23
Journal of Philosophical Research Accepted Paper (Author’s final version) Manuscript #150904A 03/18/2016 Author information Title Dr. phil. Name Jens Gillessen Institutional affiliation Universität Leipzig Contact address Universität Leipzig Institut für Philosophie Beethovenstr. 15 04107 Leipzig Germany e-mail [email protected] REASONING WITH UNCONDITIONAL INTENTION Jens Gillessen Abstract. Suppose that you intend to go to the theater. Are you therein intending the unconditional proposition that you go to the theater? That would seem to be deeply irrational; after all, you surely do not intend to go if, for instance, in the next instant an earthquake is going to devastate the city. What we intend we do not intend 'no matter what', it is often said. But if so—how can anyone ever rationally intend simply to perform an action of a certain kind? In response to the puzzle, a 'conditionality' view of intention has emerged: The con- tents of everyday intentions are claimed to be fraught with hidden conditional clauses. The paper argues that such claims are radically unmotivated: Even unconditional inten- tions have only limited inferential import and hence contrast sharply with a 'no matter what' stance. The point is established by examining relevant patterns of reasoning from unconditional to conditional intentions. Keywords. Intention, conditional attitudes, practical reasoning, Luca Ferrero, John Broome.

Reasoning with Unconditional Intention

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

JournalofPhilosophicalResearchAcceptedPaper(Author’sfinalversion)Manuscript#150904A03/18/2016

AuthorinformationTitle Dr.phil.Name JensGillessenInstitutionalaffiliation UniversitätLeipzigContactaddress UniversitätLeipzig

InstitutfürPhilosophieBeethovenstr.1504107LeipzigGermany

e-mail [email protected]

REASONINGWITHUNCONDITIONALINTENTION

JensGillessen

Abstract.Supposethatyouintendtogotothetheater.Areyouthereinintendingtheunconditionalpropositionthatyougotothetheater?Thatwouldseemtobedeeplyirrational;afterall,yousurelydonotintendtogoif,forinstance,inthenextinstantanearthquakeisgoingtodevastatethecity.Whatweintendwedonotintend'nomatterwhat',itisoftensaid.Butif so—howcananyoneever rationally intendsimply toperformanactionofa certainkind?Inresponsetothepuzzle,a'conditionality'viewofintentionhasemerged:Thecon-tentsofeverydayintentionsareclaimedtobefraughtwithhiddenconditionalclauses.Thepaperarguesthatsuchclaimsareradicallyunmotivated:Evenunconditionalinten-tionshaveonlylimitedinferentialimportandhencecontrastsharplywitha'nomatterwhat'stance.Thepointisestablishedbyexaminingrelevantpatternsofreasoningfromunconditionaltoconditionalintentions.Keywords.Intention,conditionalattitudes,practicalreasoning,LucaFerrero,JohnBroome.

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–2–

I. Apuzzleaboutflatintention

Recentphilosophicalaccountsofintentiontendtoascribetospeakersinternallycon-ditionalattitudesonthebasisofeventhesimplestreportsofintention.Supposesome-one—callhimSchmidt—states,inresponsetoacolleague’squestionwhatheisuptointheevening:

(1) Iintendtogotothetheaterat7p.m.

Beingunconditionalingrammar,thestatementsurelyinvitesascriptiontoSchmidtofanintentionthathehimselfgoestothetheaterat7p.m.,period;thecontentnotinvolvinganyhiddenconditionalclauses.ItthusseemsmostnaturaltoascribetoSchmidtaninten-tionrelatinghimtothepropositionthathehimselfwillgotothetheaterat7;which‘flat’intentionwouldbeunequivocallycapturedby:

(2) Schmidtintendsto(goat7)

Lately,thenumberofthosewhobalkat‘flat’,face-valueaccountsofreportsofinten-tionaswellasdesirehavebeenontherise.Inthecaseathand,theywouldarguethat(2)misdescribesSchmidtasakindoffanaticwithacrazyintention:anintentiontogotothetheaterat7‘comewhatmay’,or‘nomatterwhat’.Andforsure,hisassertionof(1)cannotbetakentoentail:

(3) Schmidt intendsto(goat7 ifby then,anearthquakewillhavedevastatedthecity).

Ifadoptingflatintention(2)meanttocommittoludicrousintentionssuchas(3),tak-ingstatement(1)at facevaluewouldbea folly.Still, it isquitehardtoseewhata flatintentiontoAcouldbeotherthananintentiontoAinanycircumstances.

TheproponentsofwhatIwouldliketocalltheConditionalityViewhaveconcludedthatoureverydayintentionscannotbeoftheflatsortthat(2)exemplifies.Instead,theyhavecontended,thecontentsofordinaryintentionsmustbesystematicallyanddeeplyconditional.1Whatthepresentpaperisgoingtoshowisthatthiscontentionisunmoti-vated,forasimplereason:AflatintentiontoAisnotanintentiontoA'nomatterwhat'.Myargumentisstraightforward.

1. Ifintendingthat(A)wereintendingthatA'nomatterwhat',itwouldhavetobera-tionallypermissibletobaseonone'sintentionthat(A)anintentionthat(AifC),forarbitrarychoiceofcircumstancesC.2

2. Thereisnosuchpermission.3. Therefore,intendingthat(A)isnotintendingthatA'nomatterwhat'.

Mydefenseofthefirstpremisewillbebrief.OnthebroadlyinferentialistpictureIwillbeassuming,whatitamountstotobearacertainattitudeisreflectedbytheinferencestheattitudebearerisentitledtodrawbyvirtueofherhavingthatveryattitude(againstthebackgroundofherotherattitudes).Thus,thestateofbelievingthatpispartially,butnonetheless essentially characterized by a (conditional) normative fact: It entitles itsbearertoformthebeliefthatq,conditionalonhersimultaneouslybelievingthatifpthenq.Whateverstatedoesnotsupportsuchmodusponensreasoningcannotbecountedasabeliefthatp.Analogously,Iamsuggesting,anintentiontogoat7cannotbecountedasan

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–3–

intentiontodoso'nomatterwhat'unlessitrationallyentitlesitsbearertoadoptcondi-tionalintentionssuchas,say,anintentiontogoat7ifaquakewillhavedevastatedthecitybythen.3

ThatisallIhavetosayaboutthefirstpremise.Vindicatingthesecondpremisewilltakealotmorereflection,andthisishowIshallgoaboutit:Afteraclarificationoftheconceptofconditionalintentionandsomepreliminariesofreasoningtowardthem(sec-tionII),Iwillfirstpointoutwhyreasoningtowardconditionalintentionsisparticularlydifficulttoassess.Foronewearedealingwithpracticalreasoning,whichcallsforanaptstandardofassessment(sectionIII).Foranother(sectionIV:), theinferencepatterninquestionelicitsintuitionsthatcallforsomeacknowledgment,howeverlimited,ofinfer-encesfromintentionssuchas(2)tointentionssuchas(3).InsectionVIamgoingtoarguethatreasoningwithoutfurtherpremisesfromanunconditionalintentiontooneofitscon-ditionalcounterparts—inaccordancewitharuleIlabel(SCON)—isprovenincorrectbystrikingcounter-examples.Thispointwillbeestablishedbycriticalexaminationofanum-berofspeciousresponsestothosecounter-examples.SectionVI thenrevealsacorrectpatternofreasoningfromunconditionaltoconditionalintentions.Reflectiononthenec-essarycomplexitiesofthepertaininginferencerulewillmakeitclear,however,thatthereisaworldofdifferencebetweenflatandfanaticintentions.Atthatpointthen,thetruthofpremise2willbecomeobvious.

II. ConditionalIntentionandConditionalization

Firstofall,letmeclarifywhatwillbemeantby“conditionalintention”.Virtuallyeveryintentionisconditionalinthesensethatitsbeingformed,entertainedorabandonedde-pendsonenvironmental,neural,mentalandotherconditionsexternal to the intentionitself.Theseneedtobedistinguishedfromthe internalconditionswithwhichIwillbeconcerned.Thepointneedsemphasizingbecauselocutionsoftheform‘IintendthatAifC’4admitofbothanexternalandaninternalreading.Ontheexternalreading,thespeakermerelypredictsthatifCobtains,orisgoingtoobtain,shewillformanintentionthatA.Ontheinternalreading,sheexpressesanintentionthatAifCwhichatthetimeofutter-anceshehasalreadyformed—aninternallyconditionalintention.5Inordertodisambig-uate,thelatterwillbenoteddownintheform‘Nintendsthat(AifC)’.Thisnotationismeanttobecompatiblewith,butnottoimplythecontentiousviewthattheagentthereinintendsthepropositionthat(AifC).6Theremaybenosuchthingsasconditionalproposi-tions,andmyargumentswillnotpresupposeaparticularstanceonthematter.Whattheywillpresupposeistherobustnessofthedistinctionofinternalandexternalconditions.Amonginternallyconditionalintentions,myfocuswillbeonintentionswithinternalsuf-ficientconditionsexclusively.7

ByconditionalizationIshallmeanasubject’spassagebyinferencefromastateofin-tendingthatAtoastateofintendingthat(AifC).Sometimes,theformationofacondi-tionalintentionwillnotbeinferentialatall.Scaredbylonganddeepcracksintheceilingaboveyou,youmightdecidetorushtoaparticularemergencyexitasfastasyoucanincasetheyshouldstarttowiden.Obviously,decidingsomakessenseintheabsenceofanyintentiontorushthatcouldserveasapremise.Onotheroccasions,however,itseemsasthoughyouwillnotrationallycometointendthat(AifC)unlessyoualreadyintendthatA.Ontheseoccasions,youreason,orcouldreason,towardaconditionalintention.

A goodmeans to focus on these cases is to imagine playing the conditionalizationgame.Thegameinvolvestwoplayers,andtherulesareasfollows.Player1reportsoneof

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–4–

herintentions,intheform‘IintendtoA’or‘IintendthatA’.Next,player2asksplayer1aquestionoftheform‘DoyouintendthatAifC?’,pickinguptheA-termwhilechoosingCtotallyarbitrarily.Player1isthentogiveasincereyes-noresponse.Itwilloccasionallybehelpfultorecallthissetup.

