-logics, it follows from the above theoremthat they admit a conservative extension as described in the theorem.

In [40] an explicit construction for such a conservative extension is given.We now describe the Lehmann extension for quantum consequence operations.Given y ∈ H, put Ty =: A ∈ Sub(H) | y ∈ A.

The following result characterises the consistent theories of a quantum con-sequence operation.

Theorem 10.8 Let A ⊂ Sub(H), x ∈ H. Then A is an x-consistent theory iffthere is a y not orthogonal to x such that A = Ty.

Proof. For the direction from left to right put A =:⋂A and Ax =: y. Then

〈y〉 ∈ C(A). Since C(A) = A, we have 〈y〉 ∈ A. Thus A ⊂ 〈y〉. Since Ais assumed to be consistent and 〈y〉 is one-dimensional, we have A = 〈y〉. Itfollows that A ⊂Ty.

Now assume assume B ∈ Ty. Then Ax ∈ B. This says that B ∈ C(A).Again, since (A) = A, we have B ∈ A. It follows that Ty ⊂ A. We have nowestablished that A = Ty.

It remains to be shown that y is not orthogonal to x. Suppose to the contrarythat y ∈ 〈x〉⊥, i.e. Ax ∈ 〈x〉⊥. This means that Ax = 0 and thus A isinconsistent contrary to the hypothesis.For the other direction it suffices to show that C(Ty) ⊂ Ty. Let B ∈ C(Ty). Itfollows that the operator corresponding to 〈y〉 applied to x is in B. We thenhave 〈y〉 ⊂ B and thus B ∈ Ty.

Given a quantum inference operation Cx over P presented by the functionΨ : P → Sub(H). Consider Hx := (〈x〉⊥)c. and define the function ΨL : P →2Hx presenting the Lehmann extension as follows. For α ∈ P define

Page 159: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.4. FORMAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONNECTIVES IN HILBERT SPACE LOGICS159

ΨL(α) = Ψ(α) ∩Hx,

For the connectives define

ΨL(¬α) = (ΨL(α))c,

where (ΨL(α))c is the complement of Ψ(α) in Hx.

ΨL(α ∧ β) = ΨL(α) ∩ΨL(β)

Let A be any subset of Hx. Then we denote by A∗ the smallest closed subspaceof H containing A and as always, if there is no danger of confusion, the corre-sponding projection operator. For A ∈ Sub(H) we put Ax = (A ∩ Hx)∗. Wecan now define the Lehmann extension CL omitting the subscript x.

Definition 10.6 Let Cx be a quantum inference operation over P presented bythe function Ψ. Let A be any set of formulas of L. Then define CL(A) asfollows. Let β be any formula of L. Then consider S =:

⋂ΨL(α) | α ∈ A.Now, if S∗x ∈ S, we say that β ∈ CL(A) if S∗x ∈ ΨL(β). If not S∗x ∈ S wedefine β ∈ CL(A) if S ⊂ ΨL(β).

This definition is the result of applying Lehmann’s general construction as givenin the proof of Theorem 1 in [40] to what he there calls quantum logics. te thatwhenever we have α `x ⊥, we must have the second case in the above definition,i.e. Ψ′(α) must be empty which in the atomic case means Ψ(α) ⊂ 〈x〉⊥ asrequired for conservativity.

Lemma 10.7 Let A ∈ Sub(H) and x ∈ H. Then Ax ∈ 〈x〉⊥ implies x = 0.

Proof. Assume Ax ∈ 〈x〉⊥. This means that 〈Ax, x〉 = 0. Recall that AA = A.It follows that 〈AAx, x〉 = 0. Since A is self-adjoint, we get 〈Ax, Ax〉 = 0 andthus Ax = 0.

Lemma 10.8 Let A ⊂ Sub(H) and suppose Ax 6= 0. Then Ax = Axx.

Proof. First observe that Ax ⊂ A. Moreover, note that, if Ax 6= 0, thenwe have by the last lemma that not Ax ∈ 〈x〉⊥ and thus Ax ∈ A ∩ Hx, i.e.Ax ∈ Ax. Since Ax and Axx are the unique elements of A and Ax respectivelywhich are closest to x, it follows that Ax = Axx.

Lemma 10.9 Let S ⊂ Sub(H) and let A =⋂B ∩ Hx | B ∈ S. Then

A∗ = (⋂B | B ∈ S)x.

Theorem 10.9 The Lehmann extension is a C-Logic and a conservative ex-tension of Cx such that

• (i) `x α ∧ β iff `x α and `x β.

• (ii) `x ¬α iff not `x α.

Page 160: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

160 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

Proof. Let us verify that the Lehmann extension is in fact a C-logic. So givensets of formulas A,B such that A ⊂ B ⊂ CL(A). We then need to prove thatCL(A) = CL(B). Let S =

⋂ΨL(α | α ∈ A and T =⋂ΨL(β) | β ∈ B. We

have to consider four cases.Case 1: S∗x ∈ S and T ∗x ∈ T .Case 2: S∗x ∈ S, but not T ∗x ∈ T .Case 3: not S∗x ∈ S, but T ∗x ∈ T .Case 4: not S∗x ∈ S and not T ∗x ∈ T .We prove case 1. Note that T ⊂ S. We have for every β ∈ B that S∗x ∈ ΨL(β).It follows that S∗x ∈ T and thus S∗x = T ∗x. Now let β ∈ CL(B). This meansT ∗x ∈ ΨL(β) and thus S∗x ∈ ΨL(β) which means that β ∈ CL(A).We prove case 2. First note that S∗x ∈ Ψ(β) for all β ∈ B anf thus S∗x ∈ T .Let β ∈ CL(B). Then we have T ⊂ ΨL(β). It follows that §∗x ∈ ΨL(β).We prove case 3. In this case B ⊂CL(A) implies S ⊂ T . Since T ⊂ S, we haveS = T . If β ∈CL(B), we have T ∗x = S∗x ∈ Ψ(β), hence β ∈ CL(A).We prove case 4. In this case we, again, have S = T . β ∈ CL((B) says T ⊂ΨL(β). Thus S ⊂ ΨL(β), which means β ∈ CL(A.

We now prove that the Lehmann extension is conservative. For this we needto show that for any set A of formulas of P and any β ∈ P we have β ∈ CL(A)iff β ∈ Cx(A). Assume that Cx is presented by Ψ. Assume β ∈ CL(A). LetS =

⋂ΨL(α) | α ∈ A. Let A =⋂Ψ(α) | α ∈ A. Assume the first case

in the definition 10.6, namely that S∗x ∈ S. It follows that S∗x 6= 0. Thusβ ∈ CL(A) iff S∗x ∈ ΨL(β). Since, by lemma 10.8 we have S∗ = Ax, wehave Axx ∈ ΨL(β). Noting that ΨL(β) ⊂ Ψ(β) we getthat Ax ∈ Ψ(β), whichsays that β ∈ Cx(A. Now assume the second case of definition 10.6, i.e. notS∗x ∈ S. This means that S∗x ∈ 〈x〉⊥. This is, by lemma 10.7 possible only ifSxx = 0 and thus, by lemma ?? Ax = 0. But this says β ∈ Cx(A).The other direction is established by similar reasoning. Suppose β ∈ Cx(A. Thissays that Ax ∈ Ψ(β). Assume Ax 6= 0. It follows by lemma 10.8 and lemma?? that Axx = Ax = S∗x ∈ S. Thus S∗x ∈ ΨL(β). This is the first case inDefinition 10.6 and we have β ∈ CL(A). Now suppose Ax = 0. It follows thatS is empty. So S ⊂ ΨL(β). We have the second case in Definition 10.6 andβ ∈ CL(A).

10.4.4 The Engesser-Gabbay Extension

The following extension is very much in the spirit of [14].

Definition 10.7 Given a set of atomic formulas (this is our object language, ithas no connectives). Let 2 be a binary connective, ¬ a unary connective. Theintended meaning of 2(α, β) is ”β is provable from α”, the intended meaning of¬ is classical negation at the metalevel. Define the language ML by the followingclauses.

• (i) If α, β ∈ P, then 2(α, β) ∈ ML.

Page 161: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.4. FORMAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONNECTIVES IN HILBERT SPACE LOGICS161

• (ii) If ϕ,ψ ∈ P ∪ML, then 2(ϕ,ψ) ∈ ML.

• (ii) If ϕ,ψ ∈ ML, then ¬ϕ,ϕ ∧ ψ ∈ Ml.

Now consider the language L∗ = P ∪ML. Note that the Boolean connectives ¬and ∧ act on metastatements only. Again, given Ψ : P :→ Sub(H) presentingthe quantum consequence relation `x. We extend Ψ to a function (again calledΨ) Ψ : L∗ → 2H . In fact it goes into Sub(H). In this we shall make useof orthogonal complement formation. But, as will be seen, this does not meanthat orthogonal complement formation in any way ’corresponds’ to a connective(negation). Rather it plays an auxiliary role role in the mathematical definitionof the proof operator.

We define the extension of Ψ as follows:

Ψ(2(ϕ,ψ) = (〈x〉)⊥ + (〈x〉 ∩ (Ψ(ϕ)⊥ + (Ψ(ϕ) ∩Ψ(ψ)))⊥

Ψ(¬ϕ) = Ψ(ϕ)⊥

We now define the extension of `x, again so denoted, as usual:For any ϕ, ψ ∈ L∗, ϕ `x ψ iff: Ψ(ϕ)x ∈ Ψ(ψ). And we claim that this extensionis a conservative extension of `x over L∗ which is self-referentially complete.

We now define the notion of truth for ML in a straightforward way. Wethen call a consequence relation |∼ self-referentially complete iff for all ϕ ∈ MLwe have |∼ ϕ iff ϕ is true.

Definition 10.8 Let |∼ be any consequence relation and ML the language justdefined. We say that

• (i) If α, β ∈ P, 2(α, β is true iff α |∼ β

• (ii) analogously for clause (ii) in the last definition.

• (iii( If ϕ = ¬ψ ∈ ML, then ϕ is true iff ψ is not true and ϕ ∧ ψ is trueiff ϕ is true and ψ is true.

