39
Rules, Games, and the Axiological Foundations of (International) Criminal Law Leo Zaibert When compared to domestic legal systems, international law, in general, has often been perceived as somewhat of a second-class citizen. H. L. A. Hart’s skepticism as to the credentials of international law is as good an example as any. Famously, Hart believed that international law “lacks the secondary rules of change and adjudication which provide for legislature and courts” that are found in domestic law. 1 And many a Professor of Philosophy, Union College. Email: [email protected] . 1 H. L. A. Hart The Concept of Law, (2 nd ed.) Oxford: Oxford University Press (1994). Jeremy Waldron “International Law: A ‘Relatively Small and Unimportant’ Part of Jurisprudence?” in Reading HLA Hart’s The Concept of Law (Luis Duarte de Almeida, James Edwards, and Andrea Dolcetti, eds.) Oxford: Hart (2013): 209-226, at 214.

Rules, Games, and the Axiological Foundations of (International) Criminal Law

  • Upload
    union

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Rules, Games, and the Axiological Foundations of

(International) Criminal Law

Leo Zaibert

When compared to domestic legal systems,

international law, in general, has often been perceived

as somewhat of a second-class citizen. H. L. A. Hart’s

skepticism as to the credentials of international law is

as good an example as any. Famously, Hart believed that

international law “lacks the secondary rules of change

and adjudication which provide for legislature and

courts” that are found in domestic law.1 And many a Professor of Philosophy, Union College. Email:

[email protected].

1 H. L. A. Hart The Concept of Law, (2nd ed.) Oxford: Oxford

University Press (1994). Jeremy Waldron “International Law:

A ‘Relatively Small and Unimportant’ Part of Jurisprudence?”

in Reading HLA Hart’s The Concept of Law (Luis Duarte de

Almeida, James Edwards, and Andrea Dolcetti, eds.) Oxford:

Hart (2013): 209-226, at 214.

jurisprude working in Hart’s wake has uncritically

perpetuated Hart’s dismissal of international law.

Recently, Jeremy Waldron has criticized Hart’s

views, suggesting that they present “a frustrating

combination of insight and obtuseness”.2 Waldron is

particularly critical of an inference that allows Hart to

go from the alleged absence of secondary rules in

international law just mentioned to the conclusion that

international law is somewhat limited, somehow resembling

primitive, proto-legal arrangements:

The inference goes through if Hart is

interpreted as saying that international law

lacks exactly the kind of secondary rules of

change and adjudication that are required to set

up institutions exactly analogous to municipal 2 Jeremy Waldron “International Law: A ‘Relatively Small and

Unimportant’ Part of Jurisprudence?” in Reading HLA Hart’s

The Concept of Law (Luis Duarte de Almeida, James Edwards,

and Andrea Dolcetti, eds.) Oxford: Hart (2013): 209-226, at

214.

2

legislatures and courts. It will not go through

if it is supposed to imply that international

law lacks secondary rules of change and

adjudication of any kind. On the first reading

the inference is trivial. On the second reading,

the inference is fallacious, and egregiously

so.3

As shall become clear below, I agree with a great deal of

Waldron’s criticism

But I would like to focus attention on two problems

with positions such as Hart’s which Waldron sidesteps:

one general and one particular. The general problem

relates to what we have already seen: to a certain view

that could, only slightly uncharitably be dubbed rule

fetishism. Hart’s influential thesis whereby law comes

into existence when primary and secondary rules interact

is but one instance, albeit a conspicuous one, of this

general problem. Whether or not Waldron is correct that

3 Waldron, op. cit., 214.

3

Hart was guilty of a “grotesque”4 exaggerations in his

treatment of international law, there are other problems

with positions such as Hart’s, regarding which Waldron

himself appears to give too much of a free pass. This

“free pass” is the result of Waldron not really

questioning the appeal to rules: Waldron’s defense of

international law is that the mere fact that its

secondary rules differ from those of domestic law does

not entail that such secondary rules do not exist. But he

does not directly question the appeal to rules as such –

as I will do here.