Indealingwith conditionalization it needs tobe acknowledged that there are twowell-investigatedcorrectsortsofreasoningwhichatleastsometimesleadtoconditionalintentionsasconclusions:

• InstrumentalReasoning:Youadoptaconditionalintentionbecauseyoubelievedoingsotobeasuitablemeanstoachieveoneofyourgoals.8

• Enkraticreasoning:YoubelieveyououghttoAifC,andthereforeadoptanintentionto(AifC).9

Almostneedlesstosay,neitherofthesepathscouldbeexploitedtoreasonfromanintentionsuchas(2)toacrazyintention,suchas(3).Wereintention(3),oritsadoption,recommendedbyeitherSchmidt’sreasonsorasameanstohisends,itwouldnotcountasrelevantlycrazyafterall.But thisdoesofcoursenotprovetheConditionalitycampwrong;onecanconceiveoffurther,morestraightforwardwaysofconditionalizing.Letmesummarizetheseunderthelabel:

• GenuineConditionalization:Youadoptanintentionto(AifC)becauseyouintendthatAwithoutavailingofeitherinstrumentalorenkraticreasoning.

Theshortestandmostnatural-seemingrouteofGenuineConditionalizationwouldbeSimpleConditionalization:

(SCON) Nintendsthat(A) ∴Nintendsthat(AifC)

Whatweneedtoasktheninordertodecideonpremise2fromaboveiswhethercor-rectreasoningalong(SCON),orsomerelevantlysimilarsuchpath,ispossible.

III. AssessingPracticalReasoningforCorrectness

Thetaskofjudgingschemesofinferencesuchas(SCON)iscomplicatedbythefactthatwearedealingwithpracticalreasoning.Assessingtheoreticalinferencescanseemcomparativelyunproblematic:Truth-preservation inpassing frompremises to conclu-sionsiscommonlytakentobeareliableguide;atleastwhenoperatingunderidealizingabstractionfromthelimitsofreasoners’cognitiveresources.Intherealmofpracticalin-ference, however, the lens of truth-preservation turns blind. We need an alternativestandardofassessment.Inexplainingmine,IwilldrawheavilyonJohnBroome’stheoryofactivereasoning(Broome2013:177-91,221-87).

Reasoning,IsuggestinagreementwithBroome,isacausalprocessbywhichasubjectcomestohaveanattitudeXbecauseofotherattitudesY1,…,Yn,wherethisprocesssatis-fiesatleastonefurthercondition:Theconclusionattitudemustbeconstructedfromthepremiseattitudesbyapplicationofarule.Aparticularpieceofreasoningiscorrectjustincasethethereinappliedruleiscorrect.Correctnessofarule,Isuggest,shouldinturnbeassessedbymeansofthefollowingcriterion:10

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–5–

(COR) Aninferenceruleoftheform‘toderiveattitudeXasconclusionfromattitudesY1,…,Ynaspremises’11iscorrectiffitisrationallypermissibletobaseXon{Y1,…,Yn}.

OntheaccountIamsuggesting,toreasonistoactivelybaseattitudesonotheratti-tudes.Thus,(COR)identifiescorrectnessofreasoningwithitsrationalpermissibility.Atthesametimethecriterionoffersadeeperunderstandingofwhatreasoningis—atleastinthosecasesinwhichreasoningleadsonetoadoptanewattitude:TobaseanattitudeXasaconclusiononattitudesY1,…,YnaspremisesistoconstructXbyoperatingonY1,…,Ynfollowingarule,thereinadoptingX.12

Howdoweknowwhatrationalitypermits?Broomethinksthatbasingpermissionsmust, in the last instance,derive frompertaining requirementsof rationality (Broome2013:248,256-59).Whetherthisissoneednotbeansweredhere.Itakeitthatwehave(fallible,butnonetheless)immediateepistemicaccesstowhatrationalitypermitswhenwecarefullystudyexemplaryinstancesofreasoningandthereincometohaveintuitionsabouttheir(ir-)rationality.

IV. AConflictofIntuitions

Followingintuitionsblindly,however,isoutofthequestion.Asinotherphilosophicaldomains,too,areflectiveequilibriumneedstobeestablishedbetweenconsideredintui-tivejudgmentsandatheorythatexplainsthem(Harman1986:9).Theimportanceofsuchcautioningbecomesevidentwhenconsideringtheconfusinglywiderangeof intuitions(SCON)canevoke.

TotheadherentsoftheConditionalityView,thepatternhasapparentlyseemedal-mosttriviallycorrect.Aswillbeseen,thereisquiteanumberofwaysinwhichonecouldtrytoreconcilethisfavorablejudgmentwiththeapparentoddityofconclusionssuchas(3).Sometimesrecalcitrantintuitionscanbedefusedbytracingthemtosystematicbiasesofjudgmentorcognitiveillusions.Onesucherrortheory13couldclaim,forinstance,thatinjudging(3)acrazystate,whatactuallystrikesoneascrazyisnottheinternalreading:

(3-i) Schmidtintendsto(goat7ifaquakeoccurs)

...butrathertheexternalreading:

(3-e) Ifaquakeoccurs,thenSchmidtintendsto(goat7)

Theimpressionofcrazinessbeingexplainedbythesalienceofreading(3-e),nothingseemstostandinthewayofjudging(3-i)areasonableintentiontoadopt.

Againstthissuggestion,tworejoindersareinplace.First,itisnotatallclearthattheplanning state attributed to Schmidtby (3-i) is any less crazy than thedisposition at-tributedtohimby(3-e).Inordertoproperlyisolateintuitionsabout(3-i),considerabriefstory.SupposeSchmidtinallseriousnessdeliberatedasfollows:“I’mgoingtothetheaterat7...Therecouldbeadevastatingquaketonight,though...Looterswouldbeallovertheplace...Mightbebettertoguardthehousethen...Anyhow,evenifaquakewillstrike—I’llgo!”Supposefurtherthatasaresultofsodeliberatingheacquiresanumberofdisposi-tionsthatcanbeconsideredindicativeof(3-i):

• adispositiontoreplywith“yes”tothequestionwhetherhewillgotothetheaterincaseofaquake;

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–6–

• adispositionnottoformanyplansincompatiblewithgoingtothetheaterincaseofaquake;and

• adispositionnottodeliberatefurtheraboutthematter.

Finally,letussupposethathefailstoacquiredisposition(3-e):Around7,theearthbeginstoshakeviolently,andinhorrorSchmidtforthwithletsgoofhisintention.

Inthestory,(3-i)holdstruewhileexplicitdenialof(3-e)shouldpreventtheallegeddisturbanceofone’sjudgment.Still,Schmidt’sintentionseemscrazy—contrarytowhattheerrortheorypredicts.

Second,advancinganerrortheorymakessenseonlyifthereissomethingtobesaidinfavorof(SCON)inthefirstplace.Now,asfarasIcanseeintuitivesupportfor(SCON)couldoriginatefromtwosources.

1.) Friendly-lookinginstancesof(SCON).2.) Specioussimilarityof(SCON)withacertaincorrectpathofreasoningtowardcondi-

tionalbelief.

Letmecommentontheseoneatatime.Acorrectpathofbeliefreasoningiscertainly:

(BC⊃) Ibelievethat(P)∴Ibelievethat(C⊃P)

Thepatternisrationallyunassailable;afterall,thecontentofthepremiseentailsthecontentoftheconclusion,andbeliefis‘closedunderentailment’.14Itisnaturaltoconjec-turethenthatanalogousreasoningwithintentionislikewisecorrect:

(IC⊃) Iintendthat(P)∴Iintendthat(C⊃P)

Yet,theanalogyisanythingbutperfect.Thecorrectnessof(BC⊃)isobviousforthesolereasonthatbeliefisgovernedbya‘closureunderentailment’normofidealrational-ity.Nosuchnormgovernsintention,though,ascanbeseenfromacounterexample:Arichphilanthropistcouldfullyrationallyintendthat(heexterminatespovertyintheworld)withoutintendingthat(thereispoverty)—eventhoughtheformercontentclearlyentailsthe latter.Theabsenceofanunderlyingclosureprinciple for intentiondoesnotprove(IC⊃)incorrect,tobesure;theschemecouldstillbecorrectinitsownright.Evenso,theabsenceofanydeeper justificationandtherevealeddisanalogybetweenintentionandbeliefareboundtoshattermuchofitsinitialappeal.

Realsupportfor(SCON),Itakeit,isprovidedbyfriendly-lookinginstancesofthepat-tern.IfSchmidtwereasked:“Doyouintendtogotothetheaterat7ifthesunwillalreadyhaveset?”,or“…if2plus2equals4?”,or“…ifFlorenceisinTuscany?”,hemighteachtimeaffirm,andthiswouldnotstrikeanyoneasoddbehavior.Conditionalizingtowardcircum-stancesinwhichtheintendedactionwouldbereasonablegenerallylooksharmless.Thiscountsinfavorof(SCON).

Still,theseharmlessinstancescontrastsharplywithcrazy-seemingmovessuchastheinferencefrom(2)to(3).Whatwearefacingisaconflictofintuitions,wherebothkindsofintuitionwillhavetobeaccountedfor.Acknowledgementof(SCON)withoutaworkingstrategytodealwithbad-seemingmoveswillnotdo.Rejectingconditionalizationalto-gether,bycontrast,wouldaccountforthebad-seeminginstances,tobesure.Butthisso-lutionwouldcomeatthepriceofforgoingaquiteappealingexplanationoftheintuition

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–7–

thatmany,ifnotmostinstancesofconditionalizingseemtobealmosttriviallypermissi-ble.EventuallyIshallarguethat(SCON)isinneedofsevereregimentation,butbefore-handtherulecannotbeconsideredeitherplainlycorrectorplainlyfallacious.

Itmightbeobjectedthatthepriceofaclear-cutrejectionof(SCON)maynotbethathighafterall.Couldthegood-seeminginstancesofconditionalizationoncloserinspectionnotturnouttobeinstrumentalorenkraticinferencesindisguise?Afterall,ifyouintendtoA,youwillusuallysointendeitherbecauseyoubelievethatsointendingwillpromoteyourgoals,orbecauseyoubelieveyououghttoA.Andifthelatter,itseemsasthoughtheveryreasonsthatsupportyourought-beliefwillalsosupportanintentionto(AifC);atleastwhenCdoesnotunderminethosereasons.

Theobjectionfailsbecausethereareseeminglygoodconditionalizationsthepermis-sibilityofwhichisexplainedneitherbyinstrumentalnorbyenkraticreasoning.Toseethis,itsufficestoattendtoconstellationsremindingofBuridan'sAss,inwhichtheagentintendssomethingshehasnospecificreasontointend,andwhichshealsodoesnotbe-lievetobespecificallyconducivetoanyothergoalofhers.