10.4.5 Discussing Negation

Let us now compare the three types of negation introduced in the last sec-tion. The Birkhoff-von Neumann extension is undubtedly the richest extension.However, the negation presented by orthogonal complement formation admitsno plausible intuitive interpretation. Moreover, these consequence relations haveanother undesirable property. Namely, they areare ’classically inconsistent’ inthat for any such quantum inference operation C there exists a classical contra-diction α such that α ∈ C(>). On other hand, clearly the Birkhoff-von Neumannextensions do have some goodies. They admit a internalising connective, namelythe Sasaki hook ;s, which is definable by ¬ and ∧. They are self-referentiallycomplete and, again, the proof operator is definable by ¬ and ∧. The Lehmannextension is classically consistent. Yet it does not admit a definable internalising

Page 162: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

162 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

connective and it does not admit a definable proof operator. It thus is no quan-tum logic, i.e. it cannot be presented by a Hilbert space in in the sense of [3].The Engesser-Gabbay extension is classically consistent and is sef-relferentiallycomplete. The connectives ¬ and ∧ behave absolutely clasically. All connectivesadmit a natural interpretation.

Proposition 10.4 The Birkhoff-von Neumann extension is classically incon-sistent. But it admits an internalising connective and a proof operator bothdefinable by ¬ and ∧. Negation does not satisfy ¬-R2.

Proposition 10.5 The Lehmann extension is classically consistent. Negationsatisfies ¬-R2. It admits no internalising connective and no proof operator de-finable by ¬ and ∧.

The following corollary answers a question raised by Lehmann in [?], namelythe question whether any C-logic is presentable by a Hilbert space, i.e. that itis a quantum logic. The answer is negative.

Corollary 10.1 The Lehmann extension is no quantum logic.

Proof. We can assign a truth value V (α) to every α ∈ L in a natural wayas follows. For atomic α ∈ P define V (α) = 1 iff `x α and V and extend Vcanonically to L. Then we see, using Lemma 1, that we have V (α) = 1 iff`x α. This means that any α such that `x α is classically consistent. Thatthe Lehmann extension satisfies ¬−R2 follows from theorem 1. It is, however,interesting to verify this in the special case of quantum inference operations. Solet α ∧ ¬β `x ⊥.

Let us now see why the Lehmann extension does not admit an internalisingconnective definable by ∧ and ¬. Intuitively, the reason for this is that becauseof lemma 1 the internalising connective, if existing, would have to behave ’truth-functionally’, whereas the consequence relation over P does not behave so. i.e.whether for α, β ∈ P we have α `x β does not depend on the provability orunprovability of α and β alone. So assume there is an internalising connectiveC(α, β) definable by ∧ and ¬. Then, for any α, β ∈ P we would have thatα `x β iff `x C(α, β). This means, in particular, that whether α `x β holdsdefends only on the ’truth values’ V (α) and V (β). Now, let α, β, γ such thatnot `x α, not `x γ and α `x β and not γ `x β. This constellation is perfectlypossible. Now, since C(α, β) is an internalising connective, α `x β would imply`x C(α, β) from which in turn it would follow that γ `x β, since V (α) = V (γ).But this is a contradiction.

Proposition 10.6 The Engesser-Gabbay extension is classically consistent. Nega-tion satisfies ¬-R2.

Page 163: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

10.4. FORMAL REFLECTIONS ON THE CONNECTIVES IN HILBERT SPACE LOGICS163

10.4.6 Comment on ¬ −R2

We look at ¬−R2 from the point of view of Hilbert space logics. What does ¬R2mean in terms of CRS of classical logic? Given the classical consequence relation`. Then α ∧ ¬β ` ⊥ says that if we revise `, then the revised consequencerelation `α∧¬β proves β. Since in the case of classical logic revision by α ∧ ¬βamounts to first revising by α and subsequently by ¬β or the other way round,we may interpret ¬−R2 as follows. It says in particular: if revision by α yieldsa consequence relation with which β is inconsistent, then β is a consequence of αin the original consequence relation. ` ¬α says α ` ⊥. In the Engesser-Gabbayextension this can be retrieved, namely we have ` ¬α iff ` 2(α,⊥). So thereis no loss of information in the Engesser-Gabbay extension as compared to theBirkhoff-von Neumann extension.

Page 164: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

164 CHAPTER 10. TOWARDS HILBERT SPACE

Page 165: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Chapter 11

Some SpeculativeReflections

11.1 A Look at the Measurement Problem

In this chapter we use the concept of a tensor product and the fact that thecombination of two physical systems is the tensor product of their respectiveHilbert spaces. In this draft we have not yet introduced the concept of a tensorproduct of Hilbert spaces. The reasons for this are those mentioned in Chapter4. In the final version this will of course be done.

11.1.1 General Remarks

In their article on quantum logic in the Handbook of Philosophical Logic, DallaChiara and Giuntini arrive at the conclusion that traditional quantum logichasn’t made a significant contribution to the solution of the various (founda-tional) puzzles with which quantum mechanics confronts us. In particular, thereis no satisfactory account yet for the puzzle which has become known as themeasurement problem. It is not just quantum logic that has no solution tooffer but there is no approach whatsoever that can account for this puzzle in auniversally accepted way. In this chapter we investigate what resources we havein our framework to attack this problem.

Before describing the problem in detail in the dramatic form of Schroedinger’scat let us explain its general nature and why it is crucial for the understandingof quantum mechanics and in particular its mathematical formalism. In quan-tum mechanics the concept of measurement plays a vital role - in contrast toclassical mechanics. Recall that it is one of the basic principles of QM that,given an observable A represented mathematically as the Hermitian operator(again called) A, then the eigenvalues of A are those quantities that we canfind as values of observable A when a measurement of A is performed. The un-certainty relations are statement concerning ’non-simultaneous measurability’

165

Page 166: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

166 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

of certain observables. Generally, QM makes statements about the outcome ofmeasurements.

Now, the process of measurement is a physical process itself and we mayexpect the formalism of QM to give us an adequate description of the process ofmeasurement itself. This, however, is not the case. Essentially, the mesurementproblem or the measurement paradox as it is, perhaps more adequately, calledsometimes consists in the fact that on the hand the formalism of quantummechanics is about measurements but on the other hand seems to give incorrectresults when applied to the process of measurement itself.

Generally, what are the characteristics of measurement in physics? Measure-ment is a physical process involving the interaction of two systems, the systemto be measured and the measuring system, also called the measuring instrument.The systems interact in such a way that one of the interacting systems, namelythe measururement instrument, ’gives’ us the value of a certain observable per-taining to the system to be measured. This applies equally to quantum physicsand classical physics. It is, however, clear that not every interaction betweentwo systems constitutes a measurement. There are of course physical interac-tions between systems in which neither of them ’measures’ the other. Rather,in practice, the measuring instrument is a macroscopic object with a scale or ascreen from which the result of measurement can be read off by the human eye.Bohr famously insisted that the entire experimental arrangement even in thecase of quantum measurement must be describable in terms of classical physics.Landau and Lifschitz, in their classic textbook, say that quantum mechanics’presupposes’ classical mechanics.

In principle, the formalism of QM permits us to treat any interaction of twosystems. Both are, in the formalism, represented by their corresponding Hilbertspaces the tensor product of which represents the composite system. But howis the particular nature of the measurement process reflected in the formalism?In particular, how are the different roles of the system to be measured andthe measuring instrument reflected in the formalism? What, if anything, isspecial about the Hilbert spaces of measuring instruments? As far as we see,these questions have no answer within the formalism of QM. All one can do inthis framework is to represent both systems as (in general infinite dimensional)Hilbert spaces and apply the mathematical machimery of Hilbert space tensorproducts. In this sense that we may say that not only can the formalism ofquantum mechanics not treat the process of measurement correctly but that itcannot even define it.

The issue of measurement in quantum mechanics is closely linked to anotherissue, namely that of the ’collapse of the wave function’ or (synonymously) theprojection postulate. Recall that the projection postulate says the following.Assume a measurement of an observable A represented by an Hermitian operator(denoted again by) A is performed. Then after measurement the system is in aneigenstate of A and the corresponding eigenvalue is the value of A measured. Itis important to note this link between measurement, which is a physical process,and the phenomenon of ’collapse’. It is not just that we experience the ’strangephenomenon’ of collapse (projection) in quantum mechanics but we have to

Page 167: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 167

bear in mind that it is in the process of measurement that it occurs. We maytherefore expect a theory of measurement to explain this phenomenon ratherthan to presuppose it.

Our framework of holistic logics provides us with a refined look at this.Methodologically, we may view this chapter as ’playing the game of measure-ment’ in a logical framework, namely the framework of holistic logics in analogyto the way we ’played the game of reality’ in previous chapters.

11.1.2 The measurement problem in a nutshell

We view the measurement problem in the dramatic version of Schroedinger’scat. Given a quantum system, say an electron. We want to measure the z-component of the spin of the electron. It is known that this observable canassume only two values: ”up” and ”down”. We assume that the experimentalarrangement of the measuring process is as follows. In the case ”spin = down”some device is triggered which kills a cat. If we have ”spin = up” the cat staysalive. The cat is thus the measuring instrument.

Assume that before measurement the electron is (as a fermion) in the singlettstate

(1) 1/√

(2)(| up > − | down >)

Call the system consisting both of the cat, the measuring instrument, and theelectron, the system to be measured, the composite system. Then the formalismof quantum mechanics tells us that, after measurement, the composite systemis in the following state:

(2) 1/√

(2)(| alive >| up > − | dead >| down >)

So, after measurement the composite system is in a superposition. This is atodds with the facts. The facts are that after measurement the cat is either aliveand spin up or the cat is dead and spin down, both with probability 1/2. Theformalism, however, says that the z-component of spin is not sharp nor is thecat’s life. This is what in the literature is often referred to as: ”The cat is halfalive and half dead”. Such a state has never been observed. Rather the systemis either in state

| alive >| up >

or in state

| dead >| down >

Both states have probability 1/2.Therefore, the formalism of quantum mechanics does not provide the cor-

rect prediction when applied to the measurement process itself. This is themeasurement problem in a nutshell. There seems to be no generally acknowl-edged solution to this problem yet.

