34
The Kantian (Non)-Conceptualism Debate Colin McLear University of Nebraska–Lincoln [email protected] July 21, 2014 Abstract One of the central debates in contemporary Kant scholarship concerns whether Kant en- dorses a “conceptualist” account of the nature of sensory experience. Understanding the debate is crucial for getting a full grasp of Kant’s theory of mind, cognition, perception, and epistemology. This paper situates the debate in the context of Kant’s broader theory of cog- nition and surveys some of the major arguments for conceptualist and non-conceptualist interpretations of his critical philosophy. 1 Introduction O NE OF THE CENTRAL TOPICS OF DEBATE in contemporary Kant scholarship has been whether Kant endorses a position concerning the nature of sensory expe- rience called “conceptualism.” As a first approximation, conceptualism about experience is the claim that the capacity for conscious sensory experience of the ob- jective world depends, at least in part, on the repertoire of concepts possessed by the experiencing subject, insofar as they are exercised in acts of synthesis by the cognitive faculty which Kant terms the “understanding” [Verstand]. Exactly how we should under- stand this dependence relation, as well as the notion of experience that it presupposes, is something we will discuss in much further detail below. The historical question as to whether Kant endorsed conceptualism has also been linked to the philosophical ques- tion as to the commitments of the conceptualist position and whether it is, in the end, a tenable one. For the purposes of this article I shall focus primarily on the historical question, and thus I will largely ignore issues in the philosophy of mind and perception literature that have arisen independently of the scholarly debate concerning Kant. 1 The argument of this paper proceeds as follows. §2 briefly sketches the fundamen- tal elements of Kant’s theory of cognition. §3 articulates several major considerations which help to define the non-conceptualist interpretation of Kant. In §4 I elaborate the conceptualist interpretation of Kant. I present and to some extent revise what I take to be the core interpretive commitments of the conceptualist position. §5 discusses several major objections to conceptualism and non-conceptualism, as well as a central issue of contemporary interest—viz. the so-called “Myth of the Given” and its connection to the conceptualism debate. I then summarize the argument of the paper. 1 For a useful overview of the contemporary literature see Gunther (2003); Siegel (2010); Van Cleve (2012). 1

The Kantian (Non)-Conceptualism Debate - PhilPapersThe Kantian (Non)-Conceptualism Debate Colin McLear University of Nebraska–Lincoln [email protected] July 21,2014 ... Attempt to Introduce

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    10

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebateColinMcLearUniversityofNebraska–[email protected], 2014

Abstract

OneofthecentraldebatesincontemporaryKantscholarshipconcernswhetherKanten-dorsesa“conceptualist”accountofthenatureofsensoryexperience. UnderstandingthedebateiscrucialforgettingafullgraspofKant’stheoryofmind, cognition, perception, andepistemology. ThispapersituatesthedebateinthecontextofKant’sbroadertheoryofcog-nitionandsurveyssomeofthemajorargumentsforconceptualistandnon-conceptualistinterpretationsofhiscriticalphilosophy.

1 Introduction

ONE OF THE CENTRAL TOPICS OF DEBATE incontemporaryKantscholarshiphasbeenwhetherKantendorsesapositionconcerningthenatureofsensoryexpe-riencecalled“conceptualism.” Asafirstapproximation, conceptualismabout

experienceistheclaimthatthecapacityforconscioussensoryexperienceoftheob-jectiveworlddepends, atleastinpart, ontherepertoireofconceptspossessedbytheexperiencingsubject, insofarastheyareexercisedinactsofsynthesisbythecognitivefacultywhichKanttermsthe“understanding”[Verstand]. Exactlyhowweshouldunder-standthisdependencerelation, aswellasthenotionofexperiencethatitpresupposes,issomethingwewilldiscussinmuchfurtherdetailbelow. ThehistoricalquestionastowhetherKantendorsedconceptualismhasalsobeenlinkedtothephilosophicalques-tionastothecommitmentsoftheconceptualistpositionandwhetheritis, intheend,atenableone.

ForthepurposesofthisarticleI shallfocusprimarilyonthehistoricalquestion, andthusI willlargelyignoreissuesinthephilosophyofmindandperceptionliteraturethathavearisenindependentlyofthescholarlydebateconcerningKant.1

Theargumentofthispaperproceedsasfollows. §2brieflysketchesthefundamen-talelementsofKant’stheoryofcognition. §3articulatesseveralmajorconsiderationswhichhelptodefinethenon-conceptualistinterpretationofKant. In§4I elaboratetheconceptualistinterpretationofKant. I presentandtosomeextentrevisewhatI taketobethecoreinterpretivecommitmentsoftheconceptualistposition. §5discussesseveralmajorobjectionstoconceptualismandnon-conceptualism, aswellasacentralissueofcontemporaryinterest—viz. theso-called“MythoftheGiven”anditsconnectiontotheconceptualismdebate. I thensummarizetheargumentofthepaper.

1 Forausefuloverviewofthecontemporaryliteraturesee Gunther(2003); Siegel(2010); Van Cleve(2012).

1

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

2 A SketchofKant’sTheoryofCognition

Kant’sconceptionofourmentaleconomyisbasicallytripartite, consistingofsensations[Empfindungen], intuitions [Anschauungen] and concepts [Begriffe].2 These are allvarietiesofwhatKantcalls“representation”[Vorstellung].3

Inwhatisgenerallycalledthe“stepladder”[Stufenleiter]passagefromtheTranscen-dentalDialecticofthefirst Critique, oneofthefewplacesintheKantiancorpuswhereheexplicitlydiscussesthemeaningsofandrelationsbetweenhistechnicalterms, Kantdefinesandclassifiesvarietiesofrepresentation.

