354
70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    10

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Programming + Microprocessors ≡ Superpower!

What are your super powerful programs/processors doing?Logic and Proofs!Induction ≡ Recursion.

What can computers do?Work with discrete objects.Discrete Math =⇒ immense application.

Computers learn and interact with the world?E.g. machine learning, data analysis, robotics, ...Probability!

Page 2: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Programming + Microprocessors ≡ Superpower!

What are your super powerful programs/processors doing?Logic and Proofs!Induction ≡ Recursion.

What can computers do?Work with discrete objects.Discrete Math =⇒ immense application.

Computers learn and interact with the world?E.g. machine learning, data analysis, robotics, ...Probability!

Page 3: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

My hopes and dreams.

We teach you to think more clearly and more powerfully.

..And to deal clearly with uncertainty itself.

Page 4: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

My hopes and dreams.

We teach you to think more clearly and more powerfully.

..And to deal clearly with uncertainty itself.

Page 5: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Probability Unit

• How can we predict unknown future events (e.g., gambling profit, next week rainfall, traffic congestion, …)?

– Constructive Models: Model the overall system (including the sources of uncertainty). For modeling uncertainty, we’ll develop probabilistic models and techniques for

analyzing them.

– Deductive Models: Extract the “trend” from the previous outcomes (e.g., linear regression).

Page 6: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 7: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 8: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.

midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 9: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 10: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 11: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions

=⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 12: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:

Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 13: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 14: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 15: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.

Read it!!!!Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 16: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!

Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 17: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Admin

Course Webpage: http://www.eecs70.org/

Explains policies, has office hours, homework, midterm dates, etc.

One midterm, final.midterm.

Questions =⇒ piazza:Logistics, etc.Content Support: other students!

Plus Piazza hours.

Weekly Post.

It’s weekly.Read it!!!!

Announcements, logistics, critical advice.

Page 18: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 19: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 20: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:

“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 21: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 22: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 23: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 24: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 25: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer:

Later.

Page 26: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Wason’s experiment:1

Suppose we have four cards on a table:

I 1st about Alice, 2nd about Bob, 3rd Charlie, 4th Donna.

I Card contains person’s destination on one side,and mode of travel.

I Consider the theory:“If a person travels to Chicago, they flies.”

I Suppose you see that Alice went to Baltimore, Bob drove,Charlie went to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Alice

Baltimore

Bob

drove

Charlie

Chicago

Donna

flew

I Which cards must you flip to test the theory?

Answer: Later.

Page 27: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

CS70: Lecture 1. Outline.

Today: Note 1.

Note 0 is background. Do read it.

The language of proofs!

1. Propositions.

2. Propositional Forms.

3. Implication.

4. Truth Tables

5. Quantifiers

6. More De Morgan’s Laws

Page 28: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

CS70: Lecture 1. Outline.

Today: Note 1. Note 0 is background.

Do read it.

The language of proofs!

1. Propositions.

2. Propositional Forms.

3. Implication.

4. Truth Tables

5. Quantifiers

6. More De Morgan’s Laws

Page 29: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

CS70: Lecture 1. Outline.

Today: Note 1. Note 0 is background. Do read it.

The language of proofs!

1. Propositions.

2. Propositional Forms.

3. Implication.

4. Truth Tables

5. Quantifiers

6. More De Morgan’s Laws

Page 30: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

CS70: Lecture 1. Outline.

Today: Note 1. Note 0 is background. Do read it.

The language of proofs!

1. Propositions.

2. Propositional Forms.

3. Implication.

4. Truth Tables

5. Quantifiers

6. More De Morgan’s Laws

Page 31: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

CS70: Lecture 1. Outline.

Today: Note 1. Note 0 is background. Do read it.

The language of proofs!

1. Propositions.

2. Propositional Forms.

3. Implication.

4. Truth Tables

5. Quantifiers

6. More De Morgan’s Laws

Page 32: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational

Proposition True

2+2 = 4

Proposition True

2+2 = 3

Proposition False

826th digit of pi is 4

Proposition False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 33: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition

True

2+2 = 4

Proposition True

2+2 = 3

Proposition False

826th digit of pi is 4

Proposition False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 34: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4

Proposition True

2+2 = 3

Proposition False

826th digit of pi is 4

Proposition False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 35: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition

True

2+2 = 3

Proposition False

826th digit of pi is 4

Proposition False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 36: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3

Proposition False

826th digit of pi is 4

Proposition False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 37: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition

False

826th digit of pi is 4

Proposition False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 38: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4

Proposition False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 39: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition

False

Johnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 40: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor

Not Proposition

Any even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 41: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes

Proposition False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 42: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition

False

4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 43: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5

Not Proposition.

x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 44: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x

Not a Proposition.

Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 45: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago

Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 46: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago Proposition.

FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 47: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago Proposition. False

I love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 48: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago Proposition. FalseI love you.

Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 49: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm.

Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 50: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm.

Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ...

True or False

Page 51: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm.

Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ... True or False

Page 52: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositions: Statements that are true or false.

√2 is irrational Proposition True

2+2 = 4 Proposition True2+2 = 3 Proposition False826th digit of pi is 4 Proposition FalseJohnny Depp is a good actor Not PropositionAny even > 2 is sum of 2 primes Proposition False4+5 Not Proposition.x +x Not a Proposition.Alice travelled to Chicago Proposition. FalseI love you. Hmmm. Its complicated.

Again: “value” of a proposition is ... True or False

Page 53: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 54: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 55: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True .

Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 56: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 57: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 58: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 59: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 60: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False .

Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 61: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 62: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 63: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ...

False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 64: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 65: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ...

False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 66: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 67: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ...

True

Page 68: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 69: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Propositional Forms.

Put propositions together to make another...

Conjunction (“and”): P ∧Q

“P ∧Q” is True when both P and Q are True . Else False .

Disjunction (“or”): P ∨Q

“P ∨Q” is True when at least one P or Q is True . Else False .

Negation (“not”): ¬P

“¬P” is True when P is False . Else False .

Examples:

¬ “(2+2 = 4)” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∧ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... False

“2+2 = 3”∨ “2+2 = 4” – a proposition that is ... True

Page 70: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.

P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 71: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.

....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 72: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 73: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 74: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 75: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?

Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 76: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 77: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 78: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...

complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 79: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 80: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 81: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Put them together..

Propositions:P1 - Person 1 rides the bus.P2 - Person 2 rides the bus.....

But we can’t have either of the following happen; That either person 1or person 2 ride the bus and person 3 or 4 ride the bus. Or thatperson 2 or person 3 ride the bus and that either person 4 rides thebus or person 5 doesn’t.

Propositional Form:¬(((P1∨P2)∧ (P3∨P4))∨ ((P2∨P3)∧ (P4∨¬P5)))

Can person 3 ride the bus?Can person 3 and person 4 ride the bus together?

This seems ...complicated.

We can program!!!!

We need a way to keep track!

Page 82: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F

F

F T

F

F F

F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T

T

T F

T

F T

T

F F

F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 83: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T

F

F F

F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T

T

T F

T

F T

T

F F

F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 84: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F

F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T

T

T F

T

F T

T

F F

F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 85: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T

T

T F

T

F T

T

F F

F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 86: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T

T

T F

T

F T

T

F F

FCheck: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.

One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 87: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F

T

F T

T

F F

FCheck: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.

One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 88: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T

T

F F

FCheck: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.

One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 89: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 90: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.

One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 91: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!

Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 92: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q.

Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 93: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same

TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 94: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T

F F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 95: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F

F

T F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 96: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F

F F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 97: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F

F

F T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 98: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T

F F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 99: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F

F

F F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 100: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F FF F

T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 101: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F FF F T

T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 102: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F FF F T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 103: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F FF F T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q)

≡ ¬P ∨¬Q ¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 104: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F FF F T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q) ≡ ¬P ∨¬Q

¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 105: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F FF F T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q) ≡ ¬P ∨¬Q ¬(P ∨Q)

≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 106: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Tables for Propositional Forms.“P ∧Q” is True when

both P and Q are True .

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

“P ∨Q” is True when≥ one of P or Q is True .

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Check: ∧ and ∨ are commutative.One use for truth tables: Logical Equivalence of propositional forms!Example: ¬(P ∧Q) logically equivalent to ¬P ∨¬Q. Same TruthTable!

P Q ¬(P ∨Q) ¬P ∧¬QT T F FT F F FF T F FF F T T

DeMorgan’s Law’s for Negation: distribute and flip!

¬(P ∧Q) ≡ ¬P ∨¬Q ¬(P ∨Q) ≡ ¬P ∧¬Q

Page 107: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 108: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q?

Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 109: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes?

No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 110: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 111: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes!

Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 112: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 113: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)?