The specific problem that I wish to discuss relates

to international criminal law in particular, be it in the

domestic or the international level. As I shall argue,

criminal law is itself fertile ground for a certain

narrowness of approach which includes a troubling form of

rule fetishism. Very briefly for now: this specific

problem is to see the criminal law as concerned with

4 Waldron, op. cit., 222.

4

particularly narrow understanding of what it is to

evaluate actions. I shall suggest that the future of

criminal law – again, both in its domestic and its

international incarnation – is much brighter if we avoid

these pervasive mistakes.

I. On the Origins of Rule Fetishism

It is important to remember that the very framework of

rules that undergirds Hart’s approach, and with which

Waldron is not particularly concerned, is a remnant of

positivism. Famously, Hart criticized classical Austinian

positivism by compellingly suggesting that its view of

law as “orders backed by threats” is uninspiring, and

that it fails to distinguish a legal system properly so

called and some other – non-legal – situations – such as

robbery by highwaymen, who are after all in a position to

issue orders and back them with threats. For Hart,

however, the crucial problem of classical positivism was

not its emphasis on rules per se, but that it only

5

appealed to one type of rule. Thus, Hart’s solution was

not to abandon the system of rules as such, but to add to

the primitive and simple rules of classical positivism,

what he termed secondary rules. That is why it is

precisely in connection Hart’s work that the term “soft-

positivism” gained currency. Hart is still a positivist,

albeit a “soft” one.

Recall too that, in this context, the quintessential

opponent of positivism was natural law theory, and that

what opposed these two schools of thought was the

metaphysical point as to whether something being law

could be determined independently of any appeal to

normativity – a possibility which the natural law

theorist denies and the positivist admits. Hart’s soft

positivism is a result of admitting some role for some

normative considerations in determining what exactly law

is. Admittedly, this role is limited – but here I will

suggest ways in which is too limited. My main

dissatisfaction with Hart’s soft positivism flows

6

precisely from the narrow focus on rules, and from the

ways that it shortchanges ethics.5

As it turns out, Hart’s narrow focus on rules is a

symptom of a large-scale phenomenon, visible in the work

of many highly influential analytic philosophers.

Elsewhere I attempted to diagnose the problem not only in

Hart, but also in two of the most influential

philosophers in the last fifty tyears: John Rawls and

John Searle.6 Here a summary of the phenomenon should

suffice. Hart’s distinction between primary and secondary

rules is to be placed in the context of the general 5 For the most famous objection against the appeal to rules

see Ronald Dworkin “The Model of Rules [I and II]” in his

Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

Press (1977): 14-80.

6 See Leo Zaibert, Punishment and Retribution, op. cit., 144-154, and

Leo Zaibert and Barry Smith “The Varieties of Normativity:

An Essay on Social Ontology” in Intentional Acts and Institutional

Facts: Essays in John Searle’s Social Ontology” Savas Tsohatzidis (ed.),

Dordrecht: Springer (2007): 157-174.

7

distinction between constitutive and regulative rules.

This more general distinction, whose contemporary

understanding can be traced back to Wittgensteinian

motifs, is, above all, a matter of logic.7 Very roughly,

regulative rules guide us as to how we should do things:

it is a regulative rule of chess that one should not

bring out the queen too early. Constitutive rules do not

quite offer guidance – they actually create the practice in

question: in chess, the rule that bishops move diagonally

is constitutive of the game of chess, in the sense that

if someone moved her bishops in straight lines she would

simply not be playing chess.

Invoking a game, like chess, in order to explain the

distinction between regulative and constitutive rules is

the overwhelmingly standard move. But that move speaks

volumes as to the shortcomings of rules fetishism.

Consider, for example, one of the most influential

7 See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford:

Blackwell (2009), passim.

