9 a Neuroscientific Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by Edward Nersessian (New York)

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Neuropsychoanalysis

Citation preview

  • This article was downloaded by: [Gazi University]On: 18 August 2014, At: 22:54Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: MortimerHouse, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journalfor Psychoanalysis and the NeurosciencesPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20

    A Neuroscientific Perspective on Confabulation:Commentary by Edward Nersessian (New York)Edward Nersessianaa 72 East 91st Street, New York, NY 10128, e-mail:Published online: 09 Jan 2014.

    To cite this article: Edward Nersessian (2000) A Neuroscientific Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by EdwardNersessian (New York), Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journal for Psychoanalysis and the Neurosciences, 2:2,163-163, DOI: 10.1080/15294145.2000.10773301

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773301

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) containedin the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make norepresentations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose ofthe Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be reliedupon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shallnot be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and otherliabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematicreproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in anyform to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

  • Confabulation

    A Neuroscientific Perspective on ConfabulationCommentary by Edward Nersessian (New York)

    Dr. DeLuca's extensive review of the confabulationliterature and his own findings on the subject presentus with an opportunity to briefly review psychoana-lytic ideas about memory and attempt to find areas ofcomplementary interest and dialogue.

    Heretofore, psychoanalysis has not attempted acomprehensive study of memory in all its complexityas has been done in cognitive psychology. Issues suchas the distribution of memory, short term versus longterm, encoding, storage, retrieval, consolidation,priming, and types of memory such as implicit versusexplicit, procedural versus declarative have not beenat the forefront of psychoanalytic investigation. How-ever, there has been some recent and perhaps bur-geoning interest in memory types and their possiblerelevance to understanding transference and charactertraits. This last matter, though of great potential inter-est in regards to possibly refining our understandingof aspects of procedural and semantic memories, willnot be discussed in this brief commentary.

    The main focus of study for psychoanalysts inthe area of memory has been autobiographical mem-ory, that is to say, memory that in one way or anotherinvolves the self. Whereas most researchers studyingthis type of memory-often classified under explicitand/or declarative memory-have recognized the al-terations and unreliability of such memories over time(Loftus, 1980), to my knowledge only psychoanalystsdirect much attention to the specific nature and moti-vation for such distortions. In other words, distortionsin the recollection of short- and long-term memoriesconstitute an essential component of psychoanalyticwork. This focus derives from a basic tenet of psycho-analytic theory-the pleasure-unpleasure princi-ple-which is assumed to underlie the functioning ofthe mental apparatus. According to this principle, theorganism strives at all times to minimize unpleasure(pain) and to (perhaps) maximize pleasure. Therefore,in memory functioning and specifically in recollectionor remembering, most if not all distortions are as-sumed to be motivated, that is to say, the alterationhas occurred in order to minimize distress, even at

    Dr. Nersessian is Associate Professor of Psychiatry, Cornell Univer-sity Medical College; Supervising and Training Analyst, New York Psy-choanalytic Institute.

    163

    times at the cost of an impairment in reality testing.A point that needs to be stressed here, and which isnot always fully appreciated, is that the psychoanlyticmethod, particularly the aspect of it known as freeassociation, continues to be the method that providesthe data to substantiate this assertion. (It goes withoutsaying that the aim of the dialogue and collaborativeresearch between neuroscientists and psychoanalystsis to investigate other potential sources of data.) Thispsychoanalytic data demonstrate that memory is dy-namic and alive, not fixed and static, and furthermore,that part of this activity is the ongoing interaction be-tween the past and the present. As Kris (1956) wrote:"Not only does the present experience rest on the past,but the present supplies the incentive for the viewingof the past; the present selects, colors, and modifies.Memory, at least autobiographical or personal mem-ory, i.e., the least autonomous area of memory func-tion, is dynamic and telescopic" (p. 303).

    A brief clinical example may help clarify the waythat psychoanalysts look at the motivated distortionsof autobiographical memory.

    A 30-year-old man in psychoanalytic treatment(in this case, four 50-minute sessions per week), intalking about the death of his father, described howhe had called home as usual on a Sunday evening andwas told by his mother that his father had suffered afatal heart attack that afternoon. This man's father wasa highly authoritative and at times physically punitiveman, and the son had always felt overpowered by him,both physically and intellectually. Two years into hispsychoanalysis, this same patient retold the story ofhis father's death. In this version, he had been homefor the weekend when his father had died, but hadleft to go back to college on Sunday afternoon. Uponarriving in his dorm, he had called home, and was toldabout his father's heart attack. In the fourth year ofhis analysis, having resolved much of his repressedrage and the accompanying guilt toward his father, hethen recalled that on the Sunday of his father's death,they had an altercation, and that he had felt so badlyabout it that he had called home from a gas station onthe way to college, only to be told that father hadcollapsed and died soon after the patient had left. Thislast version was later verified by the patient's motherand older brother when eventually he was able to dis-cuss with them the events surrounding the death.