The category is representation (representatio) in general. Under itstand representations with consciousness (perceptio). A perception[Wahrnehmung], that relates solely to a subject as a modification ofits state, is sensation (sensatio). An objective perception is cognition(cognitio). This is either intuition or concept (intuitus vel conceptus).Thefirstrelatesimmediatelytotheobjectandissingular; thesecondismediate, conveyed by amark, which can be common tomany things(A320/B376–7).4

AsKant’sdiscussionhereindicates, thecategoryofrepresentationcontainssensation,intuition, and concept. The faculty that provides sensory representations is called“sensibility” [Sinnlichkeit]. Sensibility generates representations based on being af-fectedeitherbyentitiesdistinctfromthesubjectorbythesubjectherself. Thisisincontrasttothefacultyof“understanding”[Verstand]whichgeneratesrepresentations“spontaneously”—i.e. withoutadvertancetoaffection.

2 Thereareothersignficantrepresentationalkinds, suchas schemata and ideas, buttheinterpretivetradi-tionhasfocusedprimarilyonsensations, intuitions, andconcepts. I followthattraditioninmydiscussionhere. Onecould, however, objectthatthedebateisnotwell-formed, andemphasizetheimportanceofincluding, e.g., schemata, inthediscussionoftherelationshipbetweenconceptpossessionandper-ceptualexperience. Fordiscussionofschematainthegenerationofperceptual“images”see Matherne(Unpublished); cf. Griffith(2012); Williams(2012).

3 Wemightquestionwhetheritisbesttotranslate“Vorstellung”as“representation.” Thereasonforhesi-tationhaslargelytodowiththebaggagewhichtheterm“representation”carrieswithincontemporaryphilosophy. Itisoftencharacterizedasan“inner,” causallyrelevant, andperhapsfunctionallydefinedstate, whosesemanticcontentallowsittoplayaroleinthecognitivelifeofsubject. InwhatfollowsIwilltranslate“Vorstellung”as“representation”butI wishtohighlightheretheimportanceofnotsimplyequatingKant’suseof“Vorstellung”witharepresentationalisttheoryofperception. ForanargumentthatKantdoes not endorsesuchatheorysee McLear(Forthcomingb)and§3.1below; cf. Gomes(2014).

4 QuotationsfromKant’sworkarefromtheAkademieAusgabe, withthefirstCritique citedbythestandardA/B editionpagination, andtheotherworksbyvolumeandpage. TranslationsarefromtheCambridgeEditionsoftheWorksofImmanuelKant, generaleditorsPaulGuyerandAllenWood. I have, onsomeoccasions, madeslightmodificationswithoutfurthercomment. Specifictextsareabbreviatedasfollows:

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 2

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Kantclaimsthatall therepresentationsgeneratedviasensibilityarestructuredbytwo“forms”ofintuition—spaceandtime—andthatallsensoryaspectsofourexperi-encearetheir“matter”(A20/B34). ThesimplestwayofunderstandingwhatKantmeansby“form”hereis thatallperceivableswillbesuchas toeitherhavespatial features(e.g. extension, shape, location), ortemporalfeatures(e.g. beingsuccessiveorsimul-taneous).5 Sotheformalelementofanempiricalintuition, orsenseperception, willalwaysbeeitherspatialortemporal, whilethematerialelementisalwayssensory(inthesenseofdeterminingthephenomenalor“whatitislike”characterofexperience),andtiedtooneormoreofthefivesenses, orthefeelingsofpleasureanddispleasure.

Kanttiesthetwoformsofintuitiontotwodistinctspheres, theinnerandtheouter.Theouterconcernsthespatialworldofparticularmaterialobjectswhiletheinnercon-cernstemporallyorderedstatesofmind. Spaceisthustheformof“outersense”whiletimeistheformof“innersense”(A22/B37; cf. An7:154). IntheTranscendentalAes-thetic, Kantisprimarilyconcernedwith“pure”[rein]intuition, andoftenonlyspeaksinpassingofthesenseperceptionofphysicalbodies(e.g. A20–1/B35). However, Kantmoreclearlylinksthefivesenseswithintuitioninthe1798 AnthropologyfromaPrag-maticPointofView, inthesectionentitled“OntheFiveSenses.”

Sensibility inthecognitivefaculty(thefacultyofintuitiverepresentations)contains twoparts: sense and the imagination…But the senses, on theotherhand, aredividedinto outer and inner sense(sensusinternus); thefirstiswherethehumanbodyisaffectedbyphysicalthings, thesecondiswherethehumanbodyisaffectedbythemind(An7:153).

An: AnthropologyfromaPragmaticPointofViewCJ: CritiqueofJudgmentG: GroundworkfortheMetaphysicsofMoralsJL: JäscheLogicLL: LecturesonLogicNM: AttempttoIntroducetheConceptofNegativeMagnitudesintoPhilosophyOD:OnaDiscoveryWherebyanyNewCritiqueofPureReasonistobeMadeSuperfluousbyanOlderOnePr: ProlegomenatoanyFutureMetaphysicsR: NotesandFragments

5 TherearecomplicationsherethatI cannotgointo, concerningwhetherorhowspatialobjectsmightberepresentedasstandingintemporalrelationswithoneanothergiventhat“Timecannomorebeintuitedexternallythanspacecanbeintuitedassomethinginus”(A22-3/B37). Kantgoesontosaythatouterobjectsaretemporallyrelatedonly“mediately”, invirtueoftheirrepresentationsbeingtemporallyrelatedininnersense(A34/B50-1). Thus, thoughouterobjectsmaybesaidtostandintemporalrelations,timeisnotanaprioriconditionoftheappearanceofanouterobjectinthewaythatspaceis. Whetherthismeansthatobjectsinspaceonly seem tobeintime, invirtueoftheirrepresentationsbeingintuitedasstandingintemporalrelationsininnersense, goesbeyondwhatI candiscusshere. Fordiscussionsee Van Cleve(1999), ch. 5; Brook(2013).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 3

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Kantcharacterizes intuitiongenerally in termsof twocharacteristics—viz. imme-diacy [Unmittelbarkeit]and particularity [Einzelheit](cf. A19/B33, A68/B93; JL 9:91).Thisisincontrasttothemediacyandgenerality[Allgemeinheit]characteristicofcon-ceptualrepresentation(A68/B93; JL 9:91).