8

articles by the most often cited living analytic

philosopher: Searle’s “How to Derive ‘Ought’ from ‘Is’”.8

On the standard interpretation, in this paper Searle has

something important to say about the age-old problem of

deriving meaningful normative statements from merely

descriptive ones. And the key to Searle’s alleged

demonstration as to how to do it was none other than the

constitutive rules of the use of the word ‘promise’:

since to say “I hereby promise to do X” means (in terms

of constitutive rules) that I ought do X. Voila – you have

derived an ought from an is! Of course, this is not the

sort of normative problem that has historically vexed

moral philosophers.9

8 John R. Searle, “how to Derive ‘Ought’ from ‘Is’”,

Philosophical Review 73 (1964): 43-58. For the claim that he is

the most often quoted living analytic philosopher see

http://leiterreports.typepad.com/blog/2015/05/the-most-

cited-living-philosophers-with-public-google-scholar-

pages.html.

9

And it is precisely this sort of humble, “soft

normativity” that pervades Hart’s view of law.10 In a way,

Hart sees law as a complex game. His forbears, the

classical positivists, did not see law as a game in this

sense, and that is why Hart complicated the picture,

turning law into a game-like phenomenon, with the all-

too-humble normativity of games. And now we are in a

position to reformulate Waldron’s objection to Hart with

which we started: Waldron points out that the fact (if it

is a fact) that international law is not quite the same

game as domestic law does not show that it is no game at

all. Waldron’s point, as noted, is correct as far as it 9 For more on Searle, see my “Intentions, Promises, and

Obligations” in John Searle (Barry Smith, ed.) Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press (2003): 35-54.

10 For more on soft normativity, see Leo Zaibert and Barry

Smith, “The Varieties of Normativity: An Essay on Social

Ontology” in in Savas L. Tsohatzidis (ed.) Intentional Acts and

Institutional Facts: Essays on John Searle’s Social Ontology, Dordrecht:

Springer, (2006): 157-175.

10

goes. But it could go farther. It is a mistake to think

of law – international and domestic, criminal and civil,

etc. – in terms of rules (at least rules modeled after

the rules of games) at all. In order to explain why it is

a mistake, I will take a closer look at the criminal law

in particular.

II. The Crying Game

While most criminal law theorists understand their field

in the decidedly narrow ways that stem from rule

fetishism, this is not always easy to show, since this

narrowness is often tacit, uncritical, or unconscious.

Antony Duff – one of today’s most influential criminal

law theorists – is, however, particularly useful for my

purposes because he emphatically and explicitly defends

precisely the sort of narrowness that I am here

criticizing. And so it is worthwhile to consider his

position in some detail.

11

In his “The Intrusion of Mercy”11 Duffs suggests that

to consider mercy in connection to criminal punishment

would be to introduce a consideration (mercy) that does

not really belong in the context of criminal punishment.

Duff does not deny either that mercy is a virtue, or,

more importantly, that sometimes punishers should behave

mercifully. But he is invested in stressing the fact that

the consideration of mercy is, as his title suggests,

always an intrusion. It is, moreover, not mercifulness

alone that Duff sees as an intrusion, but a host of other

values too – for the values which should matter to

criminal punishment are, for Duff, strictly narrow. In

other words, there is nothing about mercy in particular

that interests me here: had Duff written about “The

Intrusion of Decency”, “The Intrusion of Virtue”, “The

Intrusion of Elegance”, I would have focused on

“Decency”, “Virtue”, or “Elegance” instead.

11 R. A. Duff “The Intrusion of Mercy”, Ohio State Journal of

Criminal Law 4 (2007): 361-387.

12

Early in his article, Duff repeatedly tells us that

he is interested in the relation (or lack thereof)

between mercy and the criminal law. Remarks of the following

tenor appear often in the opening pages of Duff’s

article: “I will first […] need to identify the kind of

mercy that seems both morally and philosophically most

puzzling, at least in relation to criminal law”,12 “[i]n

the context of criminal law and punishment, mercy at

least involves remitting or mitigating a burden of

penalty…”,13 “my focus, like that of most theorists who

discuss mercy in the criminal law, will be on

sentencing…”,14 “how could mercy […] have any proper role

to play in a system of criminal law and punishment?”.15

Immediately, however, Duff turns to “an extra legal

example”16 of mercy which, he thinks, “offers a moral 12 Duff, op cit., 362.