Page 168: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

168 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

11.1.3 Some more thoughts on measurement

We said that measurement involves two interacting systems and it is thus naturalto represent the combination of these two systems as the combination of twoholistic logics. In fact, we will confine ourselves to the case of those holistic logicsthat ’come’ from a Hilbert space, i.e. Hilbert space logics. In this, however, wehave to consider a feature of the process we haven’t considered yet, namelythat of correlation. Assume we want to measure an observable A pertainingto a certain system and assume A can adopt a family of values (λi)i∈I . Forthis purpose we let it interact with a measuring instrument in such a way thatafter measurement the value λi assumed by observable A can be read off from ascale or a screen. We may thus view λi as the value of an observable pertainingto the measuring instrument. This observable is normally called the pointerobservable. So, measuring A means correlating it with the pointer observableof the measuring instrument. And the values of the pointer observable can beread off from a scale or a screen. We have to reflect this notion of correlation ofobservables in our treatment of the measurement problem.

We said that in classical physics measurement doesn’t pose a problem. In-tuitively, in classical physics measurement is just ’looking’ at the system tobe measured and the state of that system is not changed in measurement. Inour treatment of measurement this trivial feature of measurement in classicalphysics will have to be reflected as a limiting case similar to the way the logic ofclassical mechanics appears as a limiting case in the framework of holistic logicsas made precise by the Limiting Case Theorem.

To summarise, in our ’playing the game of measurement’ in logic we willhave to reflect the following characteristics of the process of measurement:

• 1) Combining two systems

• 2) Correlating two systems

• 3)The ’classical’ nature of the measuring system (instrument)

• 4)The temporal evolution in the process of measurement

• 5)The projection postulate (”collapse of the wave function”)

• 5) Classical measurement as a limiting case

11.1.4 Combining and correlating Hilbert space logics

Given two Hilbert space logics L∞, L2 with languages Fml1 and Fml2 re-spectively. We introduce the connective ⊗ to form formulas of the ’combined’language. If α ∈ Fml1 and β ∈ Fml2, then α⊗ β is a formula of the combinedlanguage. We will use the symbol ⊗ both as denoting this connective and thealgebraic operation ’tensor’ for vectors and also for the operation of combiningconsequence relations. A word of caution is in order here. The reader is advisednot to think of α⊗ β as saying something like ’α and β’. Rather, he may think

Page 169: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 169

α ⊗ β as making sense only in connection with the combined system. He may,intuitively, think of the combined language as talking about the ’whole’, i.e. thecombined system, and view the connective ⊗ as the ’connective of wholeness’.

Definition 11.1 Given a Hilbert space logic L, x1, x2.. a sequence of mutuallyorthogonal vectors which may contain the zero vector. Assume y ∈ H is notorthogonal to all non-zero members of this sequence. Then we say that `y is asuperposition of `x1 ,`x2 , ....

We will in the sequel, for the sake of brevity, use the term ’state’ familiarfrom quantum mechanics also for denoting consequence relations of a Hilbertspace logic.

Intuitively, we may look at the concept of a superposition in various ways.First, superpositions may be viewed as ’encoding’ all its (consistent) compo-nents or ’containing’ all the information of its (non-zero) components, since itis non-orthogonal to each of its (non-zero) components. Second, observe a su-perposition can be revised so as to yield any of its non-zero components or, putdifferently, superpositions can in principle ’collapse’ into each of its non-zerocomponents because a superposition is non-orthogonal to any of its non-zerocomponents.

Definition 11.2 Let L1 = LH1,Ψ1 , and L2 = LH2,Ψ2 be Hilbert space logics.We define the combination L = L1 ⊗ L2 =: LH1⊗H2,Ψ of L1 and L2 as follows.Ψ(α ⊗ β) = Ψ1(α) ⊗ Ψ(β). Given two consequence relations `x and `y of L1

and L2 respectively. Then define `x ⊗ `y:=`x⊗y. If one the component logicsis one-dimensional, we say the combined logic is a cell.

The following lemma expresses an elementary property of the Hilbert spacetensor product.

Lemma 11.1 Suppose `x⊗y α ⊗ β. Then `x α and `y β. Moreover, we have`x ⊗ `0=`0, i.e. combining any consequence relation with the inconsistentconsequence relation yields the inconsistent consequence relation.

Definition 11.3 Given a Hilbert space logic L and a family of formulas A =(αi)i∈I . Assume all Ψ(αi)’s are either mutually orthogonal pointers, i.e. theΨ(αi)’s are mutually orthogonal rays, or the zero space. We assume at leastone Ψ(αi) to be non-zero. Then we say A is an observable. We think, in abuseof notation, of αi as having the form A = λi, the λi’s being the ’values’ of theobservable A.

Obviously, the above definition is motivated by the physical concept of anobservable represented by an Hermitian operator with non-degenerate eigenval-ues. The above definition does not capture the analogue of the fact that theeigenvectors of such an operator form a complete orthonormal system. This isnot necessary for our purposes. But it could be incorporated in a straightfor-ward way. Eigenvectors are by definition non-zero. Note, however, that in the

Page 170: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

170 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

above definition we allow for the inconsistent consequence relation, i.e. the zerovector, for reasons which will become obvious later.

We now define correlation of observables.

Definition 11.4 Let L1, L2 be Hilbert space logics. Let A = (αi)i∈I and B =(βi)i∈I be observables of L1 and L2 respectively. Given a non-zero consequencerelation `x⊗y of L1 ⊗ L2. We say that `x⊗y is a pure correlation with respectto A and B if `x⊗y A = λi ⊗ B = λi for some i ∈ I. We say that `y is acorrelation with respect to A and B if it is either a pure correlation with respectto A and B or a superposition of pure correlations with respect to A and B. Wecall a correlation of the latter kind an entanglement.

Note that distinct pure correlations are orthogonal, i.e. the above definitionof correlation makes sense.

11.1.5 Passing to the limit

We said that in our treatment of the measurement problem we need to reflect the’classical’ nature of the measuring instrument. As shown in Chapter 6 (LimitingCaseec Theorem), classical logic appears as a limiting case in the framework ofholistic logics. Let us therefore, at this point, recall this process of ’passing tothe limit’.

Passing to the limit logically

By the Limiting Case Theorem the limiting case of a holistic logic may be viewedas a complete classical theory or a family of complete classical theory. The’direction’ of passing to the limit was from non-monotonicity to monotonicity.To recall, The Limiting Case Theorem says that a holistic logic is monotonic ifand only if it is of the form L(Σ for some complete classical theory Σ.

Passing to the limit algebraically

Another direction of passing to the limit is from non-commutation of operatorsto their commutation. Again, we have that a holistic logic is commutative inthe sense that all its revision operators commute must be of the the form LΣ

where Σ is a complete classical theory. So, algebraically, the direction of passingto the limit is from non-commutativity to commutativity.

Formulate this as a Proposition and give the simple proof. But it’s preferableto state and prove it earlier in the book so that we can refer to it here..

Passing from Hilbert space to phase space

These ways of passing to a limit structure at the logical and algebraic level have aparallel at the level of physics. In classical mechanics, phase space plays the roleof state space and is thus the analogue of Hilbert space in quantum mechanics.What is phase space? Let us for the sake of simplicity consider a single particle.

Page 171: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 171

Then phase space is the set of pairs 〈x(t), p(t)〉, where x(t) denotes positionof the particle at time t and p(t) its momentum at time t. A point in phasespace contains all information about the state of the particle, since it allows usto compute any relevant classical physical quantity of the particle, for instancekinetic energy, angular momentum... Thus a point in phase space encodes allclassical physical properties of the system. Logically speaking, it represents the(complete classical) theory Σ of the system or, put differently in our terminologyof holistic logics, it represents the (holistic) logic LΣ. Thus on looking at phasespace this way the transition from Hilbert space to phase space is smooth andnatural. Logically, phase space, i.e. the state space in classical mechanics, maybe viewed as the limiting case of a Hilbert space, which represents state spacein quantum mechanics. We would like to remind the reader at this point of theway how the relation between phase space and Hilbert space is described in theBirkhoff-von Neumann paper (see Chapter 5.) In that paper this relationship isviewed in a completely different way , namely as a sort of analogy. In quantummechanics, Birkhoff and von Neumann say, the state of a physical system isfully encoded in its wave function in analogy to the way that the state of aclassical system of particles is known if position and momentum of each particleis known. The state space of the quantum system should thus, according toBirkhoff-von Neumann, be reprented by a function space, namely the Hilbertspace of the wave functions of the system.

11.1.6 Complete classical theories and one-dimensional Hilbertspace logics

We now make the simple connection between holistic logics of the form LΣ,i.e. complete classical theories, with Hilbert space logics. We can represent acomplete classical theory as a one-dimensional Hilbert space logic in a naturalway.

So given a logic LΣ for some complete classical theory Σ. We have Lσ =〈C, FΣ,→〉, where CΣ = `Σ, 0, `Σ is defined by: α `Σ β if α → β ∈ Σ. Now,LΣ can be presented as a one-dimensional Hilbert space logic as follows. Givena one dimensinal Hilbert space. Then the lattice of closed subspaces consists oftwo elements only, Sub(H) = < x >, 0. Define the function Ψ : FmlSub(H)by: Ψ(α) =< x > if α ∈ Σ, Ψ(α) = 0 else. Then LΣ = LH,Ψ. We will, fromnow on, view LΣ as the one-dimensional Hilbert space logic defined above. i.e.we omit the subscript Ψ.

As already mentioned, we call a tensor product of a one- dimensional Hilbertspace logic with an arbitrary Hilbert space logic a cell

We may think of Σ as the ’theory’ of a classical physical system, i.e. theset of statements or formulas true of this system. Such a formula may have theform A = λ with the intuitive meaning that a the observable A pertaining to aclassical system has the value λ. In this case we have A = λ ∈ Σ or, equivalently,this says that A = λ is a true statement about this system. Note that for anyµ 6= λ A = µ is not in Σ or, equivalently, is a false statement about the system.

Let us reformulate this as

Page 172: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

172 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

Lemma 11.2 Given LΣ,Ψ. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

• (i) α is ’true’

• (ii) α ∈ Σ

• (iii) `x α

It makes thus sense to say that a formula is is ’true’ or ’false’ in a one-dimensionalHilbert space logic according to our intuition that it represents a classical systemand any statement about that system is either true or false.

It is easy to see that the following holds. It reflects our intuition that anobservable of a classical system has exactly one value.

Lemma 11.3 Let L be a one-dimensional Hilbert space logic and (A = λi)i∈I

an observable of L. Then there exists a (unique) j ∈ I such that A = λj is truein L and A = λi is false in L for i 6= j.