Kantcontrasts theparticularityof intuitionwith thegeneralityofconcepts in the“stepladder”passage(seethefirstquoteabove). Butthespecificremarkhemakesisthataconceptisrelatedtoitsobjectvia“amark, whichcanbecommontomanythings”(A320/B377)andthissuggeststhatintuition, incontrasttoconcepts, putsasubjectincognitivecontactwithfeaturesofanobjectthatarenothadbyotherthings.6 Spatio-temporalpropertiesseemlikeexcellentcandidatesforsuchfeatures.7 Butpehapsanynon-repeatable, non-universalfeatureofaperceivedobjectwilldo.8

Doestheoccurrenceofanintuitioncountashavinganexperience, inourcontem-porarysenseofacognitivelysignificantmentaleventorstatewithaparticular(sense-modal)phenomenalcharacter?9 Moregenerally, doesKant’susageoftermslike“per-ception”[Wahrnehmung]and“experience”[Erfahrung]cleanlymatchupwithours?Givenhowslipperythesetermsare, evenintheireverydayusage, weshouldbesome-whatcautiousinthinkingthattheydo. Atleasttwoworriesloomlargehere. First, wemightworrythatdisputesconcerningthenecessaryconditionsofhavinga“perception”oran“experience”aremerelyverbal. Second, wemightworrythattheconcepts<per-ception>and<experience>arenotwell-defined, andthusthatnosubstantivedisputeshouldhangoneitherof them. For thepurposesof thispaper, I shall take thecon-cepts<perception>and<experience>assufficientlywell-definedthatwecancredibly

6 Thereisafurthercontroversyhereaswhethertheimmediacyofintuitioniscompatiblewithanintuition’srelatingtoanobjectbymeansofmarksorwhetherrelationbymeansofmarksentailsmediacy, andthusthatonlyconceptsrelatetoobjectsbymeansofmarks. See Smit(2000)fordiscussion.

7 Thisistrueatleastifweassumethatspatio-temporallocationissufficienttoindividuateonethingfromanother. CertainlyKantthoughtthisthecase; cf. B327-8.

8 Forexample, intuitionmaygiveasubjectperceptualaccesstothetropescharacterizinganobject. Forthesuggestionofaviewalongtheselinessee Smit(2000); Grüne(2009), 50, 66-70.

9 A noteabouttheuseof“cognitive”here. Thereisadifferencebetweenmentalstateswhichpossessphe-nomenalcharacteristicsbutnoseemingobjectivecognitivefeatures, suchaswhathappensin“seeingstars”orbeingpokedintheeye, etc., andstatesthatarebothphenomenallyrichandcognitive, suchashavingaperceptualexperienceasofsomeobjectinone’senvironment, suchasatreeoranimal.Thereis, ofcourse, aseriousquestionastowhetherorhowthesetwokindsofstatesmightberelated.I shalltakeitthatKant’susageof“intuition”ismeanttodesignatea cogntive stateratherthanastatewhichmerelypossessesphenomenalcharacter. Thelatterseemstomostconsistentlybedesignatedbytheterm“sensation”[Empfindung], ormoreprecisely, by“feeling”[Gefühl]. ThisisespeciallyclearinKant’sdiscussionofsensationandfeelinginthethird Critique; cf. CJ 5:189, 203-6. Whetherandhowsuchcognitiveandnon-cognitivestatesarerelatedisacomplexissue, andwe’lltouchonitfurtherinthediscussionofconceptualismbelow.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 4

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

disputeoverthenecessaryconditionsfortheirinstantiation.10 ButI dothinkthatitisnecessarytosaysomethingaboutthepossibilityofamerelyverbaldisputeconcerningtheconditionsfortheoccurrenceofaperceptualexperience.

Kantobviouslymakesadistinctionbetween“experience”[Erfahrung]and“intuition”[Anschauung]. Heisclearthat“experience,” inhissenseofan“empiricalcognition”[empirischeErkenntnis], includesconceptual synthesis, sincesuchsynthesis iswhatbindsthevariouselementsofanempiricalcognitiontogethersuchthattheyarenon-arbitrarilyconnected (cf. B12, B161, B201, B218, B233).11 Asa result, wecannotunderstandthe(non)-conceptualismdebateasconcerning“experience”inKant’ssenseoftheterm. Non-conceptualistinterpretersallconcedethatKant’susageof“experience”[Erfahrung]and“empiricalcognition”[empirischeErkenntnis]typicallyismeantinawaythatassumessomesortofcognitivecontributionbytheunderstanding.