Supposeasaleswoman—callherMeyer—intendstogobycarfromPaloAltotoSanFrancisco.Sheisalreadyontheroad,andbeforereachingacertainintersectionshewillhavetochoosewhethertogobyHighway101orbyInterstate280.Beingunfamiliarwiththearea,shedoesnothaveanybeliefsaboutthetworoutesthatwouldjustifyfavoringoneovertheother.Afterawhile,sheplumpsfor101.Anotherminutelater,stilltravelingtowardtheintersection,shepicksupahitchhiker.OnlearningthatMeyerintendstogoby101,thehitchhikerasksherwhethersheintendstogoby101evenifitisgoingtorain.Meyerdoesnotminddrivinginrain,andifitwillrainon101,shebelieves,itwillberain-ingon280either.Shereplieswith“yes”—andrationallyso,asitseems.

Letustakestock.Intheexample,Meyerexhibits,atsomepointorother,twointen-tions:

(M1) Meyerintendsto(take101)(M2) Meyerintendsto(take101ifitwillberaining)

Atnopointdoesshehaveanyought-belief fromwhichshecouldpossiblyhavein-ferred(M2)enkratically.Arguably,sheintendsto(gotoSanFrancisco)becauseshebe-lievessheoughttogotoSanFrancisco;also,shebelievesthatsheoughttotakeeither101or280.Butnoneofthesebeliefsissuitableforobtaining(M1)bywayofenkraticreason-ing—letaloneforenkraticallyobtaining(M2).Intheabsenceofanyreasontotake101inparticular,shecannotrationallycometobelievesheoughtto(take101)—letaloneto(take101ifitwillberaining).

HoweverMeyerhasarrivedat(M2)—shecannothavereasonedherwayenkratically.Norcouldinstrumentalreasoninghaveyielded(M2);afterall,nogoalofherswouldbeservedbyadopting(M2)overandabove(M1).Whetheritwillrainornot,(M1)sufficesto takeher toSanFrancisco.Andstill, shewouldnothaveadopted (M2),hadshenotadopted(M1)inthefirstplace.Theremustbeathirdcorrectpathofreasoningtowardconditionalintentions,apartfrominstrumentalandenkraticreasoningthen;andforallthathasbeensaiduptothispoint,thispathcouldwellbeSimpleConditionalization.

V. SimpleConditionalizationinspiteofmaligninstances?

If(SCON)asitstandswerecorrect,bothbenignandmaligninstancesofconditionali-zationwouldhavetobegoodreasoning.NotonlywouldSchmidtbepermittedtoreason

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–8–

from(2)toanintentiontogotothetheaterat7ifbythenthesunwillhaveset;hewouldevenbeabletoreasoncorrectlytowardcrazyintention(3).Hencetheproposalimmedi-atelyrunsintotrouble.

Thatalonebarelyjustifiesitsabandonment,however,becausetheforceofthecoun-ter-examplesisnotentirelybeyonddoubt.Indefending(SCON)againsttheallegationoflicensingcrazyinferences,twogeneralstrategiescanbepursued.

1.) Itmight be held that bad-seeming conditionalizations, although good reasoning inthemselves,inrealityneveroccur(maybewithsomeveryspecialexceptions)becausedespiteappearances,agentsgenerallydonothave intentionsassimpleas(2) fromwhichtheycouldreasontowardcrazyintentions.ThisdefensehasatleastimplicitlybeenendeavoredbyLucaFerrero,themainproponentoftheConditionalityView.

2.) Onthecontraryassumptionthatagentsdohaveintentionsassimpleas(2),appear-ancescouldstilldeceiveinanotherway.Inseeminglycrazymovessuchasfrom(2)to(3)thecrazinessoftheconclusioncanbe(andhasinfactbeen)creditedtoviolationofrationalityprinciplesotherthan(thosearguablyunderlying)GenuineConditional-ization.ThecandidatesIshalldiscussareintentionconsistency,theinstrumentalprin-ciple,Enkrasia,andaprincipleabouttheconnectionbetweenintendingandbelieving.

A. TheDefensegivenbytheConditionalityViewThe Conditionality View of intention exploits (SCON) to argue that intentions are

crazystatesunlesstheircontentisregimentedbythepresenceofstrongimplicitcondi-tionalclauses.Ononesimplistic,butinstructiveversionoftheview,thedeepstructureof(2)amountsto:15

(4) Schmidtintendsthat(hegoesat7ifhewillthenfinditadvisabletodoso)

Callan intentionwithabuilt-inhighlygeneralevaluativeclausea ‘deep’ intention.Now,conditionalizingtowardtheearthquakecircumstance,suchasinthestepfrom(2)to(3),wouldleadto:

(5) Schmidtintendsthat((hegoesat7ifhewillthenfinditadvisabletodoso)ifby7,anearthquakewillhavedevastatedthecity)

Itisnothardtoseehowtheadvisabilityclausesaves(5)fromcraziness.Ontheas-sumptionthattheearthquakereallywilltakeplace,Schmidtwillat7hardlyfinditadvis-abletogo;theinnermostconditionalwillturnoutvacuouslytrue,andtheintentionwillbesatisfiedwhetherornotSchmidtgoestothetheater.

AdherentsoftheConditionalityViewreadilyadmitthat(SCON),whenappliedtoflatintentions,doessupportmovestowardcrazyconclusions;theinferencefrom(2)to(3)isclaimed(oratanyrateimplied)tobecorrect.Yet,sincenosanepersonhasintentionsasflatas(2) toreason from,16examplesofcrazy inferencesareclaimedtobeunrealistic;whereastheresultsofapplying(SCON)torealisticpremisesareclaimedtobesanethankstotheirbuilt-inadvisabilitycondition.

TheConditionalityViewthusoffersawaytoholdonto(SCON)eveninthefaceofseeminglybadinstances,butatthesametimeitraisesabunchofnewissues.Letmecon-finemyselftoaproblemaboutakraticintention.Areakraticintentionssupposedtobedeeporflat?SupposeGeorge,arecklessundergraduate,againsthisownbetterjudgmentgivesintoanurgeofcuriosityanddecidestotakeheroinat9p.m.whenhewillbebackinhisroom.Onthedeepconstrual,Georgehasthereinformed:

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–9–

(6) Georgeintendsthat(hetakesheroinat9ifhewillat9finditadvisabletodoso)

Georgedoesnotnowfinditadvisabletotakeheroin;thatiswhatmakeshisintentionakratic,ifanything.Unlessinthecourseofthedayheatsomepointcomestofinddrugabuseadvisable,(6)willat9failtoinitiatedrug-takingonhisbehalf;theintentionwillnotbeproductiveofakraticaction.Yetthisiswhatakraticintentionoftendoes.Soakraticintentionmustbeflat:

(7) Georgeintendsthat(hetakesheroinat9)

ButiftheConditionalityViewmustadmitthatakraticintentionisflat,itcannotsolvetheproblemofbad-seemingconditionalizationsforakraticintentions.Justconsidertheinferencefrom(7)to:

(8) George intendsthat(hetakesheroinat9 ifhisbourgeoisparentswill thenbegivinghimasurprisepartyinhisownroom)

IntendingtotakeheroinwhilebeingwatchedbyhisparentswillbeacrazythingforGeorgetointend,evenbyhisownlights(wecanassume).Themovefrom(7)to(8)wouldbeacrazyinstancetheConditionalityViewcannotaccommodate.Itwillatanyratenotdotoclaimthatintentionssuchas(7)inrealityneveroccur.Denyingthepossibilityofakrasiaseemstoohighapriceforholdingonto(SCON).Andnoticethat,if(SCON)isin-correct,soaremostlikelytheinferentialmoveswhicharesupposedtoprovidetheinitialmotivationforassumingtheConditionalityView—movessuchasfrom(2)to(3).

Insomerespects,Ihavebeensimplifying.Ferrero,whohasputforwardthebestelab-oratedversionoftheviewyet,actuallysuggestsamorecomplicated‘deepstructure’thandisplayedby(4).17Yet,evenonhiselaborateaccountitishardtoseehowakraticinten-tioncouldbedealtwithsatisfactorily.Isuggesttoexploreotherdefensesof(SCON).

B. TheInconsistencyDefenseHereistheideaofaseeminglysimpledefense:Whenever(SCON)leadsfromanin-

tentiontoacrazyintention,thecrazinessoftheprogressionisclaimedtobeduenotto(SCON)buttoanallegedinconsistencywithoneoftheagent’sotherintentions.Morepre-cisely,theInconsistencyDefensecanbeputforwardineitheroftwoforms.

(ID1) Theagentmaybeclaimedtohaveabackgroundintentionthatisinconsistentwithintendingto(AifC).Ifanagenthasa‘blockingintention’,asIshallsay,thiswillexplain sufficiently why she cannot fully rationally adopt the conclusion of(SCON).

(ID2) Alternatively,itcouldbeclaimedthatagentsspontaneouslyformsuitableblock-ingintentionswheneverconfrontedwithstimulisuchas,say,thesortofques-tionsaskedbyplayer2aspartoftheconditionalizationgame.

Forthesetobeviabledefensesof(SCON),weneedtobeabletoplausiblyascribesuit-ableblockingintentions.WhichintentionofSchmidt’s,forinstance,couldpossiblyblockaninferencefrom(2)to(3)?Thesecandidatesmaycometomind:

(9) Schmidtintends(nevertoendupintrouble)(10) Schmidtintends(nottogoifacalamityoccurs)(11) Schmidtintends(nottogoifaquakeoccurs)

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–10–

Actually,(9)willnotdo.Evenonawideconstrualofinconsistency,(9)conflictswith(3)onlyundernon-trivialadditionalassumptions;e.g.thatSchmidtbelievesthatgoinginaquakewouldtakehimintotrouble.Intentionswithhighlygeneralcontentsuchas(9)arebetterseenasreflectinggoalswhichcallforadoptionofsuitablemeans.Iwillgetbacktoblockingbywayofinstrumentalreasoningbelow.(10)and(11),bycontrast,areindeedinconsistentwith(3).(11)isplainlyso;and(10)onareasonablybroadconstrualofcon-sistencywhichalso takesasubsetof theagent’sbeliefs intoaccount.18For thesakeofsimplicity,letmefocuson(11).

