23
Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Truth-telling in Medicine

And: The Justification of Paternalism

Page 2: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Critical Analyses

Difficult question!! Veatch: As a rule is strongly in favor of

almost unlimited patient autonomy-- BUT this reading was taken from a case book where Veatch was trying to lay out both sides of the issue and not take a stand himself

Page 3: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Critical analyses cont.

Gawande: Several “mixed signals”– Title of paper– “Lazaroff” example– Mammogram example– “Mr. Howe” example

Which is the “real” Gawande?

Page 4: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Critical Analyses: take home message Need to read the article at least once

without a highlighter (don’t ignore specific words and phrases but rather put them in overall context)

Be sure to ask how each paragraph fits into overall scheme of author’s argument

Page 5: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

TRVTH

Page 6: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Traditional approaches to truth NO general duty to disclose Truth as medicine; bad news can be

harmful or fatal Subsumed under general duty of

beneficence or “do no harm” (nonmaleficence)

Page 7: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

How culturally bound is current US view? Only a tiny slice of the entire history of

medicine is dominated by an autonomy ethic of truth-telling

Majority of other world cultures still seem reluctant to embrace this ethic

BUT at least some traditional cultures are moving in a “Western” direction (e.g. Japan)

Page 8: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

“Truth-dumping”

Violation of beneficence-- usually perceived by patient as cruel and uncaring

Violation of autonomy?– Does cruel disclosure make patient a

better (freer) decision-maker?– Does patient get a voice in how truth is

told?

Page 9: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Reasonable Mix of Beneficence and Respect for Autonomy?

Robert Buckman, How to Break Bad News (Baltimore, Johns Hopkins U. Press, 1992)

Page 10: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Truth Protocol (Buckman)

Pick a good time and setting and assemble right people

Find out how much the patient already knows

Find out how much the patient wants to know

Page 11: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Protocol (cont.)

Share the information the patient seeks – in sensitive manner– in appropriate “chunks”

Respond to patient’s feelings Planning and follow-through

Page 12: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Lessons from Buckman

Effective truth-telling is heavy on listening and light on talking

Most patients want to know more and can handle it; a few don’t want to

Giving patient greater role in setting agenda is respectful of autonomy and is also compassionate and caring

Page 13: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Seldom the Question

“Should we tell the patient the truth, or conceal it from her?”

Page 14: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Usually the Questions

“When to tell?” “How much to tell?” “What exact words to use?” “Whom should be there with the

patient?” “What comes next?”

Page 15: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

When Can Paternalism Be Justified?

Atul Gawande, “Whose Body Is It Anyway?” New Yorker, Oct. 4, 1999

Page 16: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

“Weak” Paternalism

Patient lacks important dimensions of capacity to make autonomous decisions– Child– Dementia– Mentally ill

Generally easier to justify

Page 17: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

“Strong” Paternalism

Patient appears to have full capacities for autonomous decision-making

Provider nevertheless feels that decision is mistaken and will cause great harm

Usually seen as much harder to justify-- threat to respect for autonomy

Page 18: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Gawande’s defense of strong paternalism Dependent upon arguments in: Carl E.

Schneider, The Practice of Autonomy (Oxford U. Press, 1998)

Page 19: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Schneider’s Approach

Read ethics literature Read legal cases Read books written by people about

their own experiences with illness (pathographies)

Interviewed patients in a chronic renal unit

Page 20: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Schneider’s Conclusions

Some people wish to exercise autonomy as per the “ideal case” in ethics literature today

Many do not wish to and would wish to defer or delegate part or all of major health decisions to others including physician

Page 21: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Schneider (cont.)

The people who wish not to choose often have very rational reasons for this preference– Weakness and fatigue– Lack of knowledge or understanding– Awareness of problems in own thinking

process– Avoidance of guilt

Page 22: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

What Does “Respect for Autonomy” Require?

Forcing each patient into “ideal autonomy” mold regardless of preferences?

Allowing each patient to select the degree to which she wants to be informed and to participate?

Page 23: Truth-telling in Medicine And: The Justification of Paternalism

Gawande’s “Mr. Howe”

Traditional argument often offered as justification for strong paternalism-- “Thank you” test

Is this an adequate ethical justification? Is Gawande a “good physician” or an

arrogant, paternalistic physician (or both)?