13 Duff, op cit., 363.

14 Duff, op cit., 363.

15 Duff, op cit., 365.

16 Duff, op cit., 366.

13

analogue of mercy in the criminal law”.17 This is his

example:

A friend has done me some moderately serious

wrong: perhaps he has betrayed my trust in quite

a serious way, or used something that I told him

in confidence to his own advantage, in a way

that causes me serious embarrassment or loss. I

go to his home to confront him – to “have it out

with him”. I might not know whether our

friendship can survive – much depends on how he

responds to me; but my immediate aim is to

confront him forcefully with what he has done,

to make clear how wrong it was, to communicate

my hurt and my anger. I intend, that is, to

criticize and censure him: my aim is to get him

to understand, and ideally to accept, the moral

condemnation that is appropriate to the wrong he

has done. But when I reach his house, he greets

17 Duff, op cit., 366.

14

me with the news that his wife has just died. At

once (or so we might hope) my anger is replaced

by sympathy: even if I did not know his wife

myself, I share in his grief, and feel for him

in his loss. As for my complaint against him, my

determination to call him to account for the

wrong he did me, of course I do not pursue it;

indeed, one might hope that a true friend would

simply forget about it – it would be pushed from

her mind by the friend’s plight.18

I do not think that it is clear why Duff goes this

route. If it was so important to discuss the criminal law

itself (as Duff’s insistence at the outset indicated),

why did Duff not choose an example belonging to the

criminal law? Moreover, Duff is extremely careful to

avoid the word “punishment” (though he once uses the term

“castigate”19): all the wronged friend in Duff’s example

18 Duff, op cit., 366.

19 Duff, op cit., 368.

15

appears to wish to do is variously described as

“communicating”, “criticizing”, “censuring”, “calling to

account”, “complaining”, and even “confronting

forcefully” – but never punishing the wrongdoer. Duff’s

careful avoidance of the word punishment makes it harder

to understand how this example is truly “a moral

analogue”20 to anything belonging to the criminal law,

since whatever turns out to be the criminal law’s overall

point, surely punishing wrongdoers is part of it. Had Duff

simply said in his example that the wronged friend wanted

to visit the wrongdoer in order to punish him, the

analogy would have been much stronger, and the example

more useful. If, on the other hand, Duff were to join

other contemporary legal theorists in arguing that extra-

legal punishment does not really exist,21 then so much the20 Duff, op cit., 366.

21 See Michael Davis, “Punishment Theory’s Golden Half

Century: A Survey of Developments from (about) 1957 to

2007”, Journal of Ethics 13 (2009): 73-100, at 76 (fn. 8), and

Guyora Binder “Punishment Theory: Moral or Political”,

16

worse for his strategy of choosing an extra-legal case in

order to illuminate anything about (legal) punishment.

In any case, Duff believes that it would be

“obviously inappropriate for [the wronged friend] to

insist on talking about the wrong [done to him]”.22 With

this much I agree. But Duff appears to believe that the

(best? only?) way in which this inappropriateness could

be explained is through the mobilization of his

communicative account of punishment. About this, however,

I disagree. Duff believes that this inappropriateness

springs from the fact that the point of criticizing the

wrongdoer is “to get him to focus on, to attend carefully

to, the wrong [that he committed]”.23 “[G]iven what he has

now suffered”, Duff continues, “it would be callously

inhuman to expect him to do so”;24 “his attention will be

Buffalo Criminal Law Review 5 (2002): 321-371, at 321 and passim.

22 Duff, op cit., 367.

23 Duff, op cit., 367.

24 Duff, op cit., 367.

17

quite understandably, perhaps quite properly, focused on

what he has now suffered”.25

To the extent that Duff bases the inappropriateness

of insisting on talking about the wrong committed on the

wrongdoer’s inability to focus on the wrong he committed,

the communicative approach runs into difficulties.

Imagine that everything in Duff’s example remained the

same, except for the fact that when the wronged friend

arrives at the wrongdoer’s house, he learns not that his

wife has just died, but that the wrongdoer has just won

hundreds of millions of dollars in the lottery. Here,

too, it would be unreasonable to expect the wrongdoer to

focus his attention away from the millions he just won.