Could (11)bepartof Schmidt’sbackgroundof intentions, asaproponentof (ID1)mightclaim?Itcould,butthatdoesnotseemverylikely.Itshouldofcoursebeadmittedthatagentsaregenerallydisposedtorespondadequatelytosurprisingevents,ratherthaninfoolishways.AndifSchmidtis likemostofus,hewillmostlikelyallthewhilehavedispositionstotakequitespecificmeasuresinresponsetoaquake;say,toimmediatelysuspendhisplans;tostayathome;maybetoturnontheradio,etc.Yet,beingdisposedtoAinresponsetoCusuallyfallsshortofintendingto(AifC).Anagentmaybesodisposedsimplyinvirtueofadispositiontoform,inresponsetoC,anintentionthatA.EvenwithoutgoingintothedetailsaboutwhenadispositiontoAinresponsetoCcanbesaidto(co-)constitute adistal intention,19it is plain enough that thepresenceof an intention for-mationdispositionmustnotbeconfusedwiththepresenceofabackgroundintention.Schmidtisdisposednottogoifaquakeoccurs,butunlessheispromptedtotakeastanceonthescenario,hemostlikelydoesnotharboranyquake-relatedintentions;noteventacitly.Thepointgeneralizes;proponentsof(SCON)hadbettermakedowithoutappealstoagents’backgroundintentions.

Howabout(ID2)—theclaimthatplayersoftheconditionalizationgamequicklyformblockingintentions?Asimpletemporalconsiderationwillrevealaflawinthislineofde-fense,too.Supposeatt0youformanintentiontogotothetheaterthatnight.Att1youareaskedwhetheryou intendtogo ifaquakewilloccur.Let itbegranted for thesakeofargumentthatthequestiontriggerscognitiveprocessesofyoursthatissueintheblockingintention(nottogoifaquakewilloccur).Undertheassumptionsmade,youwill,however,nothavehadthisblockingintentionbetweent0andt1.Hence,throughouttheinterval[t0,t1]itwouldhavebeenrationalofyoutoavailof(SCON)andinferthecrazyintention(togo if a quakeoccurs). This still seemsutterlywrong.Apparently, defense (ID2)positsblockingintentionsattoolateapointintimetoachieveitsgoal.

C. TheInstrumentalDefenseThe InstrumentalDefense holds that in bad-seeming conditionalizationmoves the

agentviolateseithertheconsistencyrequirementonintention,orthe instrumentalre-quirement,orboth.Thus,itmaywellbethoughtthatwhatkeepsSchmidtfromrationallyadopting(3)onthebasisof(2)isthatinadopting(3),hewouldflouttheinstrumentalrequirement as follows. Schmidtmay tacitly be intending to X, and (part of) the bestmeanstoachieveXmaybethatifanearthquakeoccurs,hedoesnotgotothetheater.IfasuitableX-termcouldbepointedout,hewouldbeunabletofullyrationallyadopt(3)evenifrationalityshouldpermithimtobase(3)on(2).

WhatpropositioncouldplaythepartofXinthisstory?MaybeSchmidtintends,how-ever implicitly,nottogetstuck indebris;or, toreturntothesomewhatmorecredibleproposalfromabove,hemaybeintendingnevertoendupintrouble.Theimpressionthat(3)isacrazyconclusionmightthenbesaidtostemfromsomesuchfuzzybackgroundpolicy.

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–11–

On thisaccount,Schmidtwouldbeentitled (andunlesshedropshisgoal, at somepointrequired)toreason:20

(I-1) IintendthatIneverendupintrouble Ibelieveforminganintentionthat(Idonotgoifaquakeoccurs)tobe(partof)

thebestmeansnevertoendupintrouble ∴IintendthatIdonotgoifaquakeoccurs

Andforsure,werehetoadoptandholdontothisconclusion,hecouldnotconsistentlyadopt(3).

Theproblemwiththisdefenseisthatthebeliefpremisesitneedstoinvokeareoftentooflimsy.Inmanycases,theinstrumentalbeliefwillbefalse,whichmakesitimplausibletoseeitaspartoftheagent’sbackgroundoftacitbeliefs.Asithappens,Schmidt’sisoneofthesecases.Aminimalconditionformtobe(partof)ameanstoeshouldbethattheoccurrenceofm(jointlywiththeotherparts)raisesbysomenon-negligibleamounttheprobabilitythatewillobtain.Now,(3)willonlytakeSchmidtintotroubleifaquakewillactually occur. This is extremely unlikely, though. Schmidtwill almost certainly avoidtroubleanyway,whetherornothewillgoifaquakeoccurs,andwhetherornotheintendsnottogoifaquakeoccurs.Consequently,notgoingifaquakeoccurscontributessolittletothelikelihoodofhisnotendingupintroublethatforminganintentionnottogoifaquakeoccurscannotseriouslybeconsidered(partof)ameansoftrouble-avoidance;letalone(partof)thebestmeans.Thebeliefpremiseissimplyfalse,andwillalwaysbesowhenreasoningtowardintentionswithunlikelyinternalconditions.SincetheInstrumen-talDefensefailstoblockabroadrangeofbad-seemingconditionalizations,itwillnotdo.

D. TheEnkraticDefenseTheEnkraticDefense is theattempt toexploitenkratic reasoning towardnegative

conditionalintentionsinordertoblockmalign(SCON)-instances.NoticefirstofallthatSchmidtisquitelikelytohavecertaintacitought-beliefs.Inparticular,hemaywellbelievethatallthingsconsidered,heoughtnottogoat7ifaquakeoccurs.Nowconsiderthefol-lowing(conditional)Enkraticruleofinference:21

(I-2) Ibelievethat(IoughtthatAifC) Ibelievethat(itisuptomewhetherornotAifC) ∴Iintendthat(AifC)

Accordingtothepermissionofrationalityunderlying(I-2),Schmidtispermittedtobaseonhisought-belief(andanadditionalbeliefthatgoingwouldbe‘uptohim’)anin-tentionnottogoifaquakeoccurs.AndifSchmidtintendsnottogoifaquakeoccurs,hecannotconsistentlyadoptanintentiontogoifaquakeoccurs.

Butwhy think that Schmidt actually adopts the blocking intention? The idea is ofcoursethatenkraticreasoning inaccordancewith(I-2)willmakehimso intend.Now,(I-2)mightberootedinamerepermission;theremightnotbeanycorrespondingrationalrequirement.Theproblemwithamerepermissioninthepresentcontextwouldbethatyoucanavailofit,ornotavailofit;ineithercaseyouare(insofar)perfectlyrational.Absentacorrespondingenkraticrequirement,Schmidtcouldrationallychoosesimplynottoavailof(I-2).Ifso,noopposingintentionwillbetheretoconflictwithanintentionto(goifaquaketakesplace),shouldhechoosetoinferitbywayof(SCON)from(2).(2)wouldstilllookcrazy,andtheblamewouldrestwith(SCON).TogettheEnkraticDefenseofftheground,wecruciallyneedtoappealtoanEnkraticrequirement.Soconsider:22

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–12–

(ECR) RationalityrequiresofNthat,if(1) NbelievesattthatsheherselfoughtthatAifC,andif(2) NbelievesattthatitisuptoherselfthenwhetherornotsheA-sifC,then(3) NintendsattthatAifC

Atfirstglance,thismaylookpromising.SinceSchmidtsatisfiessub-clause(2),thereisjustonewayinwhichhecanbothhavehisought-beliefandsatisfy(ECR):Bynotin-tendingto(goat7ifaquakeoccurs).(SCON),tobesure,wouldenableSchmidttoreasoncorrectlyfromhisintentionto(goat7)towardintendingto(goat7ifaquakeoccurs);butSchmidt’sought-beliefwouldblockhimfromrationallyadoptingtheconditionalin-tention.

TheproblemwiththeEnkraticDefenseisthat(ECR)isnotreallyplausible.SupposethatSchmidtisaskedwhetherheintendstogoif(C:)aquakeoccurs.Supposefurther-morethatSchmidt,likemostofus,believesittobeextremelyunlikelythatonthedayinquestionaquakewillinfactoccur.HemaythenwellrefusetoclutterhismindwithaplanconcerningwhattodoifC—andrationallyso.Underlimitationsoftimeandmemory,itisoftensimplynotrationaltoformaplanwithrespecttocircumstanceswhichalmostcer-tainlywillnotcomeabout.Adoptingsuchplansmaybepermissible,butthatrationalityrequires it is justasimplausibleastheviewthatagentsarerequiredtoadoptbelievedlogicalconsequencesofwhattheybelieve,nomatterwhetherornottheycareaboutthoseconsequences(Harman1986:12,55-57;Broome2013:157f.).

Toovercometheobjection,(ECR)wouldneedtobeproppedupwithanadditionalsub-clause;maybe:

NbelievesattthatC

Butthen,theEnkraticDefensewillbeunabletoblocknumerousbad-seemingcondi-tionalizationstowardcircumstanceswhichtheagentdoesnotall-outbelieveto(begoingto)obtain.Oneoftheseunblockedmoveswould,oncemore,bethemovefrom(2)to(3).Apparentlythen,theEnkraticDefensedoesnotsucceedeither.

E. TheIntention-BeliefDefenseAdefenseof(SCON)thatturnsonthecoherenceofintentionswiththeagent’sbeliefs

aboutthefuturecanbedrawnfromDonaldDavidson’s“Intending”.23Asiswellknown,Davidson’saccountidentifiesfuture-directedintentiontoΦwithanevaluativejudgmentof somesort that futureΦ-ing is ‘all-out’,orunconditionallydesirable.24In thecaseofpresent-directedintention,suchajudgmentcanassumethesimpleform:“Thisactionisdesirable”(Davidson1980:98).Buthowcanonereasonablyjudgefutureactiondesira-ble?ThisistheproblemDavidsonstruggleswithonthelastpagesofhisessay.SupposeIaffirm:

(12) Iintendtoeatacandytonight.

Canmyassertionbeunderstoodasajudgmentthateatingacandytonightwillbeun-conditionally desirable? Since eating apoisoned candywouldbe highly undesirable, itseemsthatnot.Therefore,Davidsonconcludes,“itwouldbemadtoholdthatanyactionofmineintheimmediatefuturewhichistheeatingofsomethingsweetwouldbedesira-ble”(Davidson1980:99;myitalics).

Howisthisa(bad-seeming)instanceofconditionalization?AlthoughDavidsoninthe‘poisonouscandy’caseapproachestheproblemasanissueaboutspecifyingratherthanconditionalizingone’sintention,arelevantvariationisdefinitelywithinrange:Itwould

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–13–

beequallymadtojudge-desirablethatIeatacandyifitispoisoned.Therelevanceofhisconsiderationstothequestionatissuethenbecomeobvious.

Indealingwiththeproblem,Davidsonwaswellawareofthekindofsolutionnowa-daysofferedbytheConditionalityView.Ifstatementssuchas(12)involveimplicitcondi-tions,thesemayblockeatingapoisonouscandyfromsatisfyingthereportedintention’scontent.Theconditionalintentionbehind(12)wouldthenbelocatedsomewherealongaspectrumofgeneralitysuchas:

Iintendtoeatacandytonightifandonlyif… …itwillnotbepoisoned.…itwillbeagoodcandy.…doingsowillthenbeadvisable.