ThedifficultiesthatresultintryingtopindownKant’suseof“experience”[Erfahrung]havenotgoneunnoticed in the literature.12 Forexample, HannahGinsborghasar-guedthatKant’sargumentthattheunderstandingmustbeactiveinthegenerationorconstitutionof“Erfahrung”ispotentiallyambiguousbetweendesignatingsensemodalspecific states of phenomenal consciousness—”sense impressions“—and full-blownperceptual judgments. But itseemsclear thatKanthimself tookthe terms”intuition”[Anschauung], “perception”[Wahrnehmung], and“experience”[Erfahrung]todesig-natedifferentthings.13 Intuitionisarelationtoan“undetermined”[unbestimmt]ob-jectoran“appearance”[Erscheinung](A20/B34). Intuitionisdistinguishedfrom“per-ception”[Wahrnehmung]byvirtueof thesubject’sbeingconsciousof the“content”[Inhalt]of the intuition (moreon thenotionof “content”below) (Pr4:300; cf. A99,A119-20, B162, B202-3).14 Finally, “experience” [Erfahrung] involves the synthesisofperceptions[Wahrnehmungen]viaapplicationof(orperhapsguidanceby)thecat-egories. “Experience iscognition throughconnectedperceptions [durchverknüpfte

10 See Hinton(1973); Byrne(2009)forcontemporarydiscussionofworriesconcerningthenotionofan“experience”.

11 AsKantsaysinthe Prolegomena, “Experienceconsistsinthesyntheticconnection[Verknüpfung]ofap-pearances(perceptions)inaconsciousness, insofarasthisconnectionisnecessary”(Pr4:305; cf. 4:275;B147, B218, B227).

12 Seethediscussionin Van Cleve(1999), 74-6; Ginsborg(2006b).13 ThankstoClintonTolleyfordiscussionconcerningtheseandrelatedpoints.14 Whatexactly is intendedbyKant’suseof “conscious” [Bewußt] and“consciousness” [Bewußtsein]furthercomplicatesmatters. Significantly, forourpurposes, wecannottakeforgrantedthatKantmeanstoindicatewhat we typicallymeaninusingtheterm—viz. “phenomenalconsciousness”or“whatitislike”tohavetherelevantexperience. KanttypicallyusesthetermintheLeibniz-Wolffsenseinwhichitindicatestheextenttowhichtherepresentingsubjectcandistinguishbetweenobjectsorthepartsofobjects. See Wunderlich(2005); La Rocca(2008a), La Rocca(2008b); Grüne(2009), ch.1; SturmandWunderlich(2010); McLear(2011)fordiscussion.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 5

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Wahrnehmungen]”(B161; cf. B218; Pr4:300). Thisthreefolddistinctionisalsocon-firmedintheheadingstothefirstthreechaptersofthePrinciplesofthefirst Critique,inwhichKantdistinguishesbetweenthe“Axiomsof Intuition”, the“AnticipationsofPerception”, andthe“AnalogiesofExperience”. IfKant weren’t thinkingthatthetermstheterms“intuition”[Anschauung], “perception”[Wahrnehmung], and“experience”[Erfahrung]designateddistinctmentalstates, thenitwouldbedifficulttounderstandwhyheorderedacentralpartofhisarchitectonicaroundthem.

There isalsoaprimafacie tensionbetweenthesuggestionabove, thatwedistin-guish“intuition” from“perception”—i.e“Wahrnehmung”—andKant’s remark in theStufenleiter passagequotedabove, that“perception”[perceptio]isthecategoryof“rep-resentationwithconsciousness”, inwhichheincludesintuition. Onedifficultyisthat“Wahrnehmung”, “perceptio”, and“Perzeption”arealltypicallytranslatedinEnglishusing“perception”, whileitisunclearthatallthesetermsmeanthesamethingforKant,orthattheymeanwhat wemean, using“perception”initscontemporaryEnglishsense.Butthedifficultyisn’tjustrelatedtotheproblemofEnglishtranslation; rather, thetextofthe Stufenleiter seemstodefineintuitionintermsofbeingaconsciousrepresenta-tion (and thusa “perceptio”), but I suggestedabove theKantdistinguishes intuitionfrom Wahrnehmung byappealtothepresenceofconsciousnessinthelatterbutnottheformer.

Onepossiblemoveinresolvingthistensionistosaythatthenotionof“conscious-ness” in the Stufenleiter concerns consciousness of the representation, rather than,specifically, itscontent. Intuitions, onthisreading, wouldbeconsciousrepresentations,butthesenseinwhichtheyareconsciousdiffersfromthatofa Wahrnehmung. ThereisalreadygroundforsuchadistinctioninKant’sdifferentiationbetweentheconscious-ness inherent in the awareness of a representation—its “clarity” [Klarheit], whichrequiresonlythattherepresentationsufficefordistinguishinganobjectfromothers—andtheconsciousnessinherentintheawarenessofthecontentofarepresentation—its“distinctness”[Deutlichkeit], whichrequiresthatoneclearlyrepresentallthedifferentpartsofthecontentoftherepresentation(orthepartsofitscorrespondingobject)(An7:137-8; cf. JL 9:34; R 643, 15:283; R 1709, 16:89).15 Thismeansof resolving theissueisperhapsmadeevenmoreattractivebyKant’sremarkinthe Anthropology that,

distinctnessalonemakesitpossiblethatanaggregate[Summe]ofrepre-sentationsbecomesacognition[Erkenntnis], inwhichorderisthoughtinthismanifold, becauseeveryconsciouscombination[ZusammensetzungmitBewußtsein]presupposesunityofconsciousness, andconsequentlyaruleforthecombination. (7:138)

15 Therearecomplications, however, in simply equating clarityandconsciousness; cf. B414-15, note.Kantalsoseemsquitehappytoentertainthepossibilityofunconsciousor“obscure”[Dunkel]intuitions(An7:135); cf. Wunderlich(2005), 141-2; Grüne(2009), ch. 1.3.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 6