So, if what mattered were whether or not the wrongdoer

could indeed focus on, or effectively turn his attention

to, the wrong that he has committed, this ability can be

impaired by both sad events (such as the death of a

25 Duff, op cit., 369.

18

spouse) and by happy events (such as winning the

lottery).

If, on the other hand, it is only the inability to

focus that flows specifically from the death of a wife that

renders the insistence to talk about the wrong “obviously

inappropriate”, then Duff should have told us about it.

What makes it inappropriate to insist on talking about

the wrong is not the wrongdoer’s inability to focus

simpliciter, but the fact that his wife just died, or, if

you will, the fact that he-is-unable-to-focus-because-

his-wife-just-died. I believe that the inappropriateness

is related to important values about which Duff says

precious little, and which, in any event, have very

little to do with communication. Thus, imagine again that

everything in Duff’s example remains the same except that

your (no-longer) friend has been exposed as a serial

killer and child rapist. Would the fact that upon

arriving at his house you learn that his mother has just

19

died render your plan to confront him about his rapes and

murders “callously inhuman”?

Moreover, had Duff actually focused on punishment,

he would have noticed another shortcomings of his

approach. Assume that the wronged friend wanted to punish

the wrongdoer, that is, he wished to inflict on him the

suffering that he thought the wrongdoer deserved (and, to

simplify matters, that this suffering was also

recommended by whatever consequentialist rationales one

cares about). Clearly, the wronged friend could have done

this without any desire to communicate anything: he may

have gone to the friend’s house only with a desire to

slap him, without uttering a word; or he could simply

have gone there in order to secretly slash the tires of

the wrongdoer’s car.26

26 Obviously, these two examples constitute mere

descriptions of possible punishments, not endorsements. See

Leo Zaibert, Punishment and Retribution, op. cit. 59 ff.

20

And I think that even in these non-communicative

scenarios, the wronged friend, upon learning about the

fact that the wrongdoer’s wife has just died, should have

refrained from slapping him, or from secretly slashing

the tires of his car. Why? Because punishing this

wrongdoer, within the richer, tragic, context that his

wife has just died, is ugly. It is petty, churlish, smug,

self-centered, undignified, tasteless, tactless, and,

amongst many other things, downright repugnant. Again,

these reasons for not punishing this wrongdoer are based

on thick values which have no necessary connection to any

communicative enterprise whatsoever. More importantly,

they seem to have no place either in any game-inspired

understanding of law. There is no denying that

communicative acts of the sorts that Duff champions are

often valuable, and often extremely valuable. But neither

are they the only value that should matter for the

criminal law nor are other values simply intrusions. The

21

criminal law is not a communicative game – again, it is

not a game at all.

Since Duff believes that criminal punishment ought to

be seen as communicative through and through – just as he

evidently sees the example we have been discussing – he

does accept that in some analogous cases when criminal

defendants may be unable to focus on the wrong they have

done (because a major tragedy has befallen them), then

the value of things like mercy could somehow enter into

the criminal law picture. But, even in such cases, Duff

is emphatic “mercy marks, not an application of penal

justice, but rather an intrusion into the sphere of penal

justice by moral values and concerns that are not matters

of justice”.27 And Duff further stresses: “the criminal

courtroom, in which trial, conviction, and sentencing

take place, is a formal forum in which the various people

involved have their role to play”. These people are not

unencumbered, free “citizens who happen to have come

27 Duff, op cit., 381.

22

together”, and who may be seen as engaged in an

“unconstrained moral discussion” as to the defendant’s

guilt. They are, instead, “players in this game – a game

that defines their roles for them”.28

In a footnote, Duff offers the obligatory

qualification whereby his claiming that the criminal

courtroom is to be seen as a game “is not to imply that

it is either unimportant or detached from reality”.29 This

is of course old hat: it is the same sort of remark that

all other analytic philosophers make whenever they invoke

games in explaining the normative and axiological

dimensions of any realm. They do not mean to downgrade

anything, they insist on the fact that games merely are

an illustration, and so on. Whether they mean it or not,

however, positions such as Duff’s unquestionably exclude

from consideration precisely the normative and

28 Duff, op cit., 370.

29 Duff, op cit., 370, fn. 24.

23

axiological that are not amenable to be covered by

constitutive rules of games or game-like systems.