F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 114: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 115: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)?

T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 116: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 117: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)?

Q

Page 118: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quick Questions

P Q P ∧QT T TT F FF T FF F F

P Q P ∨QT T TT F TF T TF F F

Is (T ∧Q)≡Q? Yes? No?

Yes! Look at rows in truth table for P = T .

What is (F ∧Q)? F or False.

What is (T ∨Q)? T

What is (F ∨Q)? Q

Page 119: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 120: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q,

(F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 121: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 122: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)

≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 123: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).

RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).P is False .

LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 124: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)

≡ (Q∨R).P is False .

LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 125: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 126: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .

LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 127: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)

≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 128: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .

RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 129: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)

≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 130: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )

≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 131: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 132: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 133: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 134: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T ,

F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 135: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 136: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:

(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 137: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 138: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:

(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 139: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Distributive?

P ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (P ∧Q)∨ (P ∧R)?

Simplify: (T ∧Q)≡Q, (F ∧Q)≡ F .

Cases:P is True .

LHS: T ∧ (Q∨R)≡ (Q∨R).RHS: (T ∧Q)∨ (T ∧R)≡ (Q∨R).

P is False .LHS: F ∧ (Q∨R)≡ F .RHS: (F ∧Q)∨ (F ∧R)≡ (F ∨F )≡ F .

P ∨ (Q∧R)≡ (P ∨Q)∧ (P ∨R)?

Simplify: T ∨Q ≡ T , F ∨Q ≡Q. ...

Foil 1:(A∨B)∧ (C∨D)≡ (A∧C)∨ (A∧D)∨ (B∧C)∨ (B∧D)?

Foil 2:(A∧B)∨ (C∧D)≡ (A∨C)∧ (A∨D)∧ (B∨C)∧ (B∨D)?

Page 140: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 141: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 142: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 143: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.

Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 144: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 145: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 146: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.

P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 147: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”

Q = “you will get wet”Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 148: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 149: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”

Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 150: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 151: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 152: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,

Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 153: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication.

P =⇒ Q interpreted as

If P, then Q.

True Statements: P, P =⇒ Q.Conclude: Q is true.

Examples:

Statement: If you stand in the rain, then you’ll get wet.P = “you stand in the rain”Q = “you will get wet”

Statement: “Stand in the rain”Can conclude: “you’ll get wet.”

Statement:If a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c, then a2 +b2 = c2.

P = “a right triangle has sidelengths a≤ b ≤ c”,Q = “a2 +b2 = c2”.

Page 154: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 155: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 156: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothing

P False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 157: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means

Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 158: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True

or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 159: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or False

Anything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 160: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.

P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 161: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when

Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 162: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 163: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.

If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 164: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 165: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 166: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 167: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 168: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:

P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 169: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 170: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river.

Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 171: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 172: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 173: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?

((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 174: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Non-Consequences/consequences of ImplicationThe statement “P =⇒ Q”

only is False if P is True and Q is False .

False implies nothingP False means Q can be True or FalseAnything implies true.P can be True or False when Q is True

If chemical plant pollutes river, fish die.If fish die, did chemical plant pollute river?

Not necessarily.

P =⇒ Q and Q are True does not mean P is True

Be careful!

Instead we have:P =⇒ Q and P are True does mean Q is True .

The chemical plant pollutes river. Can we conclude fish die?

Some Fun: use propositional formulas to describe implication?((P =⇒ Q)∧P) =⇒ Q.

Page 175: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 176: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 177: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 178: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.

Remember if P is true then Q must be true.this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 179: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 180: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.

since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 181: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 182: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.

This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 183: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows you

to conclude that Q is true.Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 184: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 185: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 186: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 187: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Implication and English.P =⇒ QPoll.

I If P, then Q.

I Q if P.Just reversing the order.

I P only if Q.Remember if P is true then Q must be true.

this suggests that P can only be true if Q is true.since if Q is false P must have been false.

I P is sufficient for Q.This means that proving P allows youto conclude that Q is true.

Example: Showing n > 4 is sufficient for showing n > 3.

I Q is necessary for P.For P to be true it is necessary that Q is true.Or if Q is false then we know that P is false.

Example: It is necessary that n > 3 for n > 4.