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Thispassage suggests thatan intuition, of itself, isatbestconscious in the senseofbeing clear [klar]. WhenanintuitionisapprehendedinanactofWahrnehmung (cf. Pr4:300), itscontentisbroughttogetherinsuchawaythatitbecomes(atleasttosomedegree) distinct [deutlich], andthusacandidateforcognition. Inthismanner, weseemabletoresolvethetensionbetweentheaccountofthedifferencebetweenintuitionandWahrnehmung offeredaboveandKant’sremarksinthe Stufenleiter.16

GiventhedifficultyofprovidingapreciseaccountofhowKant’sterminologymapsontocontemporaryusage(assumingthatitdoesatall), I focusbelowonwhatI taketo be a central aspect of the contemporary debate between conceptualist and non-conceptualistinterpretationsofKant—viz. whether intuitions, understoodbythisde-bateasmentalstateswhicharebothcognitive, andhavesense-modalspecificphenom-enalcharacter, dependon(andinwhatwaytheydependon)actsoftheunderstanding.TheemphasisonintuitionisgroundedinKant’stextsinsofarasKantrepeatedlycitesempiricalintuitionasthatwhichisourfirstorprimarymeansofbeingsensorilyrelatedtoactualobjects(Pr4:283; cf. Pr4:350; B160; A180/B222; OD 8:217). I shallfreelyusetheterms“perception”, “experience”, and“perceptualexperience”todescribethementalstatesKantdesignatesby“intuition”[Anschauung], solongasitisunderstoodthattheseEnglishtermsaremeantinourcontemporaryusage, notnecessarilyKant’s.

SoI use“outerintuition”(orwherecontextpermits, simply“intuition”)toindicate,unlessotherwisenoted, theperception(i.e. theEnglishtermforcognitivesensorycon-sciousness)ofanexistencedistinctfromthesubject. “Inner”intuition, incontrast, istheawarenessof the subject’s existence, andaparticularmode thereof (e.g. feelingwarm, hungry, etc.). Bothareformsof experience intheEnglishsenseoftheterm—viz. acognitivementalstateoreventwithaparticularphenomenologybasedononeofthefivesenses. But, asnotedabove, neitherinnernorouterintuitionissufficientforexperience[Erfahrung]inKant’ssenseoftheterm. Kant’snotionofanexperiencere-quiresconceptualandapperceptivecapacitieswhichengenderanawarenessoflawfulrelationsbetweenconsciouslyperceivedobjects, properties, states, orevents.

Thequestiontowhichwenowturnconcernstheconditionsunderwhichamen-tal state type thatKantdesignatesas“intuition” [Anschauung] requiresorotherwisepresupposesmentalactsofsynthesis(oratleastthecapacityforsuchacts)bytheun-derstanding.

3 KantianNon-Conceptualism

Attheheartofnon-conceptualistreadingsofKantstandsthedenialthatmentalactsofsynthesiscarriedoutbytheunderstandingarenecessaryfortheoccurrenceofcognitivementalstatesofthetypewhichKantdesignatesbytheterm“intuition”[Anschauung].

16 ThankstoSamRicklessforencouragingclarityonthispoint.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 7

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Though it is controversial as towhatmightbeconsidered the “natural”or “default”readingofKant’smaturecriticalphilosophy, thereareatleastfourconsiderationswhichlendstrongsupporttoanon-conceptualistinterpretationofKant’smaturework.

First, asseveralscholarshavenoted, Kant repeatedlyand forcefullystates that inourcognitionthereisastrictdivisionofcognitivelabor—objectsaregivenbysensi-bilityandthoughtviatheunderstanding.17 AsRobertHannahasargued, whenKantdiscussesthedependenceofintuitiononconceptualjudgmentintheAnalyticofCon-cepts, heisspecificallytalkingabout cognition ratherthanwhatwewouldconsidertobeperceptualexperience.18

Second, Kantcharacterizestherepresentationalcapacitiescharacteristicofsensibil-ityasmoreprimitive than thosecharacteristicof theunderstanding (or reason), andasplausiblypartofwhathumans sharewith the restof theanimalkingdom.19 Forexample, RobertHannaconstruesKant’sdistinctionbetweenthefacultiesofsensibilityandunderstandingascapturingthedifferencebetweenthe“sub-rational”powersofthemindthatwesharewithnon-humananimals, andthe“rationalorhigher-levelcognitivepowers”thatarespecialtohumanbeings.20

Ifoneweretodenythat, accordingtoKant, sensibilityaloneiscapableofproducingmentalstatesthatwerecognitiveincharacterthenitwouldseemthatanyanimalwhichlacksafacultyofunderstanding, andthusthecapacityforconceptualsynthesis, wouldthereby lackanycapacity forgenuinely perceptual experience. Themental livesofnon-rationalanimalswouldthus, atbest, consistofnon-cognitivesensorystateswhichcausallycorrelatewithchangesintheanimal’senvironment. Asidefromwhatwewouldnowconsidertobeanunappealingandimplausiblecharacterizationofthecognitivecapacitiesofanimals, thisreadingalsofacestextualhurdles. Kantisonrecordinvariousplacesassayingthatanimalshavesensoryrepresentationsoftheirenvironment(CPJ5:464; LM 28:449; cf. An7:212), thattheyhaveintuitions(LL 24:702), andthattheyareacquaintedwithobjectsthoughtheydonotcognizethem(JL 9:64–5).21

IfKant’spositionisthatsyntheticactscarriedoutbytheunderstandingarenecessaryfor the cognitive standingof amental state, thenKant is contradicting fundamental

17 Hanna(2005); Allais(2009); McLear(2011); Hanna(2011a); Tolley(2013); McLear(Forthcominga),McLear(Forthcomingb).

18 SeethediscussionofKant’s“togethernessprinciple”andit’ssignificanceforsettingtheconditionsonobjectivelyvalidjudgmentin Hanna(2005), 265-7.