Just like in chess you ought not to move the bishops

in straight lines, a participant in a criminal trial

ought not consider matters “extraneous” to the trial –

the defendant’s life-story, the context in which her

actions have taken place, the standing of the state or of

this specific court to inflict suffering, and the very

nature of that suffering itself, to mention a few of

these matters ought to remain somehow off-limits. Like

horses that can only run with blinkers on, jurors and

judges alike ought to be limited in their field of

vision. Such is the game of the criminal law. Such is, in

Duff’s view, the game of inflicting suffering on people.

Interestingly, Duff actually admits that he is

defending an “avowedly limited, and in an important sense

shallow institution [of criminal law]”.30 But he thinks

that these limits and this shallowness are nonetheless

30 Duff, op cit., 376.

24

worth championing. And once again I disagree, for two

reasons.

First, Duff believes that “[t]hese kinds of

constraints [that undergird his limited and shallow view

of the criminal law] have a particular significance and

shape in a liberal polity that seeks to limit the reach

and scope of the criminal law”.31 Broadening the types of

values with which the criminal law is concerned, Duff

fears, threatens “a liberal system of criminal law”,

which in his view “should forbid” a sentencer from basing

“her sentencing decisions on an all-embracing

consideration of the offender’s whole life and

character”.32 This entails that sentencers – those charged

with making people suffer – should treat defendants –

those about to potentially be made to suffer – as

abstractions, whose roles and fates are in fact neatly

laid down by the rules of the game. And Duff thinks that

31 Duff, op cit., 371.

32 Duff, op cit., 371-372.

25

this is not only tolerable, but in fact the way things

should be: “a liberal system of criminal law that is to

respect its citizens’ privacy will need to abstract

agents quite drastically, if it is to avoid intruding

improperly into the deeper, more personal, aspects of

citizens’ characters and lives”.33

I share Duff’s worry. But evidently this worry is

out of place in cases such as the one Duff is discussing.

Even if a correct understanding of liberalism includes

respecting people’s privacy along the ways Duff suggests,

it surely includes also a particular view of the criminal

law. Part of the rationale for many a procedural matter

in the criminal law, is to protect alleged (or real)

wrongdoers from possible abuses in the way the state

wields its immense punitive power. As Ronald Dworkin

insightfully put it:

It would be a mistake to suppose that the

liberal thinks that these procedural rights will

33 Duff, op cit., 371.

26

improve the accuracy of the criminal process, that

is, the probability that any particular decision

about guilt or innocence will be the right one.

Procedural rights intervene in the process, even

at the cost of inaccuracy, to compensate in a

rough way for the antecedent risk that a

criminal process, especially if it is largely

administered by one class against another, will

be corrupted by the impact of external

preferences that cannot be eliminated

directly.34

So, the desire to not violate individual’s privacy

should be re-examined when putative infringements on said

privacy may in fact protect the individual in the sense

of the state not being able to punish her as much as

34 Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press (1985): 197-198. For elaboration see Leo

Zaibert “The Moralist Strikes Back”, New Criminal Law Review

14.1 (2011): 139-161.

27

otherwise, or at all. This would admittedly constitute an

asymmetrical treatment: encroachment into privacy and

considerations of other, thicker values should only be

permitted in cases in which this is to the individual’s

benefit, and not in cases in which it may hurt her. But

this is neither uncommon nor problematic. There are many

instances in the criminal law in which we make exceptions

of these sorts in favor of the defendant: the in dubio pro

reo principle, non bis in idem, and so on.