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [G

    azi U

    nivers

    ity] a

    t 22:5

    4 18 A

    ugus

    t 201

    4

  • 164

    The first two versions of the memory of eventsdiminished unpleasure by distorting the events. Thethird recollection, insofar as it is closer to the actualevents, could be recalled because much of what in hisrelationship to his father had been painful to him hadbeen diminished.

    This tendentious nature of memory distortion andalteration may, I think, have some bearing in under-standing confabulation. It also points to a potentialavenue of research, namely, can methods of investiga-tion be devised to prove or disprove this basic psycho-analytic assertion? And, if found to be valid, at whatlevel of brain dysfunction (functional or physical innature) does the principle no longer apply?

    From a psychological and psychoanalytical pointof view, the pleasure principle may be somewhat over-ridden in cases of severe (and specially sustained)trauma, such as those seen in wars. These conditions,currently diagnosed under the rubric of posttraumaticstress disorder (PTSD), offer a unique opportunity toobserve the effect of trauma on the mind-brain, andresearch in the group of patients suffering from PTSDmay help elucidate the limits of the pleasure principle.It is, in fact, through his study of war neurosis duringthe First World War that Freud came to the conclusionthat mastery of the trauma, through a repetition of thememories in the present (flashback), took precedenceover the pleasure principle. Given that an unexpectedstroke or a sudden ruptured aneurysm can be safelyassumed to be traumatic for the mental apparatus, itmay be interesting to explore the effect of these partic-ular traumas on memory and the executive functiondisorders that ensue.

    Another area of psychoanalytic work that per-tains to the subject of confabulation is that of "screenmemories," first described by Freud and later elabo-rated upon by Fenichel (1927), Greenacre (1949), andLoftus (1980) among others. Neuropsychologists usethe term observer memories to describe one character-istic of such recollections. The person rememberingsees himself or herself as observing the scene, whichdistinguishes the memories from field memories(Schacter, 1984). While such memories can be wovenaround adult experiences, psychoanalytic interest hasbeen primarily focused on the recollection of adultsabout their childhood. Typically, such memories aredated by the person recalling them as occurring be-tween the ages of 5 and 8. Screen memories havecertain particular qualities: they are regular scenesworked out in plastic form, they can be compared torepresentations on the stage, the person rememberingalways sees (watches) himself or herself as a child in

    Edward Nersessian

    the scene, there is usually a quality of distinctness andclarity, at times even of luminosity to these scenes,and when explored, there are always some elementsof the scene that are either impossible or different fromwhat the person knows to be true. These inconsisten-cies in the memory are not spontaneously recognizedby the person but are readily acknowledged whenbrought to their attention. For example, the windowin a scene may be different from where it actually is,or a picture might be hanging from a wall where, infact, a window is located. There are also alterationsin terms of time. For example, an older brother mayappear in the memory as much younger than he couldpossibly have been. One such memory, for example,involved a patient seeing himself watching his motherbeing taken by a stretcher to the hospital because shewas having a miscarriage. When during his psycho-analysis he asked his mother about this event, she toldhim that though she did indeed have a miscarriage, ithappened before he was born, and she was not takento the hospital on a stretcher.

    The alterations in these memories have some ofthe features that Solms describes in his commentaryin the present issue regarding primary and secondaryprocess and conscious and unconscious systems.Freud understood these memories as screening or cov-ering other more emotionally salient or even traumaticevents. The screen, then, is an amalgam of some aspectof the event and other more mundane and affectivelyneutral events, and also, importantly, fantasies. Inother words, such a memory, which in fact is totallyfictitious in the shape it is remembered, refers to actualevents but also to fantasies that can only be discoveredthrough the analytic method. Thus some real events,some fantasies, and some elements of a possibly trau-matic event combine to create a memory which, de-spite its easily discoverable inherent contradictions, isheld by the patient as an actual series of events. Infact, in a good number of cases, the individuals arerather insistent that the memory is accurate and quitereluctant to submit it to the process of analysis. Whatgives rise to this reluctance is no different from whatoriginally contributed to the formation of the memory,namely the pleasure-unpleasure principle.