19 Kant connects the possession of a faculty of sensibility to animal nature in various places,e.g. A546/B574, A802/B830; An7:196.

20 Hanna(2005), 249; cf. Allais(2009); McLear(2011), McLear(Forthcominga), §3.21 Forfurtherdiscussionsee Naragon(1990); Allais(2009); McLear(2011). Forsomedefenseofthecon-ceptualistpositionsee McDowell(1996), chs. 3&6; Ginsborg(2006b), Ginsborg(2006a); Ginsborg(2008); Gomes(2014).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 8

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

elementsofhisownpositionincreditingintuitions(ortheirpossibility)tonon-rationalanimals.

Third, anypositionwhichregardsperceptualexperienceasdependentuponactsofsynthesiscarriedoutbytheunderstandingmustalsoconstruethe“pure”intuitionsofspaceandtimeasdependentuponactsofsynthesis.22 However, Kant’sdiscussionofspace(andanalogously, time)inthethirdandfourtharguments(fourthandfifthinthecaseoftime)oftheMetaphysicalExpositionofSpaceintheTranscendentalAestheticseemsincompatiblewithsuchaproposedrelationofdependence.

Kant’spointinthethirdandfourthargumentsoftheMetaphysicalExpositionofspace(andsimilarlyoftime)isthatnofiniteintellectcouldgrasptheextentandnatureofspaceasaninfinitewholeviaasyntheticprocessmovingfromparttowhole. Iftheunityoftheformsofintuitionwerealsosomethingdependentuponintellectualactivity, thenthisunitywouldnecessarilyinvolvethediscursive(thoughnotnecessarilyconceptual)runningthroughandgatheringtogetherofagivenmultiplicity(presumablyofdifferentlocationsormoments)intoacombinedwhole, whichKantbelievesischaracteristicofsynthesisgenerally(A99).

ButKant’sargumentsintheMetaphysicalExpositionsofspaceandtimerequirethatthefundamentalbasisofourrepresentationofspaceandtimedoesnotproceedfromagraspofthemultiplicityoffeaturesofanintuitedparticulartothewholethathasthosefeatures. Insteadtheformofpureintuitionconstitutesarepresentationalwholethatisprior tothatofitscomponentparts(cf. CJ 5:407-8, 409).23

Hence, Kant’spositionisthatthepureintuitionsofspaceandtimepossessaunitywhollydifferentfromthatgivenbythediscursiveunityoftheunderstanding(whetheritbeinconceptualjudgmentortheintellectual cum imaginativesynthesisofintuitedobjectsmoregenerally). Theunityofaestheticrepresentation—characterizedbytheformsofspaceandtime—hasastructureinwhichtherepresentationalpartsdependonthewhole. Theunityofdiscursiverepresentation—representationwheretheactivityoftheunderstandingisinvolved—hasastructureinwhichtherepresentationalwholedependsonitsparts.24

Finally, therehasbeenextensivediscussionof thenon-conceptualityof intuitioninthesecondaryliteratureonKant’sphilosophyofmathematics. Forexample, MichaelFriedmanhasarguedthattheexpressivelimitationsoftheprevailinglogicinKant’stimerequiredthepostulationofintuitionasaformofsingular, non-conceptualrepresenta-

22 Thispositionisforcefullyarticulatedin Longuenesse(1998), ch. 8; seealso Griffith(2012); Friedman(2012).

23 Kant’sargumenthereisdirectedverymuchagainsttheLeibnizianviewthatallrepresentationispurelyconceptual. Forfurtherdiscussionsee Adams(1994), ch. 9; Janiak(2012).

24 Formuchmoreextensivediscussionofthisissuesee McLear(Forthcominga); cf. Messina(2014); OnofandSchulting(Forthcoming).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 9

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

tion.25 CharlesParsonsandEmilyCarsonhavearguedthatspacemustbegiveninaphenomenologicalmannerasanoriginal, non-conceptualrepresentationinorderthatwebeabletodemonstratetherealpossibilityofconstructedmathematicalobjectsasrequiredforgeometricknowledge.26 Ultimately, however, therearedifficultiesinas-sessingwhetherKant’sphilosophyofmathematicscanhaverelevancefortheconceptu-alismdebate, sincethesenseinwhichintuitionmustbenon-conceptualinaccountingformathematicalknowledgeisnotobviouslyincompatiblewithclaimingthatintuitionsthemselves(includingpureintuition)aredependentuponaconceptually-guidedsyn-thesis.27

Thenon-conceptualistreadingisthusclearlycommittedtoallowingthatsensibilityaloneprovides, in a perhaps very primitivemanner, objective representationof theempiricalworld. Sensibilityisconstruedasanindependentcognitivefaculty, whichhumanssharewithothernon-rationalanimals, andwhichisthejumping-offpointformoresophisticatedconceptualrepresentationofempiricalreality.

4 KantianConceptualism

IntheintroductionI characterizedconceptualismasclaimingthatthereisadependencerelationbetweenasubject’shavingconscioussensoryexperienceofanobjectiveworld,andtherepertoireofconceptspossessedbythesubjectandexercisedinactsbyherfacultyofunderstanding.

Asafirstpassatsharpeningthisformulation, wemayunderstandconceptualism, asitappearsinthescholarlyliteratureonKant, asathesisconsistingoftwoclaims: (i)senseexperiencehascorrectnessconditionsdeterminedbythe“content”oftheexperience;(ii)thecontentofanexperienceisastructuredentitywhosecomponentsareconcepts.Let’staketheseinturn.

25 Friedman(1992), ch. 2; cf. thediscussionofthenon-conceptualconditionsofjudgmentsofequalityin Anderson(2005), 54-8andthediscussionoftherepresentationofhomogeneousunitsin Sutherland(2008).