Crucially, however, the reason why we may decide not

to look too closely into these thicker values when they

may harm the individual is not that they somehow do not

belong in the criminal law, as Duff has it, but rather

that we wish to protect individuals from an over-zealous

punitive state. No one can seriously doubt that the

consideration of a defendant who although acquitted of a

crime actually committed it is something that matters when

evaluating what she did. The reason we recognize the

“defense” of res judicata is not that we think that the fact

28

that the acquitted defendant actually committed the crime

“does not belong” or does not matter for our evaluation

of her conduct. Rather, this is a way of protecting

individuals in general (even if this particular defendant

“gets away with it”).

Second, however, this is not merely a matter of my

seeing Duff’s invocation of liberal sensibilities here

inapposite and extraordinarily weak. For I think that

Duff comes close to actually contradicting himself. Duff

admits that he is not even sure that this shallowness has

any practical relevance:

one might wonder why it matters whether we

understand mercy as operating within the

perspective of criminal punishment, or as

intruding into that perspective. Perhaps it

makes little or no difference to the practical

outcomes: but if we are to understand ourselves

29

and our practices, we must get clear about their

logic and the modes of thought that structure them.35

We thus come full circle. It is not really a concern with

liberal principles that animates Duff’s defense of a

criminal law that he himself admits is shallow – since he

is after all not even sure that this shallow criminal law

would operate differently from any less shallow criminal

law. Rather, what animates Duff is precisely the same

sort of concern with the logic of the rules fetishism I

diagnosed at the outset, and which has been a

quintessential staple of the recalcitrantly positivist

modes of thought attendant to such rule fetishism.

III. The Axiological Complexity of Justice

As Elies van Sliedregt reminds us, international criminal

law is concerned with the “criminal aspects of

international law, rather than with the “international or

transnational aspects of a state’s domestic criminal

35 Duff, op. cit., 373. Emphases added.

30

law”.36 International criminal law is essentially

concerned with the following four (types of) crimes:

genocide, crimes against humanity, war crimes, and crimes

of aggression. These are crimes that can only be

committed by states (or quasi states) or by agents acting

on behalf of states (or quasi states). Thus, if, for

example, an Australian man is accused of sexual assault

in Sweden, determining the correct jurisdiction in this

case is not a matter of international criminal law. In a

way, the distinction between private international law

and public international law is helpful in this context.

By international criminal law we always mean public

international criminal law, for it is standardly believed

that the crimes that are the concern of international

criminal law just cannot be adequately handled within

domestic criminal law jurisdictions.

36 Elies van Sliedregt, “International Criminal Law”, in The

Oxford Handbook of Criminal Law (Markus D. Dubber and Tatjana

Hörnle, eds.) Oxford: Oxford University Press (2014) 1140.

31

If international criminal law is indeed an outgrowth

of international law (rather than of criminal law), then

one would understand why it may be commonly be met with

considerable skepticism, for it would simply inherit the

sort of generic skepticism which typically meets

international law. But if I am right in thinking that

Duff’s overly narrow view of the criminal law are indeed

endemic, then we have the elements in place that allow us

to see the sense in which international criminal law may

be doubly disadvantaged. For in addition to having to

overcome the sort of generic skepticism that it inherits

from international law, it would have to overcome the

shallow view of what the criminal law is supposed to be.

The positivistic rule fetish undermines, even if in

different ways, both international law (in general) and

(domestic) criminal law.

In order to see how this double undermining plays

out, let us once more return to Hart. He sensibly points

out that “the simple truisms which hold good for

32

individuals do not hold good for states”.37 He further

points out that “aggression between states is very unlike

that between individuals”.38 It is hard to imagine anyone

disagreeing with these observations. But he mobilizes

these sensible and harmless remarks in a not so sensible

and not so harmless ways: “in a population of a modern

state, if there were no organized repression and

punishment of crime, violence and theft would be hourly

expected; but for states, long years of peace have

intervened between disastrous wars”.39

Obviously, Hart wishes to defend a certain

disanalogy between domestic criminal law and

international law. Perhaps less obviously, however, this

disanalogy is in fact predicated on an analogy between

these two forms of criminal law. In these passages

37 Hart, op. cit., 219.

38 Hart, op. cit., 219.

39 Hart, op. cit., 219.

33

(though not elsewhere),40 Hart appears to think that just

as in the domestic sphere criminal law seeks to prevent

crime, in the international sphere criminal law would

allegedly seek to prevent aggression (genocide, war

crimes, crimes of aggression, and crimes against

humanity).