The limiting case results allow us to look at the logics of the form LΣ aslimiting cases in a twofold way. We may say that, given a holistic logic, thenthe limit of this logic is of the form LΣ, but we may also regard the limits ofany of its consequence relations as being of this form. For Hilbert space logicsthis means that we may either say that the limit of a Hilbert space logic iseither a single one-dimensional Hilbert space logic or a family of one-dimnsionalHilbert space logics. From the physical point of view the latter version seemspreferable since it reflects the fact that phase space is the classical analogue ofHilbert space and phase space may, as explained above, be viewed as a familyof complete classical theories.

Let us come back to the crucial question of the ’classical’ nature of themeasuring instrument. How are we to reflect this in our logical framework? Wedo not have much freedom in this. But there exists a natural way of doing it. Inthe light of the above there are two possibilities. Either we treat te measurementinstrument as a single one-dimensional Hilbert space logic or a family of one-dimensional Hilbert space logics. We opt for the latter version for reasons whichwill become obvious later. We call such a family, reminiscent of ’phase space’in classical mechanics, a phase logic. Thus phase logics are families of the form(Li)i∈I each member being a one-dimensional Hilbert space logic.

We now have to define the concept of an observable for phase logics. Asbefore it has to be a family of formulas of a certain kind.

Definition 11.5 Let L = LΨi)i∈Ia phase logic. Let (A = λi)i∈I be a family of

formulas. We say that A is an observable for the phase logic if it is an observableof all its members.

.We have now defined the notion of an observable both for Hilbert space

logics and the limiting case of phase logics.

Page 173: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 173

What does this say intuitively? Think of the phase logic as the phase spaceof a certain particle and of A as the observable of position of this particle. Thenthe family (A = λt)t∈T is the trajectory of the particle, λt being the position attime t.

We now have to say how to combine Hilbert space logics with phase logicsand how to correlate observables if one of the systems is a phase logic.

Definition 11.6 Let LH,Ψ be a Hilbert space logic and L = Li)i∈I a phaselogic. We define the combined system to be the family (L⊗Li)i∈I . Call a familyof this sort, i.e. a family of cells, a register. Given two observables A = (λ)i∈I

and B = (λi)i∈I pertaining to these systems respectively. We say that a familyof states (`i)i∈I , `i being in cell i, is a correlation of A and B if each memberis a correlation of A and B viewed as observables in each cell.

We now define measurement.

Definition 11.7 Given a phase logic L1 = (Li)i∈I and L2 any Hilbert spacelogic. Let A and B be observables pertaining to L1 and L2 respectively. Aprocess of interaction between L1 and L2 is called a measurement of B by L2

with pointer observable A if the state of the combined system ’after interaction’is a correlation of A and B. The phase logic L1 is called the measurementinstrument, B its pointer observable.

The following lemma expresses an observation which is crucial to our ap-proach to the measurement problem.. Recall that the problem with Schroedinger’scat was that that after ’measurement’ the system consisting of the cat and theelectron was in an entanglement which seems to be at odds with the facts. Thenext lemma says that cells do not contain entanglements.

Lemma 11.4 Given a cell (of a certain register), i.e. Zi = Li ⊗ L with L〉being one-dimensional and two observables A and B pertaining to Li and Lrespectively. Then every correlation of A and B in Zi is pure. In fact, thereexists exactly one correlation and this correlation is pure. For the process ofmeasurement this means that it ends up in a pure correlation, i.e. not in anentanglement.

Proof. Entanglements are by definition genuine superpositions of pure correla-tions. What do pure correlations in a cell look like? Generally, a pure correlationis of the form A = λi⊗B = λi for some i ∈ I (viewed as a consequence relation.But now recall that in a one-dimensional Hilbert space logic A = λi is true forexactly one i ∈ I. That is A = λi ⊗ B = λi is non-zero for exactly one i ∈ Iand zero for the others. This means that a cell contains exactly one correlation,which then must be pure.

Page 174: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

174 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

11.1.7 Temporal evolution in measurement as correlatinga Hilbert space logic with a phase logic

We have to say something concerning the logical analogue of the quantum me-chanical ’law of temporal evolution’ of a system. In quantum mechanics thetemporal evolution of a system is described by a unitary transformation of itsHilbert space. Unitary transformations preserve, in particular, superpositions.This leads us, in our logical treatment, to the postulate that, a Hilbert spacelogic evolves over time in a way that preserves superpositions.

Our second postulate is to capture an essential feature of the process ofmeasurement, namely the fact that after measurement the observable to bemeasured and the pointer observable are correlated. We already used the terms’the state before measurement’ and ’state after measurement’. Generally, we as-sume that at any time a system is in a certain ’actual state’. So the above termsmean ’actual state before measurement’ and ’actual state after measurement’.

By definition the state after measurement is a correlation. Note that wedefined correlation for observables A and B pertaining to arbitrary Hilbert spacelogics L1 and L2. In the special case of measurement one of these logics is one-dimensional, and in this case Lemma...? tells us that the correlation in whichthe system ends up after measurement is pure, i.e. no entanglement.

So, the (actual) state after measurement is a correlation. But, clearly, wehave to say something about how the state after measurement is related to thestate before measurement. It is plausible that the state after measurement is notany correlation but must depend on the state of the system before measurementin a certain way. Therefore we postulate the following which conforms withquantum mechanics.

Let `y be the state of ∈ before measurement. Then the state after measure-ment is of the form `x ⊗ `y, where `x is a non-zero state of L2.

......The following is probably not necessary Given any state before measure-ment of the form x⊗ | B = λ〉 (Hilbert space notation). Then this state evolvesinto the correlation | A = λ〉⊗ | B = λ〉. If the state before measurement isa superposition states as above then the state after measurement is a super-position of the corresponding correlated states after measurement. So, state∑

i x⊗ | B = λi〉 evolves into the state∑

i | A = λi〉⊗ | B = λi〉. These pos-tulates probably admit a more elegant formulation our logical framework thanthe one we gave above in this draft. We will work on this......

11.1.8 Disentanglement and projection in measurement

We now have to take a closer look at correlations, if we combine a phase logicwith an arbitrary Hilbert space logic. This is what in our view happens in mea-surement. The following is a simple but crucial observation which we formulateas a theorem. It is an immediate consequence of the above lemma.

Theorem 11.1 Let L be an arbitrary Hilbert space logic and (Li⊗L)i∈I a phaselogic. Recall that the combined system is a register, namely the family of cells

Page 175: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 175

L⊗Li∈I . Let A = (λi)i∈I and B = (λi)i∈I be observables pertaining to the twosystems respectively, i.e. B is the pointer observable. Then for every cell allcorrelations between A and B are pure, namely of the form A = λi ⊗ B = λi.In particular, no cell contains entanglements.

The above says that the combination of any Hilbert space logic with a one-dimensional one does not admit entanglements. So, intuitively, we may viewthe process of combining a (genuine) Hilbert space logic with a phase logic asa sort of ’disentanglement’. It seems that, at the physical level, this is exactlywhat happens in the process of measurement. We will see that this may also beviewed as projection or ’collapse of the wave function’.

Let us take a closer look at this.Given two correlated observables A and B in a register (LHi,Ψi ⊗LH,Ψ)i∈I .

Then, after measurement, cell i is in a state x ⊗ y, x ∈ Hi, y ∈ H such that`x⊗y A = λi ⊗ B = λi. Note that this holds no matter in which state LH wasbefore measurement. By the postulates above after measurement the state ofthe (composite) system is a correlation and, in cells, the correlations are of theabove form, namely pure.

What has happened? Assume that before measurement the state of thesystem to be measured was in a superposition y =

∑i ciB =| λi〉 (in abuse of

notation.) In the general case of correlating two arbitrary Hilbert space logicsour postulates for correlating observables imply in accordance with those ofquantum mechanics that the state after correlation (measurement) is

∑i ci |

A = λi〉⊗ | B = λi〉, i.e. a superposition of pure correlations. This is anentanglement. Now, as we saw above, in the special the case of a cell, i.e. whenone of the Hilbert space logics is one-dimensional, a process of disentanglementtakes place. Namely, the components of the entanglement A = λi ⊗B = λi areno longer ’entangled’ but are ’stored’ so to speak in the cells of the register. So,the entanglement was ’disentangled’ and its components were ’ stored’ in theregister. In this sense what we called a register is in fact a storage device. Itseems worth investigating what this view could mean for quantum computation.

In the following considerations we use, for the sake of convenience, the usualHilbert space notation of quantum mechanics. It is clear It is clear how this isto be translated into the language of Hilbert space logics.

So, again, assume the system to be measured before measurement to be inthe superposition

y =∑

i ci | B = λi〉Say, before measurement, the pointer of the measuring instrument points tosome value λ, i.e. A=λ. Since the measuring instrument is ’classical’, thepointer variable has some value λj for some j ∈ I,i.e. A = λj is true. So thecomposite system is in state

∑i ci | A = λj〉⊗ | B = λi〉

After measurement it is in the correlated state

Page 176: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

176 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

z =∑

i ci | A = λi〉⊗ | B = λi

This is still in Hilbert space language. Let us now look at this in a preciseway from the point of view of Hilbert space logics. So view the above as theconsequence relation `z. The above equation says that `z is a superpositionof certain consequence relations in the sense of Definition ?, namely the conse-quence relations `xi⊗yi

such that vdashxi⊗yiA = λi ⊗B = λi. We can now say

what is special about this superposition (entanglement) in the case of measure-ment, i.e. in the case when one of the Hilberet space logics is one-dimensional.In this case all but one of the members of the family (`xi⊗yi

)i∈I is non-zero.Namely by Lemma ? all but one of the `xi ’s are non-zero. This is the expressionof the fact that classically an observable has exactly one value in a given state.Put differently, in classical mechanics the proposition A = λ is, in a given state,true and for µ 6= λ the proposition A = µ is false. Therefore `z is not a properentanglement, rather it concides with one of the components. We have

`z=`xj⊗yiwhere j is the index for which A = λj is true.

Switching back to Hilbert space notation we can say that as a result ofcorrelation with a one-dimensional Hilbert space logic the superposition z abovewas ’projected’ onto the component | A = λj〉⊗ | B = λj〉. So our way of lookingat measurement provides an explanation of the projection postulate (collapse ofthe wave function).