But,asDavidsonremarks,onceproppedupwithconditionssufficientlycomprehen-sive toblockmaddesirabilityentailmentsaltogether, thestatementwill tellusalmostnothingaboutwhattheagentintends(Davidson1980:93f.);sothat,“ifthisistheroadImusttravel,Iwillnevergetmyintentionsright”(ibid.:99).ThushavingrejectedtheCon-ditionalityView,25Davidsonhastomakesenseofunconditionalintention.HereiswhatItaketobehissuggestion.26AccordingtoDavidson,thejudgmentanintentioncanbeiden-tifiedwithisnotconcernedwiththewholerangeofactionsthatwouldsatisfytheinten-tion,butonlywiththosecompatiblewiththeagent’sbeliefs.Thisrestrictionisanessentialpartofhisreductivedefinitionofintention,27whichcanbestatedthus:

(INTD) Natt1intendsthat(Aatt2)iffNatt1judgesthatanyinstanceof(Aatt2)compat-iblewithN’sbeliefsatt1aboutthepresentandthefutureisunconditionallydesir-able.

Howdoesthebeliefclausehelptoovercomethemadnessproblem?Suppose:

(13) IbelievethatIwillnoteatapoisonouscandy.

Inintendingtoeatacandytonight,Ijudgethatanyinstanceofdoingsothatiscom-patiblewithmybeliefsisdesirable.ButdoI,againstthebackgroundof(13),thereinjudgedesirableeatingapoisonouscandy?Thecontentof(13)entailsthattherewillbenosuchactions.Inthissense,themadactionsarenotcompatiblewith(13),sotheanswerisno.Giventhatanagenthastherequiredbeliefs,(INTD)providesthemeanstoexcludewhat-soevercrazyactionfromwhatisjudgeddesirable.

AlthoughDavidson’saccountoffuture-directedintentionhasbeenconvincinglyre-futed(seeBratman1985),itmightstillbethoughtthatthegistofhis'belieffilterdefense'canbesavedbyincorporatingitinatheoryofrationality,theideabeingthatitisirrationaltointendthat(AifC)whilebelievingall-outthatinC-typecircumstancesonewillnotA.Soconsiderthe‘BeliefFilterRequirement’:28

(BFR) Rationalityrequires((Nbelievesthat¬(C∧A))⊃¬(Nintendsthat(AifC))

Atleasttacitly,Schmidtsurelybelievesthatnotbothanearthquakewilloccur(C)andhewillgotothetheater(A).Aslongasheholdsontothisbelief,hecannotcometointendtogoifanearthquakeoccurs('AifC')withoutviolating(BFR).

Theproblemwiththesuggestionisthatitinheritsnotonlythepower,butalsotheshortcomingsofDavidson’sdefense.Letmeconfinemycritiquetohisoriginalsuggestion.InordertoblockallmaddesirabilityentailmentswithDavidson’sbelieffilter,agents’be-liefswouldhavetobeeithernumerousorabstractenoughtodenywhatevermad-making

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–14–

circumstancetheagentcouldconceiveof.Nowithasofcoursetobeadmittedthattheo-riesoftacitbeliefindeeddoascribesurprisinglydensepatternsofbeliefs.ConsiderasanexampleMarkCrimmins’account:One“at-least-tacitlybelievesp just incase it isas if[one]hasanexplicitbeliefinp”(Crimmins1992:248).Onthisaccount,ItacitlybelievethatIneverateabicycle:AlthoughIneverevenconsideredthepossibility,IdothinkandactasifIexplicitlybelievedthatIneverateabicycle.Likewise,Schmidtispredictedtotacitlybelievethatnothingwillinterferewithhistheater-going;afterall,heplansongoingjustashewouldifhehadanexplicitbeliefthatnothingwillinterferewithhisplan.Ac-countsoftacitbeliefcanindeedmakeitseemasifourbeliefswerevirtuallyall-encom-passing.

Yet,evenourtacitbeliefsaregappy.SupposeIplantoapplyforanopenjobpositionatmyhomeuniversity,whichhasnotbeenadvertised.Iknowthatatpresent,thereisexactlyoneapplicant,aboutwhomIknownothingfurther.Ialsobelievenooneelseisgoingtoapply,andhavenocluehowtheemployerwillmakethedecision.Beingaskedaboutmychancestogetthejob,Ithereforeestimatethemat0.5.Nowconsiderthefol-lowingpossiblecircumstance:

(14) Theemployerwillgivethejobtomyrival.

Judgingitdesirableto(applyforthejobifitwillbegiventomyrival)wouldcertainlybefoolish.Canthebelieffilterdefenseblockthispurportedupshotofmyplan?ItwouldhavetobecontendedthatIat-least-tacitlydisbelieve(14).ButIlackthedispositionschar-acteristicofhavinga(negative)belief.ItisnotasifIhadanexplicitbeliefthat(14)isfalse.Iamnotinanywaydisposedtodeny(14)whenasked;nordoIinmybehaviorordelib-erationinanywayrelyonmyrival’sfailure.IdonothappilytellmybestfriendthatIamsoongoingtohaveabetterjob;Idonotmoveintoalargerapartment,andsoon.AllthismakesitutterlyimplausibletosupposeItacitlydisbelieve(14).Andthen,therewillbenobeliefinmymentalstockthatcouldblockthemadjudgment.

Thebelieffilterdefensefailsbecauseitdoesnotblockallcrazyjudgments(orinten-tions,respectively).Itwouldwork,tobesure,ifdoxasticindifferencewereimpossible;but if theonlyreason forassumingsuchanextremeviewofbelief is thewish tosave(SCON),weshouldratheradmititsfailure.

VI. RestrictedConditionalization(RCON)

Themostnaturaldefensesof(SCON)havingfailed,theremaystillbefurtherrequire-mentsofrationalitywhichgiverisetodefensesIhavenotconsidered.Despitethisuncer-tainty, I suggest to radically change the strategy. By any reasonable standard, (SCON)shouldbeconsidereduntenableandbeabandoned.

Recall, however, thatwestillneed tomake senseof those conditionalizations thatseemedtobealmosttriviallypermissible:SinceSchmidtintendsto(goat7),heispermit-tedtoadoptanintentionto(goat7ifFlorenceisinTuscany).Andrecallalsothatenkraticreasoningcanaccountformany,butnotalloftheseharmless-seemingmoves.Ifwedis-card(SCON),wehadbetterreplaceitwithsomealternativeschemeofGenuineCondition-alization.Bymodestlycomplicating(SCON),wemaystillobtainaninferenceschemethatdoesnotproducebad-lookingconsequencesinthefirstplace.Tothatend,wewillneedtointroduceadditionalschematicpremisesintotherule.WewillthusobtainrulesofRe-strictedConditionalization—RCON,forshort.

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–15–

A. TheOught-RestrictionandtheEnkraticRestrictionWheretotakesuitablerestrictivepremisesfrom?Eventhoughenkraticreasoninghas

beenproveninsufficienttoaccountforallofthedata,thecorrectnessofconditionalizingtowardcircumstancesCdoesseemtobesomehowrestrictedbywhatought,oroughtnot,tobedoneifCweretoobtain.Letusseeifwecanmakesenseofthisidea.Firstconsideraruleof‘Ought-Restricted’Conditionalization:

(I-3) Iintendthat(A) IoughtthatAifC ∴Iintendthat(AifC)

Thisnaturalsuggestionwillnotdo.(I-3)iseithernotyetfullyexplicit,ornotaninfer-enceruleanyonecouldfollow.Surelycannooneavailof(I-3)withouttakingsomeatti-tudinalstanceonwhethersheoughtthatAifC.29Hence,thesecondpremisein(I-3)can-notyetbefullyexplicit.Yet,onmakingitexplicitweobtainarulethatfatallyremindsofenkraticreasoning:

(I-4) Iintendthat(A) IbelievethatIoughtthatAifC ∴Iintendthat(AifC)

With(I-4)wewouldoncemorebuyintothelimitationsofenkraticreasoningwhileforgoingmostofitsvirtues.TherulewouldstillnotsupportconditionalizinginthecaseofMeyerandtheHitchhikerfromabove.Furthertroubleistobeexpectedfromitsomis-sionofBroome's‘uptome’-beliefpremise(Broome2013:159-63,170f.).Andmostim-portantly,itseemssimplyirrationaltobasetheconclusiononthesetcomprisingofboththeought-beliefandtheintentionpremise:Theought-beliefbyitselfsufficientlyrational-izesadoptinganintentionto(AifC)—atanyratewhenA-ingifCis‘uptotheagent'.Theintentionpremiseisdispensable,andwouldthereforehavetobeeliminatedfromtherule.Ought-RestrictedConditionalizationthuscollapsesintoaconditionalversionofenkraticreasoning.

B. TheDisbeliefRestrictionFromthisinitialfailureanimportantlessonshouldbedrawn,towhichIshallgetback

belowingreaterdetail.Thesoughtlicensetoconditionalizecannotdependonanought-belief providingadditional rational support. Instead, the required sort of premisewillhavetoactasaconstraintontherationalityofconditionalizingone'sintention;apremisethatisnegativeinnature.Consider:

(I-5) Iintendthat(A) Ibelievethat¬(Ioughtthat¬(A)ifC) ∴Iintendthat(AifC)

ThesecondpremiseintroduceswhatIshallcallthedisbeliefrestriction.Eventhoughtherulecannotbeadoptedasitstands,itpointsthewayaheadtoatenableversionofRCON.

Themotivationfortheproposalshouldbeclearbynow.TheEnkraticDefensewasbasedonthefactthataninstanceofthefollowingschemesufficestoblockrationaladop-tionofanintentionto(AifC):

(15) IbelievethatIought¬(A)ifC

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–16–

Eventhoughabsenceofsuchought-beliefsdoesnotposeanexternalconstraintonconditionalizing,oneofthenegationsof(15)couldstillinternallyrestrictthecondition-alizationruleitself.Now,therearethreesuchnegations:

IbelievethatIoughtthat¬(¬(A))ifC ¬(IbelievethatIoughtthat¬(A)ifC) Ibelievethat¬(Ioughtthat¬(A)ifC)

Thefirstoptionyieldsthediscardedrule(I-4).TheoptionIsuggesttoelaborateisthethird,whichisbuiltinto(I-5).AsfarasIcansee,thesecondoptionwould(afteranalogouselaboration)cater to thedata justaswell. Ishallput itasidebecause itraisesworriesaboutreasoningwithnon-beliefsthatneednotbedealtwithhere.