26 Parsons(1964); Parsons(1992); Carson(1997); Carson(1999); cf. Hanna(2002). ForageneraloverviewofrelatedissuesinKant’sphilosophyofmathematicssee Shabel(2006)andtheworkscitedthereinatp. 107, note29.

27 MichaelFriedman(Friedman(2012))hasrecentlyarticulatedsuchaposition; cf. Longuenesse(1998).If, asFriedmanargues, Kant’snotionoftheconceptualistiedtohislogic, then, aswemoveawayfromsyllogisticlogicpost-Frege, theremaybenotionsoftheconceptualthatarecompatiblewithKant’sviewsinmathematics. Fordiscussionsee MacFarlane(2002); Anderson(2004), Anderson(2005).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 10

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

4.1 Content&Correctness

Animportantbackgroundassumptiongoverningtheconceptualismdebateconstruesmentalstatesasrelatedtotheworldcognitively(asopposedtomerelycausally)ifandonlyiftheypossesscorrectnessconditions. Thatwhichdeterminesthecorrectnesscon-ditionforastateisthatstate’s“content”.

Suppose, forexample, thatanexperienceE hasthefollowingcontentC:

C:Thatcupiswhite.

ThiscontentdeterminesacorrectnessconditionV:

V:S’sexperienceE iscorrectiffthecupvisuallypresentedtothesubjectasthecontentofthedemonstrativeiswhiteandthecontentC correspondstohowthingsseemtothesubjecttobevisuallypresented.

Herethecontentoftheexperientialstatefunctionsmuchlikethecontentofabeliefstatetodeterminewhethertheexperience, likethebelief, isorisnotcorrect.

A state’spossessionofcontentthusdeterminesacorrectnesscondition, invirtueofwhichwecanconstruethestateasmapping, mirroring, orotherwisetrackingaspectsofthesubject’senvironment.

PerhapsthemostprominentrecentinterpretationofKantasendorsingthecontentassumptionisfoundinJohnMcDowell’s MindandWorld. McDowell’sprojectthereistoshow, givencertainpresuppositionsconcerningthenatureofjustification, howitisthatexperiencecanplayajustificatoryandnotmerelycausalroleinthefixationofbelief. InthecourseofthisargumentMcDowellarticulatesveryclearlyacommitmenttoconstruingrepresentationalcontentasthekindofthingthatiscorrectorincorrect.Hesays,

Theveryideaofrepresentationalcontentbringswithitanotionofcorrect-nessandincorrectness: somethingwithacertaincontentiscorrect, intherelevantsense, justincasethingsareasitrepresentsthemtobe. I canseenogoodreasonnottocallthiscorrectness“truth.” Butevenif, forsomereason, wereservethat titleforcorrectnessinthissensewhenit ispos-sessedbythingswithconceptualcontent, itseemsaroutinethoughtthattherecanberationalconnectionsbetweentheworld’sbeingasapossessorofonebitofcontentrepresentsitandtheworld’sbeingasapossessorofanotherbitofcontentrepresentsit, independentlyofwhatkindofcontentisinquestion.28

28 McDowell(1996), 162. ManyofMcDowell’sinterlocutorssharesimilarviews. Cf. Evans(1982), 202;Peacocke(1992), 55, 65; Burge(2003), 506.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 11

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

McDowellexplainsthecloseconnectionbetweentheideaofrepresentationalcon-tentandthatofcorrectnessintermsofthenormativecharacterofanyworld-directedmentalstate, aparadigmaticinstanceofwhichisjudgingthatsomethingisthecase. Hesays,

Tomakesenseoftheideaofamentalstate’sorepisode’sbeingdirectedtowardstheworld, inthewayinwhich, say, abelieforjudgementis, weneedtoputthestateorepisodeinanormativecontext. A belieforjudge-menttotheeffectthatthingsarethusandso—abelieforjudgementwhosecontent(aswesay)isthatthingsarethusandso—mustbeapostureorstancethatiscorrectlyorincorrectlyadoptedaccordingtowhetherornotthingsareindeedthusandso. (Ifwecanmakesenseofjudgementorbeliefasdirectedtowardstheworldinthatway, otherkindsofcontent-bearingposturesorstancesshouldeasilyfallintoplace).29

HereMcDowellclaimsthatbeliefsandjudgmentshaveaparticularwayofdisclosingtheworld to a subject and that this is away inwhichwemightunderstandworld-directedmentalstatesmoregenerally. Hefurtherclaimsthatthewayinwhichamen-talstate isdirectedat theworld is in termsof itspossessingacorrectnessconditionconcerninghowtheworldinfactis. McDowellthenrelateshisunderstandingofsuchworld-disclosingorworld-directedstatestoperceptualexperience.

WeshouldunderstandwhatKantcalls“intuition”—experientialintake—notasabaregettingofanextra-conceptualGiven, butasakindofoc-currenceorstatethatalreadyhasconceptualcontent. Inexperienceonetakesin, forinstancesees, thatthingsarethusandso. Thatisthesortofthingonecanalso, forinstance, judge.30

McDowellhereutilizesKant’sterm“intuition”[Anschauung]whichMcDowellequateswith“experiential intake.‘’Soheendorses the idea that intuitionhascontent (beingnecessaryforour“takingin”thatsomethingisthecase), andthatitisinvirtueofthiscontentthattheexperientialstate, togetherwiththeworld, iseithercorrectorincorrect.Fromthiswecanconcludethat, accordingtoMcDowell, intuitionshaverepresenta-tionalcontent, thatthisentailsthatsuchcontentisassessableforitscorrectness, andthatintuitionswithcontentaretherebymentalstatesassessablefortheircorrectness.Hence, McDowell’sinterpretationclearlyunderstandsKantasendorsingaversionofthecontentassumption.