Let us summarise. Recall we regard measurement as correlating two obderv-ables A and B one of which say A pertaining to a phase logic (L)〉)〉∈I and Bpertaining to an arbitrary Hilbert space logic L]. The combination of the twologics is a register, namely the family (Li ⊗ L)i. The members of this familyare called cells. We proved that cells do not admit entanglements. In fact, aftermeasurement cell i is in state `xi⊗yi with `xi A = λi and `yi B = λi.

So, on this view, the result of measurement is ’the contents’ of the register,i.e. a family of the form (A = λi ⊗ B = λi)i∈I rather than a single member ofsuch as a family. Though appealing from a formal point of view this is in contrastto our intuition of measurement as yielding a single value for the observable tobe measured rather than the family of all values it can assume. We could in ourmodel account for this by assuming that there is only one cell of the registerwhich is actualised in measurement in the sense that its value ’appears on thescreen’. This cell would contain the ’actual’ state of the combined system aswe always assumed in our previous considerations that a system possesses anactual state. This process of actualising a value would then be governed by thestatistical formalism of quantum mechanics. But this is beyond the realm of ourlogical framework. All the logical framework can account for is how the processof disentanglement, projection and storage involved in measurement works.

There is, however a striking parallel between this logical model and Everett’smany worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. According to Everett’s ap-proach all values that an observable can assume are realised in measurement,however in different worlds.

To get a more intuitive picture imagine one gets the task of somehow ’imple-menting’ the model say as a computer program. In order to do this one would

Page 177: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 177

have to implement the register as a data structure so to speak. One would,moreover, have to implement the process of disentanglement and storage of the’entangled’ components in the register. Another part of this implementationwould then be ’actualisation’, i.e. the process of (randomly) selecting a certaincell of the register the contents of which constitutes the ’actual value’. On thisview of the model as being ’implemented’ in nature the (Hilbert space) logicsinvolved, in particular the register and its cells, appear as physically real. Again,we are reminded here of a certain analogy with the many worlds interpretationof quantum mechanics according to which all the diverse worlds into which theactual world splits in the process of measurement are considered equally real.

11.1.9 Classical Measurement and the Idempotence of Mea-surement

Let us now look at our model of measurement in the case of two classical sys-tems. It should reflect the ’unproblematic’ nature of classical measurement. Inthe case of classical measurement we have two classical systems. Both the mea-suring system and the system to be measured are classical and thus representedas one-dimensional Hilbert space logics. We will first analyse this case and thenmake the point that repeated measurement is very mich like classical measure-ment leaving the system to be measured unchanged. This is idempotence ofmeasurement.

So let (Li)i∈I be the phase logic representing the measurement instrumentand L) the logic to be measured. Let A = (λi)i∈I be the pointer variable andB = (λi)i∈I the observable to be measured. Now note that there exists exactlyone j ∈ I such that (in Hilbert space notation) | A = λj〉⊗ | B =j 〉 is acorrelation (in cell j. What is j? It is the unique index j such that B = λj

is true in calL. The correlation (in cell j is then | A = λj〉⊗ | B = λj〉. Weview of the fact that the second ⊗ -factor is the state of the system measured asexpressing the fact that there was ’no change of state’ in the system measured.

Let us now look at the case of repeated measurement. We already saw thatwe have an explanation of the fact that on measurement there was ’collapse’(projection). What our model of measurement still needs to explain is that anyfurther measurement does not change the state of the system measured. This isidempotence of measurement. This follows from our second postulate concerningthe temporal evolution in measurement as follows. Assume the state of L aftermeasurement (and thus projection) is | B = λj for some j ∈ I. Now performa further measurement, i,e. correlate with the same measuring instrument asin the preceding measurement. We claim that the combined system ends upin state A = λj〉 ⊗ B = λj〉. This is a correlation as required. Why is itthe correlation the measurement ends up with? The answer is that all othercorrelations violate the second principle. Namely, all correlations have the form| A = λi〉⊗ | B = λi〉. But, clearly, if | B = λj〉 was the initial state of L, then| A = λj〉⊗ | B = λj〉 is the only corelation satisfying the second postulate.

Our (logical) model of measurement, therefore, provides an explanation ofthe absence of collapse in classical measurement as well as the idempotence of

Page 178: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

178 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

measurement in general.

11.1.10 Schroedinger’s cat revisited

Let us now revisit Schroedinger’s cat and look at it from the viewpoint of thetheory presented above.

Let A be the observable representing ’the cats’s life’ assuming the values 1and 2. A = 1 says ”the cat is alive”, A = 2 says ”the cat is dead”. Let B bethe observable representing the direction of the (z-component of ) the spin ofthe electron. B = 1 says ”spin is up” and B = 2 says ”spin is down”.

Let the phase logic representing the cat be ( in explicit notation) (L)i, i =1, 2. More precisely L〉 has the form LΨi

Ψi(A = i = 〈x〉. This says that A = 1,i.e. ”cat is alive”, is true in L1 and thus A = 2, i.e. ”cat dead”, is false in L1.A = 2, i.e. ”cat is dead”, is true in 2 and A = 1, i.e. ”cat is alive”, is false inL2.

Let L denote the (two-dimensional) Hilbert space logic pertaining to theelectron (spin).

According to our general theory there are only two correlations of A andB, again in Hilbert space notation, | A = 1〉⊗ | B = 1〉 or in the notation of..? | alive〉⊗ | up〉, and | A = 2〉⊗ | B = 2〉, i.e. | dead〉⊗ |〉 ’stored’ in theregister (Li ⊗ L))i, i = 1, 2. So, in our model, the only possible states aftermeasurement are the above, as we expect on the basis of our (macroscopic)experience of measurement. On this view the cat cannot be ’half alive’ and ’halfdead’ but must be either alive or dead nor is the electron in a superposition.Rather the electron spin is either ’up’ or ’down’

We may view the mechanism involved as follows.Before measurement the state is (in Hilbert space notation)

z =| alive〉 ⊗ 1/√

(2)(| up〉− | down〉)

or equivalently

z1 = 1/√

(2)(| alive〉⊗ | up〉− | dead〉⊗ | down〉)

Viewed logically the above says that the state x in the logical sense, i.e. `z1

is a superposition of x1 and y1 such that `x1 | alive〉⊗ | up〉 and `y1 | alive〉⊗ |down〉.

After measurement we have a correlation, namely

z1 = 1/√

(2)(| alive〉⊗ | up〉+ | dead〉⊗ | down〉Viewed logically this means that `z1 is a superposition of `x2 and `y2 such

that `x2 | alive〉⊗ | up〉 and `y2 | dead〉⊗ | down〉. Both `x2 and `y2 are incalL1⊗L as well as in 2⊗L. However, both in calL1⊗L and in L2⊗L exactlyone of them zero and exactly one of them non-zero. Thus, from the logical pointof view, vdashz2 is in fact equal to `x2 or `y2 and thus no genuine superposition.

This is how Schroedinger’s cat looks in our picture.

Page 179: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 179

11.1.11 Is the Hilbert space formalism the whole story?Legget’s macrorealism

In several papers Anthony Legget, distinguished physicist and Nobel laureate,put forward his view on physical reality and the formalism of quantum mechanicswhich has become known as ’macrorealism’. Here are some quotations from [37].

”There is simply no convincing evidence that macroscopic superpositions ofthe type. .. exist in nature”

”A second reason for reluctance to consider the possibility outlined above liesat a more philosophical level. With few exceptions (who include David Bohm),scientists of the last 300 years or so have been deeply committed to a form ofreductionism which holds, in effect, that the behaviour of a complex system ofmatter must be simply the the sum of the behaviour of its constituent parts.”

”In this essay I shall try to defend three claims. the first is that the classicquantum measurement paradox, so far from being a non-problem, is a suffi-ciently glaring indication of the inadequacy of quantum mechanics as a totalworld view that it should motivate us actively to explore the likely direction inwhich it will break down.”

”Indeed, Bohr, and with greater sophistication Reichenbach were able to todevelop an interpretation of the quantum-mechanical formalism which is con-sistent with within its self-imposed limits precisely by postulating a radicallydifferent ontological status for microscopic entities such as electrons or neutronsand the macroscopic apparatus which perfoms the measurement. In the wordsof a famous quatation by Bohr: ’Atomic systems should not even be thought ofas possessing definite properties in the absence of a specific experimental set-updesigned to measure these proprties.”

”The point of view I am proposing - namely that QM may not be the wholetruth about the physical world- is likely to be strongly antithetical to the viewsof many ...”

So, according to Leggett the (Hilbert space) formalism of quantum mechan-ics gives a correct description of microscopic reality, the world of subatomicparticles, quantum reality so to speak. He doubts however, that it provides anadequate description of macrosopic reality such as cats and buildings or plan-etes. On this view, it is the laws of classical physics, more precisely the theoryof relativity, that govern macroscopic reality.

The crucial question is whether there exist ’macroscopic superpositions’.Can Schroedinger’s cat be ”half alive and half dead”? Something like this hasnever been observed. The explanation given by those believing in the universalvalidity of the formalism of quantum mechanics is a phenomenon called deco-herence. We need not go into this in detail here. It is enough to say here thatdecoherence is a quantum effect arising from the interaction of macroscopicreality with its environment to the effect that superpositions of macroscopicstates cannot be observed. So, on this view, even in the macroscopic worldsuperpositions do exist, but, due to decoherence, they cannot be observed.

Let us, in this section, describe some parallels between the approach takenin this book, in particular our treatment of measurement, and Legget’s views.

Page 180: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

180 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

These parallels are surprising because both approaches stem from completelydifferent origins. Legget’s macrorealism rests on purely physical considerationswhereas the approach of this book has its roots in logic. In fact, purely logi-cal results (on holistic logics) and our (logical) treatment of the measurementproblem suggest, at the physical level, a view very much along the lines ofLegget’s macrorealism. In particular, our results suggest an answer to the ques-tion whether the Hilbert space formalism is the whole story. This answer isnegative. Moreover, our results suggest an answer to the question what thewhole story is.