In accounting for good-seemingandavoidingbad-seeming conditionalizations, thedisbeliefrestrictiontakesusabigstepforward.Toshowthis,letmeput(I-5)towork,firstinexplainingsomegood-seemingmoves.(Assumeforthemomentthatagentsarefullyrational.)

Example#1.SupposethatSchmidtisaskedwhetherheintendstogotothetheaterat7ifbythenthesunwillhaveset.Onrecallinghisreasonsforgoing,Schmidtwillcometobelievethatinthatcase,heoughttogo(ascanbeassumed).Hisought-beliefwillthencausehim30totacitlydisbelievethatheoughtnottogoifthesunwillhaveset.Thus,hewillbeinthepositiontoreasoncorrectlytowardintendingto(goifthesunwillhaveset),andthatispreciselywhattheaccountneedstopredict.

Example#2.Confrontedwiththehitchhiker’squestionwhethersheintendsto(take101ifitisabouttorain),Meyerfailstoseeanyreasonnottotake101,evenifitisabouttorain.Sincethedecisiontotake101wasunderdeterminedbyMeyer’sreasonsinthefirstplace,shethuscomestodisbelievethatsheoughtnottotake101ifitisabouttorain,andisthusinthepositiontoinferbywayof(I-5)anintentionto(take101ifitisabouttorain).ThisisanimportantresultbecauseitshowsthatGenuineConditionalizationcanyieldconclusionsbeyondthereachofbothinstrumentalandenkraticreasoning.

Thenextpointtobenotedisthatthankstothedisbeliefrestriction,(I-5)steersclearofmostbad-seemingconclusions.Assumeasthebasicscenariounderlyingthecasestofollowthat it isnoon, that(2:)Schmidt intendsto(gotothetheaterat7),andthatheintends(2)forthesolereasonthathebelievestheannouncedplaywillpleasehim.Hispresentattitudesthendefeasiblyentailthat,allthingsconsidered,heoughtto(goat7),andthisiswhathetacitlybelieves.

Example#3.IsSchmidtpermittedtoinferfrom(2)anintention(3:)to(goat7ifaquakewillhavedevastatedthecitybythen)?Itisnaturaltosupposethathetacitlybelievesheoughtnottogoifaquakeoccurs,whichrulesoutascribingtohimthedisbeliefrequiredtoavailof(I-5).Theinferenceisnotpermitted,andthisisthedesiredoutcome.

Example#4.IsSchmidtpermittedtoreasontowardanintentionto(goiftrafficjamswillforcehimtodeparthoursbeforetheplay)?Inexamplesofthiskind,itisnotentirelyclearwhatought-beliefstheagentholds,orwillcometoformincognitivelyprocessingtherespectivequestion.Inordertoapply(I-5)properly,weneedtoknowtheagent'srel-evantreasons,andhowtheyrelatetooneanotherbyherownlights.Inaddition,weneedaformalaccountthattellsus,giventhosereasonsandtheirinteractions,which(condi-tional)ought-beliefsitwillberationaloftheagenttoformorhave.Thetopicistoointri-catetobetreatedhere,sothatanadhocsuggestionseemsappropriate.Conditionaloughtclausescanbeconstruedbyanalogywithsuppositionalaccountsofconditionalassertionsandbeliefs.Theycanthenbeascribedtruth-conditionsinthefollowing,counterfactualmanner,whichlinksconditionaloughtwithdefeasiblelogic:

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–17–

(OGT) NoughtthatAifCiff,werethebeliefthatCaddedtoagentN’smentalstock,N’srevisedsetofattitudeswoulddefeasiblyentail31thatNoughtthatA.

Forthepresentpurpose,thisnutshellaccountmakesitsufficientlyclearwhatought-beliefsagentscouldrationallyarriveat,weretheytodeliberateaboutthematter.WithrespecttoSchmidt,weneedtoaskwhatwouldhappenifthebeliefthattrafficjamswilloccurwereaddedtohismentalstock.Obviously,hewouldbeprovided,inadditiontohisreasoninfavorofgoingtothetheater,withareasonnottogo.Whichofthesereasonswouldrebuttheotherwouldthendependontheirrespectiveweightsor(ifyouprefer)thepriorityorderingamongSchmidt’sreasons.Ifbyhisownlights,hispassionfortheplayoutweighsanyworriesabouttrafficjamshemayhave,hispleasurereasonwillpre-vail.Inthatcase,(I-5)willenablehimtoreasontowardanintentionto(goat7iftrafficjamsoccur).Noticethat,givensuchardentpassionfortheater, themovewouldnotbecrazy.OrelseassumeSchmidtwouldratherforgothepleasurethanhavethehassle.Thenhispleasurereasonwouldberebutted,hewouldcometobelieveheoughtnot togo iftraffic jams occur. Consequently, he would not be in the position to conditionalize—rightlyso,becauseinthatcaseitwouldbecrazy.

Example#5.Consider,bycontrast,conditionalizationtowardanintentionto(goat7ifbythen,thetheaterwillhavecollapsed).AddingtherespectivebelieftoSchmidt’smentalstockandrevisinghisattitudeswouldresultinabeliefthathewillnotbeabletogotothetheater(inthesenseofattendingaperformance).Sinceanagentcannotrationallyintendanactionsheall-outbelievesshewillnotperform,Schmidt’sought-(dis-)beliefsarenotevenrelevanttothecase.Whatblockshimfrombeingfullyrationalincomingtointendthat(AifC)hereistheintention-beliefinconsistencyhewouldincur(seeBratman1987:37f.).

Theseresultsareencouraging.Therestofthepaperwillhavetodealwithtwoseem-inglyproblematicsortsofupshots,though.

C. SuppressedconsiderationsAsitstands,(I-5)producescounter-intuitiveresultswhenreasoningwithirrationally

heldintentionsaspremises.Example#6.ConsideroncemoreGeorge’scaseofdistalakrasia.Georgehasformed

hisintention(7:)to(takeheroinat9)forreasonshewouldbyhisownlightsnotconsiderdecisive,werehewillingtoproperlytakethemintoaccount.Thistime,though,consideragood-seemingmove,namelyfrom(7)to:

(16) Georgeintendsthat(hetakesheroinat9ifbythenthesunwillhaveset)

TheConditionalityViewwas unable to block bad-seeming inferences based on anakraticpremise;thepresentaccountfailstopermitanakraticallybasedgood-seeminginference.ForGeorgecertainlydoesbelievethatheoughtnottotakeheroin,whetherthesunwillhavesetornot.Unlessheisoutrightinsane(andIamsuggestingheisnot),thisbeliefwillblockhimfromacquiringthedisbeliefrequiredby(I-5)totakehimto(16).

ThecounterexamplefeaturesabroadlyDavidsonianconstrualofakraticirrationality,whichsuggestsaremedyaswell.Agentssometimesbaseanintentiononapropersubsetofwhat,bytheirownlights,arereasonsfororagainstadoptingthatveryintention;theysuppresssomeoftheirreasons,asIshallsay.Astheexampleshows,thesortofought-beliefthatconstrainsconditionalizationcannotrequirethatonhypothesisC,thepractical

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–18–

conclusion¬(A)wouldbedefeasiblyentailedbytheentiretyoftheagent’sreasons. In-stead,weneedtofocusonthose‘unsuppressed’reasonswhichtheagentherselfiswillingproperlytotakeintoaccountinpracticaldeliberation.

Technically,thisisachievedintwosteps.LetMbeagentN’smentalstock,andletSbethesubsetofMwhichcomprisesoftheinternalreasonssuppressedbyN.Thenwecanfirstdefineapartialoughtoperatorbystating:32

(OGTʹ) Nought,allunsuppressedreasonsconsidered,toXifCiff(M∪{NbelievesthatC})\SafterattituderevisiondefeasiblyentailsthepracticalconclusiontoX.

Second,wecanamend(I-5)soastoavailofthenewpartialoperator:

(I-6) Iintendthat(A) Ibelievethat¬(Iought,allunsuppressedreasonsconsidered,that¬(A)ifC) ∴Iintendthat(AifC)

Forallthosecasesfromwhichreason-suppressionisabsent,(I-6)willproducethesameresultas(I-5).Whenitcomestoexamplessuchas#5,though,theweakenedoughtmakesadecisivedifference.Georgecanplausiblybeattributedtheatleasttacitbeliefthat,allunsuppressed reasons (and only these) considered, he ought to take heroin at 9—whetherornotthesunwillhaveset.Sohewillat leasttacitlydisbelieve thatheought(unsuppressedreasonsconsidered)nottotakeheroinifthesunwillhaveset.Hecanthusplausiblybeattributedthedisbeliefrequiredtoavailof(I-6),andthisistheintuitivelyrightresult.

(I-6)ismyfinalsuggestion.Andsinceapplyingtheruleamountstobasingtheconclu-sionstateonthesetcomprisingofallandonlythepremisestates,wearenowinapositiontoconjecturethattherationalpermissionwhichunderliesRCONis:

(RCP) Rationalitypermits( NintendsthatA∧ Nbelievesthat¬(sheought,allunsuppressedreasonsconsidered,that¬(A)ifC)

∧ Nintendsthat(AifC)∧ Nbasesherintentionto(AifC)onherintentionthatAandherdisbelief)

D. TherationaleofGenuineConditionalizationAsatisfactoryaccountofGenuineConditionalizationhasbeenreached.Someof its

upshots, however, can still seem counter-intuitive. But rather than threatening theachievedresult,theseupshotscanleadustoadeeperunderstandingofwhyRCONiscor-rectreasoning;orsoIamgoingtoargue.

Example#7.Schmidtplanstogotothetheaterbecausehebelievestheplaywillpleasehim.Next,heplaystheconditionalizationgame,andplayer2confrontshimwiththefol-lowingshockingfigment.“Justwhenabouttogotothetheater,youwillreceiveacallfrominsidethetheaterbuilding.Itwillbeyourchild,reportingindistressthatamajorearth-quakehasjustdestroyedtheroofstructureduringtheafternoonperformanceforkids.Youwilltherebygathertwocrucialpiecesofinformation:Therewillbenoplay(¬P),andyourchildistrappedunderthedebrisinsidethetheater(T).Doyouintendtogotothetheaterifthisstorywillcometrue?”