    Another area of interest, and one that remainscontroversial, is the fate of the original memory andwhether it remains unaltered, with other variants justbeing added to it. Freud believed that memory tracespersisted forever and that under the right conditions,that is to say, with the lifting of repression, they couldbe recalled or in some instances, affectively relived.Given the fact that past and present events are occa-

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [G

    azi U

    nivers

    ity] a

    t 22:5

    4 18 A

    ugus

    t 201

    4

  • Confabulation

    sionally combined to alter memories both in normalindividuals and in patients with the kinds of brain in-jury DeLuca discusses, this issue is also relevant toconfabulation. In other words, once patients are nolonger confabulating, are they capable of remember-ing the events that occurred at the time of their illnesswhich they could not remember while still confabulat-ing? This could be particularly interesting in regard tothe tests DeLuca's patients were given; for example,how much of the stories they were told in a test situa-tion could they remember after recovery?

    What I have done in this brief and highly incom-plete excursion into the complex area of memory andpsychoanalytic notions about memory is to try to un-derscore that for psychoanalysts a significant part ofwhat happens when memories are altered, which isinevitable, is that there is a motive behind their distor-tion and that the motive stems from the requirementof the mental apparatus to decrease unpleasure andoptimize pleasure. Furthermore, I have tried to showthat this tendentious nature of memory is so prevalentthat the person is not aware of the distortion and notinfrequently resists any attempts to correct it. In otherwords, in the normal, not brain-injured individual, thefunctions that evaluate the accuracy of the memory,the time period in which it occurred, whether it ismemory or fantasy, whether it is one event or twoor three events condensed into one, do not performperfectly as they would in a machine or a computer;rather, they perform imperfectly to satisfy other moreimportant exigencies of the individual and the mind.

    I think all the phenomena described above fallwithin DeLuca's broad sense confabulation. Fromwhat has been said above, it can be concluded that atone end, broad sense confabulation is the natural stateof things, since the mental apparatus is constantly al-tering facts to make sure that affects are regulatedwithin an optimal range, though broad sense involves awhole range from somewhat altered to unrecognizablyaltered. Incidentally, Gazzaniga's Interpreter (1998)and the kind of confabulatory rationalizations offeredafter posthypnotic suggestion do not represent contra-dictions to psychoanalytic understanding.

    In the usual situation of psychoanalytic workwith patients whose brain is intact (see Kaplan-Solmsand Solms's work with patients who have sustainedbrain damage; Kaplan-Solms and Solms, 2000) andwhere no massive trauma has occurred, the pleasureprinciple holds, but what about cases where brain in-tegrity is compromised? In other words what aboutnarrow sense confabulation? Do the basic regulatorymechanisms of the mind continue to operate, but op-

    165

    erating on and with functions that are to a greater andlesser degree damaged? Or, are the regulatory mecha-nisms themselves to a greater or lesser degree im-paired? The Solms' work would suggest that the basicregulatory principle remains and that whatever execu-tive functions are intact attempt to prevent unpleasureeven at the cost of a denial of reality. Whether thedenial of reality is for the purpose of affect regulationor is itself a consequence of the underlying pathologi-cal condition, is an interesting question and one thatcould be a subject of an investigation, possibly leadingto a better delineation of the underlying physicaldamage.

    Additionally, while thinking of confabulation inthe broad sense may be crucial in recognizing themechanisms common to all confabulation, as well asuseful in directing research toward finding the cerebralcorrelates for certain executive functions, it is of lim-ited value in the clinical setting where diagnostic is-sues are more pressing. Here, it is the notion of narrowsense confabulation with more specific characteristicsthat is helpful. In one Korsakoff patient I saw manyyears ago, the distinctive feature was his telling anentirely different story when he was asked the samequestion after a relatively brief interval. Such is, ofcourse, not the case with the everyday variety of con-fabulation I focused on above, nor is it the case withdelusions seen in paranoia or certain schizophrenias.An intermediate state may be provided by cases ofpseudologia fantastica, where the patient's storieskeep constantly changing and where clearly not all theevents have a basis in reality. With the advent of mod-ern methods of studying brain function (PET, fMRI,etc.) pseudologia fantastica may provide importantclues regarding confabulation.