Once one has adopted macrorealism one is tempted to give a ready madeanswer to that question by saying that the whole story is ”quantun mechanics +classical mechanics” rather than quantum mechanics (Hilbert space formalism).What is unsatisfactory about this answer is that this framework, ”Hilbert space+ phase space” does not constitute a unified framework. Rather, this answeramounts to saying that there are two different types of reality, i.e. quantum andclassical, which have to be described in two completely different (mathematical)frameworks. This is unsatisfactory. A satisfactory answer to the question whatthe whole story is must provide a unified framework treating these two types ofreality in a unified way. We will argue that from the logical point of view thereis such a unified framework.

What is the main link between the logical framework of this book andLegget’s macrorealism?

To explain this let us recall the train of thought underlying our discussionof the measurement problem. In our treatment of measurement we faced theproblem how to represent the ’classical’ nature of the measuring instrument.In this choice we were guided by the Limiting Case Theorem. We representmeasurement instrument, logically, by a complete classical theory, more pre-cisely by a family of complete classical theories. We combined in our treatmentof the measurement problem Hilbert space with phase space. And, on certainreasonable assumptions in accordance with those of Quantum Mechanics, thisapproach provided us with a satisfactory way of accounting for the measurementproblem.

holistic logics. The latter are, as we proved, closely related to Hilbert spaces.It is via this logical connection that two seemingly unrelated structures, namelyphase space, which is the state space in classical mechanics, and Hilbert space,which is the state space in quantum mechanics, appear closely related in anatural way. As already explained in section ?, from the logical point of viewphase space is a limiting case of Hilbert space. Logically, phase space is the’monotonic limit’ of Hilbert space. Since this is important for the point wewant to make in this section let us recall what this means more precisely. Thelogics presentable by Hilbert spaces are non-monotonic. Now, the property ofnon-monotonicity may be ragarded as the logical counterpart of the presence ofuncertainty relations at the physical level. Monotonicity of logic,accordingly, isthe logical counterpart of the absence of uncertainty relations at the physicallevel. If, logically, we ’pass to the limit’ in the direction of monotonicity weget classical logical structures, namely complete classical theories. Physically,

Page 181: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.1. A LOOK AT THE MEASUREMENT PROBLEM 181

we may regard this ’passage to the limit’ as being from uncertainty relations tothe absence of uncertainty relations and we may think of these classical theoriesas the ’logics’ of classical physical systems, i.e. sets of propositions true of aclassical physical system. Thus, in this sense, we may view phase space as alimiting case of Hilbert space if we pass to the limit from uncertainty relationsto the absence of uncertainty relations. This is the situation we have in classicalmechanics.

On this view the transition from general holistic logics, in particular itsmain representatives, Hilbert space logics, to complete classical theories appearssmooth. Moreover, complete classical theories are holistic logics, namely themonotonic ones.

Now, we can ask the question what all this could mean for physics? Ofcourse, in this we can only speculate. But let us in the light of our results makea guess.

There is overwhelming evidence that the formalism of quantum mechanics,the core of which is Hilbert space, is adequate for describing the microscopicworld. It undoubtedly provides the adequate description of electrons and otherelementary particles. It is the measurement problem, especially in its dramaticform as ’Schroedinger’s cat’, however, that raises the question whether this for-malism offers an adequate description of macroscopic reality such as the planetsor cats.

From our logical point of view we may say that Hilbert space logics ’rep-resent’ microscopic reality whatever this means. In any case it is the realityof electrons etc. Now, if there is such a close conection between Hilbert spacelogics and classical logic and such a smooth transition, could it be that the limitstructures, which are classical, represent some domain of reality too? In viewof the role of phase space as a limiting case, could it be that the issue at stakeis not ”either Hilbert space or phase space” but ”Hilbert and phase space”?Could it be that the limiting case is realised too in nature? If we answer thesequestions in the affirmative we arrive at Legget’s macrorealism.

As we said, any answer to the question is speculation. But let us for thesake of an argument in favour of a positive answer return to our discussion ofmeasurement. Recall that in our attempt to treat measurement we faced theproblem of representing the measuring instrument. We had to account for the’classical’ nature of the measuring instrument. The way we chose to do this wasto represent the measuring instrument by a limiting case structure, namely acomplete classical theory and, in fact, this was the only reasonable choice wehad. But let us also note that this way of doing it gave us -on certain naturalassumptions also made in quantum mechanics- a satisfactory treatment of themeasurement problem. Essentially, what we did was to combine a classical(holistic) logic with a non-classical one, a monotonic one with a non-monotonicone with the monotonic (classical) one representing the classical part in themeasurement process, namely the measuring instrument. Formally this way ofdealing with the measurement problem was successful. in that it provided anexplanation that the state after measurement is not an entanglement and itprovided an explanation for the projection postulate. The question we now face

Page 182: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

182 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

is whether is not a purely formal trick or whether could be that way in nature.Again, all we can say is that if nature is that way then measurement poses noproblem. This would in fact mean that the Hilbert space formalism is not thewhole story. The whole story would be our framework of holistic logics includingthe limiting case structures. In a more familiar terminology the it would not be”Hilbert space” but ”Hilbert space + Phase space”. And the whole of (physical)reality would be not ”quantum” but ”quantum + classical”.

Of course Leggett’s macrorealism raises problems. First, if he were right, wewould have completely different, even seemingly contradictory descriptions ofthe microscopic and the macroscopic physical world respectively. But what ismacroscopic? What is microscopic? Second, it would mean that, since macro-scopic objects may be regarded as aggregates of microscopic objects, classicalmechanics should be reducible to quantum mechanics which, however, doesn’tseem to be the case.

The question is whether the state of a macroscopic object can be a super-position. Can Schroedinger’s cat be ”half alive and half dead”? Somethinglike that has never been observed. The explanation given by those believing inthe universal validity of the formalism of quantum mechanics is a phenomenoncalled decoherence. We need not go into this in detail here. It is enough tosay this here. Decoherence is a quantum effect arising from the interaction ofmacroscopic reality with its environment to the effect that superpositions ofmacroscopic states cannot be observed. So, on this view, even in the macro-scopic world superpositions do exist, but, due to decoherence, they cannot beobserved.

Another problem raised by Legget’s macrorealism is the general problem ofreductionism. Can the behaviour of macroscopic objects in principle be reducedto that of microscopic objects? If there are no macroscopic superpositions, thenthe answer is no because,if if the formalism of quantum mechanics applies, wenever get rid of superpositions. The cat’s being ’half alive and half dead’ cannotbe ruled out as a possible state of the cat.

11.1.12 Does logic depend on decoherence?

The explanation offered for the apparent absence of superpositions in our macro-scopic experience by those who adhere to the view that the formalism of QMapplies universally is, as already mentioned, a quantum mechanical effect calleddecoherence. On the other hand it seems that absence of superpositions is aprecondition for classical (predicate) logic in which it is taken for granted thatobjects possess definite properties. If the adherents to decoherence were right,would this then mean that the possibility of classical logic is due to a a quantumeffect? This question is at least worth discussing.

Page 183: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.2. A BIT OF METAPHYSICS 183

11.2 A Bit of Metaphysics

11.2.1 Dualism versus Monism in Physics and Logic

One of the fundamental differences between classical and quantum physics un-doubtedly concerns the role of observation. In classical physics observation or,say, measurement is a sort of ’looking’ at a certain objective reality outside theobserver. It is taken for granted that there exists a clear cut separation betweenthe observer and the reality observed. It is undisputable, however, that thisdualistic picture is hard to defend in quantum mechanics. In Bohr’s words, theprocess of measurement is ”unanalysable”. In the process of measurement inquantum mechanics the observer and the observed system form an inseparablewhole. The dualistic view of the observer on the one hand and the observedreality on the other, of subject on the one hand and the object on the other,seems to be untenable in quantum mechanics.

In modern logic we have a similar dualism which is not even confined consti-tutes a typical feature of modern style logic in general since Tarski. It concernsthe separation between the two components a modern logical system generallyconsists of, namely the separation between syntactic representation on the handand semantic representation of the other. This issue of separation between syn-tax and semantics is addressed by Girard in [] as follows: ”The current explana-tion of logic distinguishes between the world (objective) and its representation(subjective), the object and the subject. Logical realism relies on an oppositionbetween semantics (the world) and syntax (its representation): this oppositionis highly problematic...”. There efforts under way which aim at overcoming thisdualism, for instance in what has become known as game theoretic semantics.

In this book we have come across logical systems in which the problemof dualism is solved or at least avoided in a radical way. These are the logicalstructures we called holistic logics. How do holistic logics get rid of the problem?

In order to make things precise we first have to ask ourselves what thecounterpart of this question is on the side of logic. This is closely related tothe issue of semantics in logic. Suppose we have a logical system presented,say, as a deductive system. We are confronted with the issue of ”reality” whenit comes to giving a semantics to this system. It is in choosing the semanticstructures that we make our commitment to a certain type of reality. The term’giving semantics’ shows by the way that we tacitly take it for granted that inbuilding a system in the style of modern logic we require the system to have twoseparate components, namely a syntactic component and a semantic component,one describing the laws of reasoning so to speak and the other describing thedomain of reality the reasoning is about. This issue of separation between syntaxand semantics is addressed by Girard in a completely different context: ”Thecurrent explanation of logic distinguishes between the world (objective) and itsrepresentation (subjective), the object and the subject. Logical realism relies onan opposition between semantics (the world) and syntax (its representation):this opposition is highly problematic...”. One question we may ask is this. Is itpossible to depart from classical logic in such a way that the resulting system is

Page 184: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

184 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

free from this dualist feature which is displayed not only by classical logic butwhich, according to Girard, is characteristic of our current explanation of logic.

In any case, it seems that the way we reflect our intuitions concerning realityin quantum mechanics at the level of logic must be based on considerationsconcerning the role which semantics is to play in the systems to be constructed.In fact, our way of departing from classical logic in building quantum logicconsists in imposing a condition on the system to be constructed which amountsto overcoming the dualism between syntactic and semantic representation.

There is another requirement, however, if the analogy classical (quantum)mechanics versus classical (quantum) logic is to be complete. Since classical me-chanics is a limiting case of quantum mechanics we must require the structureswe are looking for to have classical logic as a limiting case. So let us formulateour task as follows: Define the concept of holistic logic in such a way that it hasclassical logic as a limiting case!

Assume we succeed in this enterprise and assume further that the structureswe come up with are strongly connected to the formalism of quantum mechanics(Hilbert space formalism), what would be gained? Well, we could then withsubstantial justification say that we touched upon the ’true’ logical structuresunderlying quantum mechanics.