Page 188: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F

F

F T

T

F F

T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T

T

T F

F

F T

T

F F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 189: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T

T

F F

T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T

T

T F

F

F T

T

F F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 190: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F

T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T

T

T F

F

F T

T

F F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 191: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T

T

T F

F

F T

T

F F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 192: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T

T

T F

F

F T

T

F F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 193: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T TT F

F

F T

T

F F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 194: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T TT F FF T

T

F F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 195: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T TT F FF T TF F

T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 196: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T TT F FF T TF F T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 197: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T TT F FF T TF F T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 198: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Truth Table: implication.

P Q P =⇒ QT T TT F FF T TF F T

P Q ¬P ∨QT T TT F FF T TF F T

¬P ∨Q ≡ P =⇒ Q.

These two propositional forms are logically equivalent!

Page 199: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 200: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.

I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 201: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 202: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 203: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.

I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 204: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 205: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.

(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 206: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.

(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 207: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 208: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.

P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 209: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q

≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 210: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q

≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 211: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P

≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 212: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 213: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.

If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 214: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!)

converse!

I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.

Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 215: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!) converse!I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.

(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.

Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 216: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!) converse!I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.

(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 217: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Contrapositive, ConverseI Contrapositive of P =⇒ Q is ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I If the plant pollutes, fish die.I If the fish don’t die, the plant does not pollute.

(contrapositive)

I If you stand in the rain, you get wet.I If you did not stand in the rain, you did not get wet.

(not contrapositive!) converse!I If you did not get wet, you did not stand in the rain.

(contrapositive.)

Logically equivalent! Notation: ≡.P =⇒ Q ≡ ¬P ∨Q ≡ ¬(¬Q)∨¬P ≡ ¬Q =⇒ ¬P.

I Converse of P =⇒ Q is Q =⇒ P.If fish die the plant pollutes.Not logically equivalent!

I Definition: If P =⇒ Q and Q =⇒ P is P if and only if Q orP ⇐⇒ Q.(Logically Equivalent: ⇐⇒ . )

Page 218: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 219: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 220: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 221: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No.

They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 222: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 223: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”

Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 224: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 225: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 226: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 227: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 228: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”

C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 229: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 230: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x).

Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 231: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.

If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 232: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 233: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next:

Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 234: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Variables.Propositions?

I ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .

I x > 2

I n is even and the sum of two primes

No. They have a free variable.

We call them predicates, e.g., Q(x) = “x is even”Same as boolean valued functions from 61A!

I P(n) = “∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

I R(x) = “x > 2”

I G(n) = “n is even and the sum of two primes”

I Remember Wason’s experiment!F (x) = “Person x flew.”C(x) = “Person x went to Chicago

I C(x) =⇒ F (x). Theory from Wason’s.If person x goes to Chicago then person x flew.

Next: Statements about boolean valued functions!!

Page 235: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 236: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 237: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 238: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)

∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 239: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)

∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 240: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)

∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 241: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”

Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 242: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 243: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 244: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 245: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 246: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 247: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 248: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 249: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait!

What is N?

Page 250: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..There exists quantifier:

(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) means “There exists an x in S where P(x) is true.”

For example:(∃x ∈ N)(x = x2)

Equivalent to “(0 = 0)∨ (1 = 1)∨ (2 = 4)∨ . . .”Much shorter to use a quantifier!

For all quantifier;(∀x ∈ S) (P(x)). means “For all x in S, P(x) is True .”

Examples:

“Adding 1 makes a bigger number.”

(∀x ∈ N) (x +1 > x)

”the square of a number is always non-negative”

(∀x ∈ N)(x2 >= 0)

Wait! What is N?

Page 251: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers: universes.

Proposition: “For all natural numbers n, ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

Proposition has universe:

“the natural numbers”.

Universe examples include..

I N= {0,1, . . .} (natural numbers).

I Z= {. . . ,−1,0, . . .} (integers)

I Z+ (positive integers)

I R (real numbers)

I Any set: S = {Alice,Bob,Charlie,Donna}.I See note 0 for more!

Other proposition notation(for discussion):“d |n” means d divides n

or ∃k ∈ Z,n = kd .2|4? True.4|2? False.

Page 252: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers: universes.

Proposition: “For all natural numbers n, ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

Proposition has universe: “the natural numbers”.

Universe examples include..

I N= {0,1, . . .} (natural numbers).

I Z= {. . . ,−1,0, . . .} (integers)

I Z+ (positive integers)

I R (real numbers)

I Any set: S = {Alice,Bob,Charlie,Donna}.I See note 0 for more!

Other proposition notation(for discussion):“d |n” means d divides n

or ∃k ∈ Z,n = kd .2|4? True.4|2? False.