Onthepresentaccount,Schmidtisentitledtoavailof(I-6)andinfer:

(17) Iintendto(goat7if(¬P∧T))

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–19–

Hereiswhy:Nosuppressedconsiderationsbeinginvolved,Schmidtispermittedtodrawconclusion(17)justincasehedisbelievesheoughtnottogoif(¬P∧T).Andthatheatleasttacitlyentertainsthisdisbeliefisindeedwarranted.Granted:Inthefictitiouscir-cumstances,hisactualreasonforgoing—theexpectationtoseeaplay—wouldnotholdanymore;therewouldbenoplay.Yet,thesecondpartoftheconjunctionwouldgivehimasubstitutereasonforgoing:Hewouldneedtosavehischild.Hencehewillcometobe-lievethatheoughttogoif(¬P∧T),andthisinturnwillmakehimdisbelievethatheoughtnottogoif(¬P∧T).Thepresentaccountthereforepredictstherationalanswertoplayer2’squestiontobe“yes”.

Noticethatthisanswerisnotinitselfwrong.IfSchmidtredeliberatedfromscratchwhethertogoif(¬P∧T),hecouldnotendupwithanythingbut(17).Itisnotasthough(17)wereacrazyintention.Whatcanmaketheexamplelooktroublesomeistheinferen-tialpathonwhichSchmidtarrivesat(17).Itcanseemcrazyofhimtoinfer(17)from(apremisesetthatincludes)hispriorlyformedintentiontogotothetheater.Afterall,thereasonsonwhichhisintentionisactuallybasedwouldintheenvisagedcircumstancesbeannihilatedwithoutresidue;anditseemsasthoughSchmidtwouldnotintendtogofortherightreasons,werehetointendtoinconsequenceofapurelyhedonicdecision.

Theexamplethusdisplayswhatcanbecalledreasondisconnect.Hereisabriefanaly-sis.CallthosereasonswhichanagentactuallytakestosupportA-ingthe‘A-reasons’,andcallthosereasonswhichwouldsupportA-ingifCcameaboutthe‘C-hypotheticalreasonsforA-ing’.Thenreasondisconnect takesplace just incaseanagent’sA-reasonsdonotintersectwithherC-hypotheticalreasonsforA-ing.Thisiswhathappensintheexample,anditgivesrisetoaquitenaturalworry:Howcanitinsuchcasesberationallypermissi-bletobaseanintentionto(AifC)onone’sintentionto(A)?

Itmightbethoughtthattheproblemcanbecopedwithbyfurthertinkeringwiththeinferencerule.Isuggesttoresistthepullandreflectinsteadonwhypreciselyreasondis-connectlookstroubling.ItistemptingtothinkofRCONascorrectinsofaritreflectstheoccasionalrobustnessofA-reasons in the faceofC-hypothetical reasonsagainstA-ing.Yet, it iscrucial toseethatsuchrobustnessconsiderations,howeverwell theymaygowithenkraticreasoning,areclearlyoutoflinewiththeveryideaofRestrictedCondition-alization.IfRCONistofarebetterthanenkraticreasoning,itmustnotdrawontheforceofagents’A-reasons.AsMeyer'sBuridancaseillustrates,therewilloftenbenosuchrea-sonsatall;evenso,conditionalizingbasicallyisaplausiblemoveinsuchcases.

IcontendthatRCONissanctionedinsteadbythenormativeimportofanagent’sveryintentiontoA,asopposedtothereasonsinsupportofit.AsBratmanhasargued,aninten-tiontoA,onceformed,hasanormativeimportoverandabovetheimportofthereasonsforitsadoption.Thisismostconspicuouslyrevealedinsituationsinwhichthescarcityofdeliberativeresourcesmakesitirrationaltoreconsiderone’sintentioneventhoughthereasonswhichoriginallyrationalized itsadoptionhave,asamatterof fact,beenover-turned.Insuchconstellations,itcanberationaltoholdontointentionswhich,werethedecisiontobemadefromscratch,oneoughtbyone'sownlightsnottoadopt.33Intentionsthusdonotonlyphysicallytendtopersist;toacertaindegree,thereisalsorationalpres-sure to retain them once they are formed, and to abstain from reconsidering them.34RCON,properlyunderstood,revealsjustanotherfacetofthisnormativeimportofintend-ingassuch.

Inthisperspective,example#7doesnotlookthreateninganymore.ThatSchmidt’sinferencetoward(17)woulddisplayreasondisconnectdoesnotthreatenitscorrectnessbecauseheneednotthereinrelyontherobustnessofhispleasurereasontogo.Ifheavails

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–20–

ofRCON(ratherthanredeliberatingfromscratch,therebybypassinghistheater-inten-tion),hewillthereinberespectingthenormativeimportofhisactualintentiontogo.Hewillbe fullyrational indoingsobecausehebelieves that thisnormative import isnotoverturnedbyhisC-hypothetical reasons.That thesereasons includeanevenstrongerreasonforA-ing—hischildbeingindistress—thanhisactualhedonisticreason,issimplyadifferentmatter.

VII. Conclusion

Asithasturnedout,thereisnosupportforidentifyingflatintentionwiththemostlycrazystateofintending'nomatterwhat'.Fortheidentificationtoholdtrue,SimpleCon-ditionalization(SCON)wouldhavetobegoodreasoning.But(SCON)facesobviouscoun-terexampleswhichcannotbedefusedordeflectedbyanynaturalmeans.RestrictedCon-ditionalization (RCON), by contrast, has turnedout tobeonmuchmore solid footing.Here,anadditionalpremisemakessurethatincomingtointendthat(AifC)theagentdoesnotdeemintendingtoAabadideashouldCobtain.Inavailingofought-beliefs,RCONresemblesenkraticreasoning,butthereremainsacrucialdifference:Whileenkraticrea-soningmobilizespracticalreasonstorationalizeitsconclusions,RCONreliesonthenor-mativeimportofintendingassuch;practicalreasonsareinvoked,butasaconstraintonly.Asaconsequence,RCONyieldsmoreconclusionsthan(bothinstrumentaland)enkraticreasoning.Thisresultiswelcomebecausesomeconditionalizationmovesarerationallyunassailableandyetdictatedbyneitherreasonsnorgoals.

Onthesuggestedaccount,flatlyintendingtoAisintendingtoAinthosecircumstanceswhich,looselyspeaking,wouldnotmakeitabadideatoA.Butthen,tointendflatlytoAcannotmeanto intendtoA inanycircumstances; flat intentioncannotbea 'nomatterwhat'stance.TheConditionalityView'skeymotiveforsystematicallyreadingconditionalclausesintoordinaryintentionsthusevaporates.Itsadherentswerenottotallymistaken,tobesure.Tomymind,Ferreroandothershavestartedoutwithanaccurateobservation:Ourintentionsdonotnormativelycommitusinanywaytoactionsthatwouldbefoolishorimmoralbyourownlights.Wheretheyhavegonewrongisinexplainingthisobserva-tionbyappealtorestrictiveconditionswithinthecontentofintention.Ihave,bycontrast,beensuggestingtolocatethesoughtrestrictionwithinthecontentofabasingpermissionofrationality;apermissionthatshapes the inferentialrolecharacteristicof intentions,thusreflectingafeatureofthestateofintendingassuch.Asaconsequence,asimplerpic-tureofagencyregainscredibility;apictureaccordingtowhicheverydayintentionsareinthemselvesjustassimple,wieldyandunsophisticatedastheypresentthemselvestouswhenweform,revise,orexecutethem,orcommunicatethemtoothers.35

1 TheviewisimplicitinMeiland1970:18f.andGrice1971.Foranexplicitelaboration,seeBratman1979and,morerecently,Ferrero2009andKlass2009:111,124.Analogousclaimshavebeenmadewithre-gardtodesire,seeMcDaniel/Bradley2008:280,282;Lycan2012:209,andFara2013.Parfit1987:151hasadvancedthesomewhatrelatedviewthatmostdesiresareimplicitlyconditionalontheirownper-sistence;seeMcDaniel/Bradley2008:270.

2 I.e.aslongasCiscompossiblewithA.3 TheproponentsoftheConditionalityViewhavenotbeenoutspokenaboutwhatprecisely,ontheirview,

makesunconditionalintentionscrazy;usuallytheclaimisputforwardwithdirectappealtointuitions.

Notes

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–21–

Butsincetheyproposeaconditionalviewofintentionastheremedy,myreadingofthe'nomatterwhat'clauseshouldbeacceptabletothemaswell.Cf.Klass2009:107;Ferrero2009:700.

4 Inwhatfollows,AandCstandproxyforfull-fledged,self-standingpropositions.TheA-termwillusuallyinvolveaself-representationoftheintendingsubjectasherself.

5 Theexternal/internaldistinctionisdrawnbyCartwright1990:235;seealsoFerrero2009:701f.and,fordesire,McDaniel/Bradley2008:272,whodiscern(read:internally)conditionalfrom(read:exter-nally)hypotheticaldesire.Asthelatterauthorspointout,aconditionaldesireneednotbeconditionalonitsownpersistence(cf.Parfit1987:151);thesameholdsforintention.

6 Therearevariousreasonstobecarefulhere.McDaniel/Bradley2008havearguedthatconditionalde-siresandintentionsareattitudestowardtwopropositionsratherthanone;andinlinguistics,AngelikaKratzer’s‘restrictorview’offersahighlyunifiedaccountofif-clausesingeneralbysuggestingthattheyservetorestrictthemodalbaseofsome(attimescovert)modaloperator;seech.4ofKratzer2012.

7 Onissuesaboutintentionswithinternalnecessaryconditions,seeKlass2009:120-24.8 Forthedetails,seeBroome2013:159-170,262,264.9 Cf.Broome2013:159-63,170f.,290.10 Cf.Broome2013:246-48,255.Broomedefendsafirst-orderaccountofreasoningaccordingtowhich

whatisusuallyoperatedoninactivereasoningarenotattitudes,butpairsofpropositionsandattitudemarkers, jointly constituting ‘marked contents’; see ibid.: 251f. For the sake of greater convenience,(COR)operatesonattitudes,butIdonotintendtotakeastanceonwhetherreasoningis‘first’or‘higher-order’.

11 ‘Y1...Yn∴X’willserveasanalternativerulenotation.12 Cf.Broome2013:225.Noticethatbasingpermissionsonthisconstrualof‘basing’arepermissionsto

performactsofattitude-construction.Broome’sbasingpermissions,bycontrast,arepermissionstobebasedratherthantobase,asisclearfromthetemporalpatterndisplayedbytheircontents.Cf.ibid.:187.