11.2.2 Logical Monadology

In chapter 3 we described Bohm’s rheomode experiment with language. In thatexperiment he proposed to construct a new mode of language in addition tothe modes we have so far such as indicative, subjunctive, imperative,and, to acertain degree even developed a concrete view on this. Bohm’s motivation forthis was the issue of reality in quantum mechanics. This is our starting pointtoo. Let us make the connection.

As already pointed out, we want our way of departing from classical logictowards quantum logic to reflect the way how quantum mechanics departs fromclassical mechanics. We said that this departure is of a profound nature in thatit involves a revision of our traditional view of physical reality.

We saw that in building a modern-style logical system the issue of realityenters the stage via semantics. It is in the choice of the semantic structuresfor a logic that we make a commitment to the structure of reality. What willour commitment to reality be? The answer is that we want this commitmentto be minimal. In what sense? In order to explain this, assume we have alogic L presented somehow, say as a deductive system. Giving semantics tothe logic means specifying a class of semantic structure for L. Normally, thesestructures are ’external’ to the logic ’L’. Think for instance of predicate logicpresented as a deductive system, say in Hilbert, Gentzen style... The procedureof giving semantics to the system is well known: specify the well known relationalstructures (models) of predicate logic, define the notion of satisfaction (truth)of a formula in a model, prove soundness and completeness of the system ...

If we now claim that the logic thus obtained is not just a mathematicalconstruction but constitutes a tool for actually reasoning about the world, then

Page 185: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.2. A BIT OF METAPHYSICS 185

we have made a commitment to our view of reality. Namely, we have committedourselves to the view that the relational structures that we chose as our semanticstructures properly represent or reflect reality, at least the type of reality wereason about in predicate logic.. We commit ourslves to the view that there existindividuals, that these individuals have properties represented as predicates,that there exist relations between undividuals and so on. Needless to say, this isthe linguistic reconstruction of the fragmented world view which needs revisionin the quantum domain. Let us now, at this stage, make clear how we want todepart from classical logic in building quantum logic. Let us reiterate that ourmotivation is the issue of reality in quantum mechanics. We cannot solve theseproblems nor did we try to do that. What we tried to convey is nothing but thewide spread feeling among physicists and philosophers of science that quantummechanics departs from classical mechanics in a very profound way in that thisprocess touches upon the very nature of reality. On the other hand we said thatgiving semantics to a logical system always involves a certain commitment to acertain view of reality. We are, however, unclear about the nature of ’quantumreality’. It seems to us that this is the main dilemma we face in building quantumlogic.

Is there a way out of this dilemma?We think there is and and for this we propose an experiment. We emphasise

it’s an experiment!We want to construct logical structures with a minimum of commitment to

the structure of (external) realityLet us make precise what we mean by ’mimimum of commitment to the

structure of reality’.Since we can hardly deny the logic to be real, we think that the following

Principle expresses a sort of minimality condition.Principle of Monadicity: The only semantic structures relevant to the logics

to be described are the logics themselves. If we think of a logical system as asystem reasoning about some domain of reality, then for a systems satisfying theabove principle, a logical monad so to speak, this reality is nothing but itself.Thus the only (domain of) reality such a logic can ’reason’ about is itself. Ourintuition is that these systems -yet to be constructed- reason about themselvesonly, about their own ’internal working’ so to spek. It should be a sort ofreasoning about their own reasoning.

This is indeed a radical way of getting rid of the problem of reality in logic.That the logic itself is real can hardly be denied, and thus this is a radical way ofavoiding any too strong commitment regarding the nature of (quantum) reality.

We would like here, for methodological reasons, to emphasise the following.The fact that we aim at constructing logics not committed to any reality ’out-side itself’ does by no imply any claim on our part concerning the nature ofphysical reality. Rather, let us reiterate that what we are doing is performingan experiment on the platform of logic in which we do not have the vexingproblem of a potentially too strong commitment to the structure of reality. Wepursue this line and we will see what the outcome of the experiment is.

The above principle has several implications.

Page 186: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

186 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

The first implication concerns the notion of truth. Generally, in the spiritof the correspondence theory of truth, the notion of truth of a formula in somelogical language is defined as ’truth in a model’, i.e. relative to the semanticstructures for the logic. In view of the above principle our notion of truth willbe a notion of self-referential truth.

We may further ask the question what formulas can be true or false in view ofthe above principle. Obviously these are the formulas that ’talk’ about the logic,formulas making a statement about the logic, i.e. metastatements. This posesanother problem if we are tmake sense of the monadicity principle. Namely, ifmetastatements are the only formulas that can be true or false, then the objectlanguage must be capable of expressing metastatements. Moreover, we mustrequire it to be rich in expressive power with respect to metastatements, i.e.it must be able to express all statements that can be a made in the languagewhich may reasonably be called the metalanguage of the logic. We thus expectthe object language to contain the metalanguage of the logic.

And, if we require the logic, as usual, to be sound and complete, this meansthat we require it to be capable of proving all true metastatements and onlythose. And thus, if we require sundness, we require self-referential soundnessand if we require completeness, we require self-referential completeness.

What do we expect to be the logic of the metastatements. Since the metas-tatement ’talk’ about some reality, namely the logic itself, and we, in this,assume the correspondence theory of truth, we expect them to obey classicallogic. This means that the logic of the metalanguage must be classical logic.

Let us first point out that our condition that classical logic should be alimiting case of holistic logic should, heuristically, be viewed as imposing acondition on the way we depart from classical logic in the process of constructingquantum logic. It should be viewed as saying that we should not deviate ’toofar’ from classical logic in that process.

We may, reminiscent of Leibniz’s ”Monadology”, want to construct ’logicalmonads’, logical systems which are so to speak as self-contained as Leibniz’smonads. In fact, we will see that there exist striking parallels between theframework of holistic logics and Leibniz’s ”Monadology”.

We start this section with a word of caution because it may easily be per-ceived as having a smell of metaphysics. And if there is one thing we do not wantto do then this is to engage in metaphysical speculation. Rather we would liketo direct the reader’s attention to certain parallels with a famous philosophicaltreatise which may be regarded as being metaphysical speculation. This trea-tise is Leinniz’s ”Monadology”. All we will do in this paragraph is to pointout certain parallels between what Leibniz says about the monads and certainproperties of holistic logics. We think that these parallels are surprising and,maybe, not accidental.

What are Leibnz’s monads? In paragraph 1 he says: ”Monads, which are ourconncern here, are nothing other than simple substances” They have ’no parts’.Paragraph 3 reads: ”Now where there are no parts, neither extension nor shapenor division is possible. These monads are the true atoms of nature. In aword, they are the elements of things”. Monads are completely self-sufficient.

Page 187: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.2. A BIT OF METAPHYSICS 187

Paragraph 7 contains the famous sentence: ”The monads have no windowsthrough which anything can come in or go out”.

Another property of the monads is stated in paragraph 18: ”...They enjoyself-sufficiency (autarkia that renders them the source of their internal actionsand makes them, so to speak, incorporeal automata”

Another famous property Leibniz attributes to the monads is that of being amirror. Every monad ’mirrors’ the whole universe. Paragraph 56 reads: ”Nowthis interconnection and accommodation of every created thing to every other,of all to each, gives every simple substance relations that express all the othersso that each one is a perpetual living mirror of the universe.”

The reader may note the ’modern talk’ which might easily be found in a pop-ular scientific or seriously scientific or philosophical book on quantum mechanicsemphasising the fatures of interconnectedness and wholeness of ’quantum real-ity’.

What, now, are the parallels with holistic logics? To see this let us recallthe main features of the notion of a holistic logic. First, why did we call themholistic? The main reason for this was the phenomenon of encodedness whichmeans that non-orthogonal consequence relations of a holistic logics. We re-state this for the case of a Hilbert space logics. Let LH be a (holistic) logicpresented by a Hilbert space H,let x, y ∈ H be non-orthogonal with pointersσx, σy respectively. . Then we have:

`x α iff `y σx ; α

and

`y α iff `x σxα

In this sense `x and `y are encoded in each other. We may view this asa sort of ’mirroring’ . Note that ’mirroring’ in this sense does not in any wayimply ’containing’. For `x α does not imply `x. What the above intuitivelysays is: If `x proves α, then `y provesnotnecessarilyα but the provability of αin `y. But in which sense does the metaphor ’monad’ apply to holistic logics?In which sense may they be viewed as ’self-contained’ (logical) atoms. It isthe property of self-referential completeness that supports this metaphor. Letus recall what self-referential completenees means. Essentially, it means thatthe elements of a holistic logic are logical systems reflecting their metatheoryat the object level in the sense that they can prove all true metastatementsand only those metastatements which are true. This, however, is not the fullstory yet. Rather, we have the ’no windows’ theorem saying that the set ofall statements proved by a holistic logic is classically inconsistent and thus hasno classical model. So, metaphorically, we may say that holistic logics are justabout themselves without ’windows’. Here the picture of Leibniz’s self-contained’incorporeal automata’ comes to mind.

Leibniz regards the monads not only as real but as the ultimate constituentsof reality. Let us tentatively pursue the analogy between Leibniz’s monadsand our holistic logics a bit further. We saw that, in our logical picture, pure

Page 188: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

188 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

quantum states, which in the Hilbert space formalism are represented as rays ina Hilbert space, appear as the logical monads described. What about ascribingphysical reality to them? What would it mean? It would mean ascribing realityto the quantum states themselves. On the raditional view the quantum statesare states of a certain physical system say the electron in the hydrogen atom.The primary physical reality , however, is on this view the electron and and theconcept of a (quantum) state appears as derived from the concept of a particle.They are, in this picture, a sort of states of information about the particle whichconstitutes the primary physical reality. In this there is no conceptual differencewith classical mechanics where the state of a particle is known if its positionand momentum are known (phase space). The analogy with Leibnz’s monadswould suggest a different view, namely the view regarding the quantum statesas physical reality prior to that of the particle. On this view it would be the’logical monads’ (quantum states) that constitute the electron. The concept ofa particle would on this view be a derived concept, namely derived from that ofa state (monad). But this is enough metaphysics.

11.3 Reflections on holicity

Let us revisite the intuitive considerations on what in a preliminary terminologywe called logical monads. We argue that the concept of a holistic logic, the topicof this chapter, conforms to those intuitions.