Page 253: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers: universes.

Proposition: “For all natural numbers n, ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

Proposition has universe: “the natural numbers”.

Universe examples include..

I N= {0,1, . . .} (natural numbers).

I Z= {. . . ,−1,0, . . .} (integers)

I Z+ (positive integers)

I R (real numbers)

I Any set: S = {Alice,Bob,Charlie,Donna}.I See note 0 for more!

Other proposition notation(for discussion):“d |n” means d divides n

or ∃k ∈ Z,n = kd .2|4? True.4|2? False.

Page 254: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers: universes.

Proposition: “For all natural numbers n, ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

Proposition has universe: “the natural numbers”.

Universe examples include..

I N= {0,1, . . .} (natural numbers).

I Z= {. . . ,−1,0, . . .} (integers)

I Z+ (positive integers)

I R (real numbers)

I Any set: S = {Alice,Bob,Charlie,Donna}.I See note 0 for more!

Other proposition notation(for discussion):“d |n” means d divides n

or ∃k ∈ Z,n = kd .2|4?

True.4|2? False.

Page 255: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers: universes.

Proposition: “For all natural numbers n, ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

Proposition has universe: “the natural numbers”.

Universe examples include..

I N= {0,1, . . .} (natural numbers).

I Z= {. . . ,−1,0, . . .} (integers)

I Z+ (positive integers)

I R (real numbers)

I Any set: S = {Alice,Bob,Charlie,Donna}.I See note 0 for more!

Other proposition notation(for discussion):“d |n” means d divides n

or ∃k ∈ Z,n = kd .2|4? True.

4|2? False.

Page 256: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers: universes.

Proposition: “For all natural numbers n, ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

Proposition has universe: “the natural numbers”.

Universe examples include..

I N= {0,1, . . .} (natural numbers).

I Z= {. . . ,−1,0, . . .} (integers)

I Z+ (positive integers)

I R (real numbers)

I Any set: S = {Alice,Bob,Charlie,Donna}.I See note 0 for more!

Other proposition notation(for discussion):“d |n” means d divides n

or ∃k ∈ Z,n = kd .2|4? True.4|2?

False.

Page 257: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers: universes.

Proposition: “For all natural numbers n, ∑ni=1 i = n(n+1)

2 .”

Proposition has universe: “the natural numbers”.

Universe examples include..

I N= {0,1, . . .} (natural numbers).

I Z= {. . . ,−1,0, . . .} (integers)

I Z+ (positive integers)

I R (real numbers)

I Any set: S = {Alice,Bob,Charlie,Donna}.I See note 0 for more!

Other proposition notation(for discussion):“d |n” means d divides n

or ∃k ∈ Z,n = kd .2|4? True.4|2? False.

Page 258: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory:

“If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 259: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 260: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 261: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 262: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.”

Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 263: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 264: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x)

=⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 265: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 266: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False .

Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 267: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?

No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 268: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No.

Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 269: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 270: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False .

Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 271: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?

Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 272: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes.

Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 273: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B)

≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 274: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 275: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 276: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True .

Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 277: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?

Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 278: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes.

Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 279: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 280: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True .

Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 281: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?

No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 282: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No.

Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 283: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 284: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Back to: Wason’s experiment:1Theory: “If a person travels to Chicago, he/she flies.”

Alice to Baltimore, Bob drove, Charlie to Chicago, and Donna flew.

Which cards do you need to flip to test the theory?

Chicago(x) = “x went to Chicago.” Flew(x) = “x flew”

Statement/theory: ∀x ∈ {A,B,C,D},Chicago(x) =⇒ Flew(x)

Chicago(A) = False . Do we care about Flew(A)?No. Chicago(A) =⇒ Flew(A) is true.

since Chicago(A) is False ,

Flew(B) = False . Do we care about Chicago(B)?Yes. Chicago(B) =⇒ Flew(B) ≡ ¬Flew(B) =⇒ ¬Chicago(B).

So Chicago(Bob) must be False .

Chicago(C) = True . Do we care about Flew(C)?Yes. Chicago(C) =⇒ Flew(C) means Flew(C) must be true.

Flew(D) = True . Do we care about Chicago(D)?No. Chicago(D) =⇒ Flew(D) is true when Flew(D) is true.

Only have to turn over cards for Bob and Charlie.