13 Iamgratefultoananonymousrefereeforhavingbroughtthepossibilityofsuchanaccounttomyatten-tion.

14 NoticethatP⊃(C⊃P)isatautology,andwillthereforevalidatetriviallyinHintikka-stylebeliefsemanticsaspresentede.g.inHendricks/Symons, ‘EpistemicLogic’,sec.I.Onclosureprinciplesforbelief,morewillbesaidinsectionV.D.below.

15 Cf.thetwomoresophisticatedversionsinFerrero2009:723.16 Ferreroadmitscertainexceptions,suchasfanaticsandagentspursuinganabsolutelypraiseworthygoal;

seeFerrero2009:727,730.Thesecanbeputasidehere.17 SeeFerrero2009:720,723.18 Itseemstobearequirementofrationalitythat¬((NintendsthatX)∧(NintendsthatY)∧(Nbelieves

thatwithat leastmetaphysicalnecessity, ifXthennotY)).ThisgoesbeyondBroome’srespectivere-quirementofintentionconsistency;cf.Broome2013:156.

19 Foranaccountofthedifference,seeMele2007.20 Foranelaboratedaccountofinstrumentalreasoning,seeBroome2013:159-170,262,264.Iamsimpli-

fyingmattershere;against thebackgroundofBroome'saccount, (I-1)mustbeconsideredenthyme-matic.

21 Foranaccuratenon-conditionalversionthatoperateson‘markedcontents’,seeBroome2013:290.Ac-cordingtoBroome,mis‘uptome’iffwereImyselfnottointendm,becauseofthat,mwouldnotbeso.For the details, see Broome 2013: 159-63, 170f.—Why appeal to a conditional version of Broome'sEnkratic inferencerule? Ifweconstruedbothconditional intentionsandconditionalought-beliefsasattitudestowardsconditionalpropositions,wecouldmakedowithBroome'srule,thefirstpremiseofwhichruns:“IbelievethatIoughtthatP”.Wecouldthensubstituteaconditional-propositionsignifier“(AifC)”for“P”,whichwouldgiveusthesoughtinferentialroutetowardsaconditionalintention.Yet,itisfarfromevidentthatinreportsofconditionalintention,theintentionoperatortakesaconditionalpropositionasitsargument,andthesameworrycouldofcourseberaisedaboutconditionaloughtstate-ments.Thedifficulty is circumvented,however,whenwe leave thescopeof ‘ought’asambiguousasfoundinnaturallanguage,stickwithourconventiontoread“Nintendsthat(AifC)”asnotcommittingustoaparticularstanceontheconditional-propositionissue,andstateanew,self-standing,conditionalversionoftheenkraticrule.

22 ThisisanadaptationofthesimplifiedenkraticrequirementofrationalityinBroome2013:171.23 SeeDavidson1980:92-102.Ishalluntiehisaccountofunconditionalintentionfrommostofitsoriginal

context:i.e.thequestionofwhetherintentionsareakindofbelief.ForadiscussionofthisaspectseeVelleman1989:114-24;seealsoFerrero2009:732f.,n.13.

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–22–

24 SeeDavidson1980:100.Onemightthinktheviewhasaproblemtoaccountforgenuinelyconditional

intention—asortofintentionthatDavidsonclearlywantstoadmit(seeibid.:94).Butthereisnoprob-lemhere.Aconditionalintentionisanintentionto(AifC),andhisproposalmapsthissmoothlyontojudgingthat(AifC)isunconditionallydesirable.

25 Lateron,heseemstohavechangedhisviewonthematter:„Icannotimaginesomeoneintending,evenatthestart,tobuyanycar.Evenifitwerewiredtoexplode?SurelytherearemanythingsIcouldeasilyspecifyinadvance,andwouldifIwereordering,say,fromacatalogue.However,thereisneverapointatwhichIcouldcompletelyspecifythecontentofmyintention[…]”,Davidson1999:498.

26 ThefollowinginterpretationhasbeensuggestedbyBratman1999:213-19.27 “[…]thereisnothingabsurdinmyjudgingthatanyactionofmineintheimmediatefuturethatisthe

eatingofsomethingsweetwouldbedesirablegiventherestofwhatIbelieveabouttheimmediatefuture”,Davidson1980:99.“Tointendtoperformanactionis,onmyaccount,toholdthatitisdesirabletoper-formanactionofacertainsortinthelightofwhatonebelievesisandwillbethecase”,ibid.:100.

28 Noticethat(BFR),althoughcloselyrelatedto,isnotasubstitutioninstanceofBratman’sintention-beliefconsistencyconstraint,whichcan,forthesakeofcomparison,berenderedas:Rationalityrequires((Nbelievesthat¬P)⊃¬(NintendsthatP)).Cf.Bratman1987:37f.Whatpreventsthederivationofarelevantnormfromthelatteristhatbecauseofthefirstnegationsign,substituting“(AifC)”forthefirstoccur-renceofPmakessenseonlyif‘(AifC)’denotesaproposition.

29 Expressivistswilldisagreewiththis.Ifought-utterancesaretreatedasexpressingsomee.g.volitionalattitude,mymainobjectionagainst(I-4)appliesdirectlyto(I-3):IfIoughtthatAifC,thisbyitselfsuffi-cientlyrationalizesadoptinganintentionthat(AifC).

30 Onsub-personalprocesseswhichensureconsistencybyautomaticallyerasingbeliefs,seee.g.Broome2013:77f.,189,268.Suchrevisiondispositionsbelongtothefoundationsofourrationalcapacity.

31 JohnHorty’stheoryofdefeasiblereasoningiswellsuitedforfleshingoutthisproposalbecauseheiden-tifiesconclusionsofpracticaldefeasiblereasoninggenerallywithunconditionaloughts;seeHorty2012:18,65ff.Hislogicthusmeshesnicelywithmyaccountofconditionalought.Itakeit,however,thatprac-ticalreasoning(defeasibleornot)canalsoyield intentionsthemselvesas itsproperconclusions;seeBroome2013:250ff.

32 ‘A∖B’denotesthesetdifferenceofAandB,and‘A∪B’theirunion.ItakeitthatconditionaloughtisafourplaceoperatorOUGHT(N,X,C,T)whereTstandsforthe‘thingsconsidered’,butadefinitionofpartialoughtingeneralwillnotbeneeded.

33 Foranexample,seethesecondMondalecaseinBratman1987:74f.SeealsoBratman2012:74,79f.34 Bratmanhasoutlinedthisrationalaspectofthe‘inertia’ofintentionsintermsofasystemofrationality

constraintsonreconsideringone’sintentions;seeBratman1987:16,60-110.Thenatureofthesepres-sures isstillunderdebate;seeBratman2012;Ferrero2012,2014.Problemsstemfromthefactthatdroppingone’sintentionbeforeitsexecutionisoftenperfectlyrational.Itakeit,however,thattherearegenuinelydiachronicrationalpressurestowardretainingone’s intentions—eventhoughIagreewithFerrerothatthesepressuresneverreachmorethanminimallyintothefuture.SeeFerrero2014:332;Gillessen2015.

35 Thisworkwassupportedbyaresearchstipendinthepost-docprogramofGermanAcademicExchangeService(DAAD).Inwriting,Ihavebeenabletoprofitenormouslyfromdiscussionwithandencourage-mentbyMichaelBratman,JohnBroome,MarkCrimmins,andLucaFerrero.Forveryhelpfulcomments,adviceandhintsIamindebtedtoBartKamphorst,SamuelAsarnow,NathanHauthalerandCarlosNuñez.Iwouldfurthermoreliketothankorganizersandaudienceoftheworkshop“VarietiesofAgency”attheStanfordHumanitiesCenterfortheopportunitytodiscussanearlydraft,andananonymousrefereeoftheJPRforscrutinythathelpedclarifysomecrucialpoints.

References

Bratman,Michael.1979.“SimpleIntention.”PhilosophicalStudies36:245–59.———.1987.Intention,Plans,andPracticalReason.Cambridge,MA:HarvardUniversityPress.———.1999.“Davidson'sTheoryofIntention.”ReprintedinFacesofIntention.SelectedEssaysonIn-

tentionandAgency.Cambridge,NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,209-224.———.2012.“Time,rationality,andself-governance.”PhilosophicalIssues22:73–88.Broome,John.2013.Rationalitythroughreasoning.Malden,MA:Wiley-Blackwell.

FINALDRAFT,PLEASECITEPUBLISHEDVERSION:DOI:10.5840/jpr20171011115

–23–

Cartwright,J.P.W.1990.“ConditionalIntention.”PhilosophicalStudies60:233–55.Crimmins,Mark.1992.“TacitnessandVirtualBeliefs”.Mind&Language7:240–63.Davidson,Donald.1980.“Intending.”InEssaysonActionsandEvents.Oxford:ClarendonPress,83–102.———.1999.“ReplytoEdnaUllmann-Margalit.”InThephilosophyofDonaldDavidson,ed.L.E.Hahn.

Chicago:OpenCourt,497–99.Fara,DeliaGraff.2013.“SpecifyingDesires.”Noûs47:250–72.Ferrero,Luca.2009.“ConditionalIntentions.”Noûs43:700–41.———.2012.“DiachronicConstraintsofPracticalRationality.”PhilosophicalIssues22:144–64.———.2014.“DiachronicStructuralRationality.”Inquiry57:311–36.Gillessen, Jens.2015.“DoIntentionsSetUpRationalDefaults?Commitments,Reasons,andtheDia-

chronicDimensionofRationality.”PacificPhilosophicalQuarterly.DOI:10.1111/papq.12147

Grice,HerbertPaul.1971.“IntentionandUncertainty.”ProceedingsoftheBritishAcademy57:263–79.Harman,Gilbert.1986.ChangeinView.PrinciplesofReasoning.Cambridge,MA;London,England:MIT

Press.Hendricks,Vincent,andJohnSymons.2015.“EpistemicLogic.”InStanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy,

ed.E.Zalta.Fall2015Edition.http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/logic-epistemic/

Horty,John.2012.Reasonsasdefaults.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.Klass,Gregory.2009.“AConditionalIntenttoPerform.”LegalTheory15:107–47.Kratzer,Angelika.2012.Modalsandconditionals.Oxford,NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.Lycan,WilliamG.2012.“DesireConsideredasaPropositionalAttitude.”PhilosophicalPerspectives26:

201–15.McDaniel,Kris,andBenBradley.2008.“Desires.”Mind117:267–302.Meiland,J.W.1970.TheNatureofIntention.London:Methuen.Mele,AlfredR.2007.“PersistingIntentions”.Noûs41:735–757.Parfit,Derek.1987.ReasonsandPersons.Oxford:ClarendonPress.Velleman,David.1989.PracticalReflection.Princeton,NJ:PrincetonUniversityPress.