As it turns out, I do believe that there is an

analogy between domestic and international law – although

not quite the analogy that Hart assumes. There is of

course nothing wrong with preventing crime, in either the

domestic or international contexts. But that is not the

essential task of the criminal law: in whatever the

context, the essential task is to bring about justice.

The analogy then would be that just as in the domestic

context the criminal law seeks to bring justice vis-à-vis

crimes committed by individuals (or smallish groups of

40 See, e.g., his Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the Philosophy

of Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press (2008), where he

seeks to combine consequentialism with retributivism.

34

individuals), in the international context the criminal

law seeks to bring justice vis-à-vis crimes committed by

states (or quasi-states, etc.).

And from this it of course follows that I too

believe that there is, in a sense, a disanalogy between

the domestic and the international contexts, although not

quite the one on which Hart focuses. The disanalogy flows

from the first of Hart’s harmless remarks quoted above:

what is involved in bringing about justice amongst

individuals (or smallish groups) is not necessarily

identical the same as what is involved in bringing about

justice amongst states (or quasi states). But the

disanalogy that I have in mind does not really map onto

the domestic/international divide. Rather, it is a much

more global claim: what is involved in bringing justice

about in one case need not be identical to what is

involved in bringing about justice in other cases – and

this holds true whether these cases are all in the

domestic context or all in the international sphere.

35

Admittedly, bringing about justice is a complicated

affair. Operating with a broad understanding of

‘justice’, it ought to be admitted that there is

something unjust about the state of affairs that allows a

vicious billionaire to charge the virtuous pauper for the

small amount of money that the latter owes her (in a

narrow, rule-based sense of ‘owing’). Or consider the

differences between the war of aggression waged by a

relatively under-developed third world country against a

much more powerful country and the war of aggression

waged by a powerful nation against much weaker countries.

Sometimes, of course, the law needs to leave out certain

considerations, say, that this creditor is a billionaire,

or that this pauper will suffer tremendously if forced to

pay this amount, or that the billionaire is a nasty human

being, and so on. But any of these considerations could be

relevant to the overall assessment of the justice of a

situation. And the default position should be that these

considerations matter unless considering them is likely

36

to issue in more problems than solutions: micro-managing

justice in this or that case can lead to less justice

overall.

But it is easy to overestimate the magnitude of this

complexity, particularly if one is in the grip of

positivistic modes of thought. Many aspects of life, and

many instances of extra-legal injustices, are complex –

and we often cope with them with relative ease and with

relative success. To dodge these complexities in the case

of the criminal law – be it in the domestic or in the

international context – by stipulating that they are

“intrusions” is to pay to dear a price for simplicity.

Similarly, it is only if one is in the grip of

positivistic thinking that one would think that this more

complex approach is somehow deeply at odds with a

manageable, working criminal law (in whatever context).

For example, just as it is not obvious that mercy is an

“intrusion” in domestic criminal law (even if it is

somewhat unclear what exact role this fact ought to

37

play), it is not obvious, for example, that the fact that

due to the vagaries of the cold war Germany (and not

other nations) was the beneficiary of massive financial

help from Western victors is an irrelevant consideration

within the context of international criminal law. The

fact that it is unclear what exact role – if any – this

fact ought to play in administering justice within the

criminal law, should not entail that there is no such

role.

But this is just one example. All sorts of issues

related to colonialism, to history, to persecution and

ethnic cleansing, and even to sheer luck, may belong

within the context of international criminal law. That

the prospect of incorporating (some of) these sorts of

considerations may look messy is not a reason not to do

it. No one said that administering justice was supposed

to be easy and neat. Needless to say, I have not here

attempted to explain how to do this. All I attempted was

to warn against some popular reasons for perhaps too

38

summarily deciding that these considerations are

“intrusions”.

39