Page 285: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 286: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 287: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x)

False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 288: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False

Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 289: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 290: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 291: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x)

True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 292: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 293: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 294: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)

(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 295: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5

=⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 296: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒

x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 297: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 298: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert:

Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 299: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 300: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

More for all quantifiers examples.

I “doubling a number always makes it larger”

(∀x ∈ N) (2x > x) False Consider x = 0

Can fix statement...

(∀x ∈ N) (2x≥x) True

I “Square of any natural number greater than 5 is greater than 25.”

(∀x ∈ N)(x > 5 =⇒ x2 > 25).

Idea alert: Restrict domain using implication.

Later we may omit universe if clear from context.

Page 301: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 302: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N)

(∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 303: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N)

(y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 304: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2)

False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 305: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 306: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 307: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)

(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 308: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N)

(y = x2) True

Page 309: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2)

True

Page 310: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 311: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers..not commutative.

I In English: “there is a natural number that is the square of everynatural number”.

(∃y ∈ N) (∀x ∈ N) (y = x2) False

I In English: “the square of every natural number is a naturalnumber.”

(∀x ∈ N)(∃y ∈ N) (y = x2) True

Page 312: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 313: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 314: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,

¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 315: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 316: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 317: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x)

“For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 318: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”

For False , find x , where ¬P(x).Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 319: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 320: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.

Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 321: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.

Case that illustrates bug.For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 322: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 323: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim.

Next lectures...

Page 324: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Quantifiers....negation...DeMorgan again.

Consider¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)),

English: there is an x in S where P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∀x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∃(x ∈ S)(¬P(x)).

What we do in this course! We consider claims.

Claim: (∀x) P(x) “For all inputs x the program works.”For False , find x , where ¬P(x).

Counterexample.Bad input.Case that illustrates bug.

For True : prove claim. Next lectures...

Page 325: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Negation of exists.

Consider

¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x))

English: means that there is no x ∈ S where P(x) is true. English:means that for all x ∈ S, P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∀(x ∈ S)¬P(x).

Page 326: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Negation of exists.

Consider

¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x))

English: means that there is no x ∈ S where P(x) is true. English:means that for all x ∈ S, P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∀(x ∈ S)¬P(x).

Page 327: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Negation of exists.

Consider

¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x))

English: means that there is no x ∈ S where P(x) is true.

English:means that for all x ∈ S, P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∀(x ∈ S)¬P(x).

Page 328: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Negation of exists.

Consider

¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x))

English: means that there is no x ∈ S where P(x) is true. English:means that for all x ∈ S, P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∀(x ∈ S)¬P(x).

Page 329: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Negation of exists.

Consider

¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x))

English: means that there is no x ∈ S where P(x) is true. English:means that for all x ∈ S, P(x) does not hold.

That is,¬(∃x ∈ S)(P(x)) ⇐⇒ ∀(x ∈ S)¬P(x).

Page 330: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 331: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 332: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 333: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 334: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 335: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 336: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:

Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 337: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Which Theorem?

Theorem: (∀n ∈ N) ¬(∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Which Theorem?

Fermat’s Last Theorem!

Remember Special Triangles: for n = 2, we have 3,4,5 and 5,7, 12and ...

1637: Proof doesn’t fit in the margins.

1993: Wiles ...(based in part on Ribet’s Theorem)

DeMorgan Restatement:Theorem: ¬(∃n ∈ N) (∃a,b,c ∈ N) (n ≥ 3 =⇒ an +bn = cn)

Page 338: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 339: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 340: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 341: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 342: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q

⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 343: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 344: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬P

Converse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 345: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 346: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 347: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 348: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems!

And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 349: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 350: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”

¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 351: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒

(¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 352: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒

∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 353: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!

Page 354: 70: Discrete Math and Probability Theory

Summary.Propositions are statements that are true or false.

Proprositional forms use ∧,∨,¬.

Propositional forms correspond to truth tables.

Logical equivalence of forms means same truth tables.

Implication: P =⇒ Q ⇐⇒ ¬P ∨Q.

Contrapositive: ¬Q =⇒ ¬PConverse: Q =⇒ P

Predicates: Statements with “free” variables.

Quantifiers: ∀x P(x), ∃y Q(y)

Now can state theorems! And disprove false ones!

DeMorgans Laws: “Flip and Distribute negation”¬(P ∨Q) ⇐⇒ (¬P ∧¬Q)¬∀x P(x) ⇐⇒ ∃x ¬P(x).

Next Time: proofs!