We said that logical monads should in no way rely on any ’external reality’.The only semantic structure relevant to the logic was to be the logic itself. Doholistic logics meet this requirement? We think yes they do. Recall our notionof truth in a holistic logic. It is selfreferential truth. Only metastatements, i.e,statements talking about the logic itself, can be true or false. The requirementthat the metalanguage may be regarded as a sublanguage of the object languagehas been made precise. We have a proof operator in the (object) language,namely σ ; .... Holistic logics are sound and complete in that they can proveall true formulas and only these. The true formulas are the true metastatements.This is what we called self-referential truth.

What is the logic of the metastatements? Since metastatements talk aboutsome piece of reality, namely the logic itself, we expect them to ’obey’ classicallogic. In fact, formulas expressing metastatements behave classically in everyrespect.

What is the significance of the No Windows Theorem, which says that theset of formulas proved by a consequence relation of a holistic logic is classicallyinconsistent. What would it mean if these ’theories’ were classically consis-tent? We would then, by the completeness theorem of classical logic, have aclassical models, i.e. ’external’ semantic structures. The consequence relationswould reason about some ’external reality’. This would destroy the picture ofthe monads. We think that this fact, namely the classical inconsisteny of theconsequence relations, together with self-referential soundness and completenessstrongly support our intuitions. The Non Windows Theorems ’protect’ the sys-

Page 189: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

11.3. REFLECTIONS ON HOLICITY 189

tems considered from any ’external reality’. One is reminded of what Leibnizin his ”monadology” says about the monads: ”The monads have no windows”.

Note, however, the following. We saw that the metalanguage may be re-garded as a sublanguage of the object language. What about the set of metas-tatements proved by the consequence relations? This set of formulas is classi-cally consistent. It is the set of true statements about a certain ’reality’, andthat reality is the logic itself.

We will see in ”Kochen-Specker-Schutte Revisited” that the sharpened nowindows theorem imlies the existence of a Kochen-Specker-Schutte tautology.So, on this view the Kochen-Specker-Schutte phenomenon loses its seeminglyaccidental nature. It appears as an exression of an essential feature of the logicsunderlying quantum mechanics.

Page 190: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

190 CHAPTER 11. SOME SPECULATIVE REFLECTIONS

Page 191: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

Bibliography

[1] G. Antoniou. Nonmonotonic Reasoning, MIT Press, 1997

[2] G. Birkhoff, J. von Neumann. The logic of quantum mechanics. Annals ofMathematics, 823–843, 1936

[3] G. Boolos. The Logic of Provability, Cambridge University Press, 1993.

[4] D. Bohm. Wholeness and the Implicate Order, Routledge, 1980

[5] M. Born. Quantenmechanik der Stossvorgaenge. Zeitschrift f. Physik, 1926

[6] M. Born, P. Jordan, W. Heisenberg. Zur Quantenmechanik II, Zeitschrift f.Physik, 1926

[7] M. Born, P. Jordan. Zur Quantenmechanik, Zeitschrift f. Physik, 34, 1925

[8] M. Born, N. Wiener. Eine neue Formulierung der Quantengesetze fur peri-odische und nicht periodische Vorgaenge. Zeitschrift f. Physik, 1926

[9] C. Cohen-Tannoudji, B. Diu, F. Laloe. Quantum Mechanics Vol. 1, 2. JohnWiley, 1977

[10] M.L. Dalla Chiara. Quantum Logic. In Gabbay and Guenthner (eds.) Hand-book of Philosophical Logic Vol. III, pp 427–469, 1986. Revised version inHandbook of Philosophical Logic, Second edition, Volume 6, pp. 129–228,Kluwer, 2001.

[11] M.L. Dalla Chiara. Quantum logic and physical modalities. J. PhilosophicalLogic, 6, 77, 391–404, 1977

[12] M.L. Dalla Chiara, R. Giuntini, R. Greechie. Reasoning in Quantum The-ory, Kluwer, 2004

[13] A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, N. Rosen. Can the quantum mechanical descrip-tion of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 1935

[14] K. Engesser, D.M. Gabbay, Quantum logic, Hilbert space, revision theory.Artificial Intelligence, 2002

[15] R. Feynman. Lectures on Physics. Addison Wesley, 2006

191

Page 192: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

192 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[16] U. Friedrichsdorf. Einfuehrung in die klassische und intensionale Logik.Vieweg, 1992

[17] D.M. Gabbay. Investigations in Modal and Tense Logic with Applicationsto Problems in Philosophy and Linguistics. Dordrecht, 1976

[18] D.M. Gabbay. LDS. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1996

[19] D. M. Gabbay. Fibring Logics. Oxford University Press, 1999

[20] D. M. Gabbay. Dynamics of Practical Reasoning: A position paper InAdvances in Modal Logic 2, K. Segerberg, M. Zakhryaschev, M. de Rijkeand H. Wansing, eds. pp. 179–224. CSLI Publications, CUP, 2001.

[21] D.M. Gabbay. Theoretical Foundations for non-monotonic reasoning in ex-pert systems. In K.R. Apt, editor, Proceedings NATO Advanced Study In-stitute on Logics and Models of Concurrent Systems, pp. 439-457. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1985.

[22] P. Gardenfors. Knowledge in Flux, MIT Press, 1989

[23] J.-Y. Girard. From foundations to Ludics. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic9, 131-168, 2003

[24] . on the Meaning of Logical Rules I: Syntax versus Semantics, ?

[25] R.H. Goldblatt. Semantic analysis of orthologic. J. Philosophical Logic, 3,74, 19–35, 1974

[26] P.Halmos. Introduction to Hilbert Space and the Theory of Spectral Multi-plicity, 2nd edition, Chelsea, New York, 1957

[27] G.M. Hardegree. The Conditional in Quantum Logic. Synthese, 29, 63–80,1974

[28] W. Heisenberg. Uber die quantentheoretische Umdeutung kinematischerund mechanischer Beziehungen. Zeitschrift fur Physik, 33, 1925

[29] W. Heisenberg. Physics and Philosophy,

[30] D. Hilbert, P. Bernays. Grundlagen der Mathematik II. Springer ?, Berlin,1970

[31] S.S. Holland. Orthomodularity in Infinite Dimensions, A Theorem of M.Soler. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 32, 205–234, 1995

[32] G. Kalmbach. Orthomodular Lattices. London Math. Soc. Monographs, Vol.18 Academic Press, London and New York, 1983

[33] S.Kochen, E. Specker. The problem of hidden variables in quantum me-chanics. Journal of Mathematics and mechanics 17, pp. 59-87

Page 193: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

BIBLIOGRAPHY 193

[34] S. Kraus, D. Lehmann, and M. Magidor. Non-Monotonic Reasoning, pref-erential models and cumulative logics. Artificial Intelligence, 44, 167–207,1990

[35] H. Katsuno and K. Sato. A unified view of consequence relation, beliefrevision and conditional logic. In G. Crocco, L. Farinas del Cerro, and A.Herzig, editors, Conditionals : From Philosophy to Computer Science, pp.33–66. Oxford University Press, 1995.

[36] H. A. Keller. Ein nichtklassischer Hilbertscher Raum. MathematischeZeitschrift, , 41-49.

[37] A. Legget, ?

[38] D. Lehmann, M. Magidor. What does a conditional knowledge base entail?Artificial Intelligence, 55, 1–60, 1992

[39] D. Lehmann. Non-Monotonic Logic and Semantics, Journal of Logic andSemantics, ?

[40] D. Lehmann, Connectives in quantum and other cumulative logics. Tech-nical Report Hebrew University of Jerusalem, 2002

[41] D. Lehmann. Non-monotonic logic and semantics. Journal of Logic andComputation

[42] D. Lehmann, K. Engesser, D.M. Gabbay. Algebras of Measurements: thelogical structure of Quantum Mechanics. International Journal of Theoreti-cal Physics

[43] D. Makinson and P. Gardenfors. Relation between the logic of theorychange and non-monotonic logic. In The Logic Theory of Change, A.Fuhrmann and H. Morreau, eds. pp. 185–205. Lecture Notes in AI, 465,Springer Verlag, 1991.

[44] G. Hardegree. The conditional in quantum logic. in Suppes (ed.) Logic andProbability in quantum Mechanics, reidel, Dordrecht, pp 55-72 CHECK!

[45] R. Mayet. Some Characterizations of the Underlying Division Ring of aHilbert Lattice by Automorphisms. International Journal of TheoreticalPhysics, 37, 1998

[46] P. Mittelstaedt. Quantum Logic. D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1978

[47] Monk. Mathematical logic. Springer, 1976

[48] R.C. Moore. Semantical Considerations on Nonmonotonic Logic. ArtificialIntelligence 25, 1985

[49] F.D. Peat. Einstein’s Moon, Contemporary Books, 1990

Page 194: A New Approach to Quantum Logic

194 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[50] C. Piron. Foundations of Quantum Physics. W.A. Benjamin, Inc., 1976

[51] . K. Popper. ?

[52] A. Prestel. On Soler’s Characterization of Hilbert spaces. ManuscriptaMath., 86, 225–238, 1995

[53] H. Putnam. Is logic empirical? in R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds),Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol 5, Reidel-Dordrecht, 1969,pp 216-241

[54] M. Redei. Quantum Logic in Algebraic Approach. Kluwer Academic Pub-lishers, 1998

[55] M. Redei. The prenatal history of quantum logic. Preprint

[56] W. Rudin. Real and Complex Analysis. McGraw Hill, 1974

[57] A. Savile. Leibniz and the Monadology, Routledge, 2000

[58] E. Schrodinger. Quantisierung als Eigenwerproblem. Annalen der Physik,1926

[59] R.M. Smullyan. Forever Undecided. Oxford University Press, 1987

[60] R.M. Smullyan. Godel’s Incompleteness Theorems. Oxford UniversityPress, 1992

[61] M.P. Soler. Characterization of Hilbert spaces with orthomodular spaces.Comm. Algebra, 219–234, 1995

[62] J. von Neumann. Mathematische Begruendung der Quantenmechanik.Gottinger Nachrichten, 1927, pp 273-291

[63] J. von Neumann. Wahrscheinlichkeitstheoretischer Aufbau der Quanten-mechanik. Goettinger Nachrichten, 1927

[64] J. von Neumann. Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik,Berlin, Springer, 1932