    The distinction between broad sense and narrowsense confabulation does help to narrow the field ofstudy. Nevertheless, a problem of definition continuesto persist and judicious dissection of all the phenom-ena currently collected under the rubric of confabula-tion is in order. The fixed nature of someconfabulations versus the variability of a confabula-tion from one moment or hour or day to the next, theseverity or bizarre quality of the distortion, the tempo-ral alteration in only some cases, the rigid adherenceto the distorted memory despite all evidence to thecontrary, as in the case of the man with a dead friendmentioned in Solms's target discussion, even the ab-sence of confabulation in some amnesia where theperson recognizes his inability to remember-all theseneed further study and careful delineation. The psy-choanalytic perspective offers a way of understanding

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [G

    azi U

    nivers

    ity] a

    t 22:5

    4 18 A

    ugus

    t 201

    4

  • 166

    the content and the form of distortions, but simultane-ously points to the need for a better understandingof the nature of specific executive dysfunction, or inDeLuca's words, the "cognitive-perceptual disorderin confabulation."

    Finally, I would like to end this brief commentaryon DeLuca's very clear delineation of the pertinentissues in confabulation, with a quote from David Ra-paport (1951). In a paper entitled "States of Con-sciousness," Rapaport compares and contrasts threesets of phenomena: fugue states with loss of personalidentity; dreams, hypnogogic reverie, and daydreams;and Korsakoff s syndrome. In doing so, he usesFreud's speculation about the early development ofthe mind and describes the distinctions between pri-mary and secondary process reviewed in this issue byMark Solms in his commentary. He then concludeswith the following:

    The gradual development from thought as "hallucina-tory gratification" to thought as "experimental ac-tion" reflects the gradual development frommonoideic consciousness of the drive gratification topolydideic consciousness of the relation of perceivedexternal reality, internal need, and memories of pastexperiences. The gradual development corresponds tovarieties or forms of consciousness in which variousbalances are struck between perception of internaland external reality, in which internal experience isto various (ever-decreasing) degrees experienced asexternal reality, and in which internal and externalperception (thought and perception of reality) are dif-ferentiated with increasing clarity. Correspondingly,the thought forms consciously experienced changefrom prelogical to logical, from syncretic to abstract,from idiosyncratic to socialized. When thought hasreached the differentiation where it appears as experi-mental action, exploring reality for the safest and mostfeasible path toward gratification, it has attained acomplex organization of safeguards guaranteeing acorrect appraisal of reality and a sharp distinction ofwish and reality, certainty and uncertainty, etc. It isthis complex organization that is reflected in thosevarieties of conscious experience which I have de-scribed above with the Korsakoff syndrome, in whichthese safeguards are to a considerable extent put outof action by the pathological process [po 402].

    Edward Nersessian

    The forward development in judgment, realitytesting, differentiation between internal and externalperception, change in thinking from prelogical to logi-cal and from syncretic to abstract that occurs in child-hood development, are all to a greater or lesser degreereversed (last in, first out hypothesis; Schacter, 1984)in the brain-damaged patients DeLuca describes, withconfabulation as only one manifestation of this gen-eral reversal.

    References

    Fenichel, O. (1927), The economic function of screen mem-ories. Collected Papers, Vol. 1. New York: W. W. Nor-ton, 1953, pp. 113-116.

    Gazzaniga, M. S. (1998), The Mind's Past. Berkeley: Uni-versity of California Press.

    Greenacre, P. (1949), A contribution to the study of screenmemories. The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child,3:73-84. New York: International Universities Press.

    Hall, D. F., & Loftus, E. F. (1986), The fate of memory:Discoverable or doomed? In: Neuropsychology ofMem-ory, ed. L. R. Squire & N. Butters. New York: GuilfordPress, pp. 25-32.

    Kaplan-Solms, K., & Solms, M. (2000), Clinical Studies inNeuro-Psychoanalysis. Madison, CT: International Uni-versities Press.

    Kris, E. (1956), Recovery of childhood memories. In: TheSelected Papers of Ernst Kris. New Haven, CT: YaleUniversity Press, 1975, pp. 301-340.

    Loftus, E. F. (1980), Memory: Surprising New Insights intoHow We Remember and Why We Forget. Reading, MA:Addison-Wesley.

    Rapaport, D. (1951), States of consciousness. In: The Col-lected Papers of David Rapaport, ed. M. M. Gill. NewYork: Basic Books, 1966, pp. 385-404.

    Schacter, D. L. (1984), Toward the multidisciplinary studyof memory: Ontogeny, phylogeny, and pathology ofmemory systems. In: Neuropsychology of Memory, ed.L. R. Squire & N. Butters. New York: Guilford Press,pp. 13-24.

    Edward Nersessian72 East 91st StreetNew York, NY 10128e-mail: [email protected]

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [G

    azi U

    nivers

    ity] a

    t 22:5

    4 18 A

    ugus

    t 201

    4