29 McDowell(1996), xi-xii.30 McDowell(1996), 9.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 12

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Manynon-conceptualistopponentsofMcDowell’sinterpretationneverthelesssharewithhimanendorsementofthecontentassumption.31 However, theydifferwithhiminatleastoneoftwoways. First, thecontentofanexperiencewhichsetsitscorrectnessconditionsisattributedtotheexperienceregardlessofwhat, ifany, otherconceptualcapacitiesthesubjectmayhave. Non-conceptualcontentsarethusmeanttocaptureaspectsoftheperceivingsubject’sexperiencethatmaywelloutrunthesubject’sowncapacitiesforarticulation.32

Second, proponents of non-conceptualist readings of contentmay construe non-conceptualcontentsascorrectinamannerthatisaltogetherdistinctfromconceptualcontents, whicharetrueorfalsedependingonwhethertheconditionssetoutbytheconceptsconstituting thecontentare satisfied. Incontrast, non-conceptualcontent,muchlikethecontentofamaporarecording, isaccurateorinaccurate. Itthusadmitsofdegreesofapproximation.33

Thus, formanynon-conceptualists, whileitisstillthecasethatasubject’smentalstatesonlycountasrepresentationalinvirtueofpossessingcorrectnessconditions, thenatureandarticulationofthesecorrectnessconditionsmaywelldifferradicallyfromthosesetoutbyconceptualism.

Wecanseethesetwofeaturesofnon-conceptualismatworkinaninterpretationofKantthatis, inmanyways, directlyopposedtoMcDowell’sconceptualism. RobertHannahasargued that, forKant, sensible intuitionspossesswhollynon-conceptualrepresentationalcontent. WecanseethisintwoquotesfromHanna, thefirstofwhichdescribes thenon-conceptualist position andattributes it toKant, while the secondarticulatesingreaterdetailthekindofrepresentationalcontentHannathinksispresentinperceptualexperience.

Non-conceptualismholdsthatnon-conceptualcontentexistsandisrep-resentationallysignificant…Non-conceptualcognitivecontentinthecon-temporarysenseis, forallphilosophicalintentsandpurposes, identicaltointuitionalcognitivecontentinKant’ssense.34

31 Many, butnotall. See Tolley(2011), Tolley(2013); McLear(Forthcomingb).32 Endorsementofthisthesissometimesgoesunderthename’statenon-conceptualism’or’relativenon-conceptualism.’ See Heck(2000); Speaks(2005); cf. Allais(2009); Hanna(2005), Hanna(2008), Hanna(2011b).

33 Cf. Burge (2003). This conception of non-conceptual content also goes under name ’content non-conceptualism’or’absolutenon-conceptualism.’ See, again, Heck(2000); Speaks(2005).

34 Hanna(2005), 248.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 13

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

essentiallynon-conceptualcontentiseitheraccurateorinaccurate, andasI havesuggested, inherentlypoisedforuseintheintentionalactionsofconsciousanimals.35

WecanthusseethatforHanna, intuitionalcontentisnon-conceptualbutneverthelessrepresentational—itexpressesanaccuracyconditioninvirtueofwhichthementalstaterepresentssomeportionof themind-independentworld. Hanna’sposition (bothonits ownandas attributed toKant) regards thisnonconceptual content as essentiallyveridical, indexical, andcontextdependent.36 ButthebasicpresumptionwhichdrivesHanna’snon-conceptualismisthesameasthatofMcDowell’sconceptualism. A mentalstatecountsasastateofperceptualawareness—i.e. a“world-directed”state—onlyinvirtueofhavingarepresentationalcontentwhichsetsacorrectnessconditionforthestate. Hence, Hanna, likeMcDowell, articulatesaninterpretationwhichendorsesthecontentassumption.

I takeitthatMcDowell’sandHanna’sviewsarerepresentativeoftwoextremesre-gardinginterpretationsofKantunderstandingofthecontentofintuition. McDowell, atleastinthediscussionin MindandWorld, arguesthatintuitionisthroughandthroughconceptual. Thatis, McDowellunderstandstherepresentationalcontentofperceptionasthesamekindofcontentasisfoundinbeliefsorthoughts. Sothecontentofanexpe-rienceisaconceptuallystructured, truth-evaluableproposition.37 Hanna, incontrast,arguesthatintuitionhasabsolute non-conceptual content—ithasastructureessentiallydifferentinnaturefromthatofconceptualcontent.38

HannaandMcDowellarticulatethebasicshapeofmuchrecentdebateconcerning

35 Hanna(2008), 58.36 Hanna(2006), chs. 1-2; Hanna(2011b); cf. Howell(1973); Pereira(2013).37 McDowellhassincechangedhisview. A morecurrentspecificationof itstates that intuitionisnotpropositionalinstructurethoughitneverthelesspossessesconceptualcontent. See McDowell(2008).However, sinceMcDowellstillconstruesthecontentofintuitionasintentionalandconceptual, bringingwithitanormativenotionofcorrectness, I considerevenhismorecurrentstatementstobeanendorse-mentofthecontentassumption. Cf. McDowell(2013), whereheexplicitlysaysthatitis“invirtueofhavingcontentastheydothatperceptualexperiencesputusinsuch[i.e. cognitive]relationstothings”(p. 144).

38 Hanna(2011a), 354; cf. Hanna(2005).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 14

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

theinterpretationofKant’sviewsconcerningperceptualexperience.39 Sowhetheraperceptualexperientialstatehasconceptuallystructuredcontent(McDowell), ornon-conceptuallystructuredcontent(Hanna), itisinvirtueofthestate’saimingatawaytheworldmightbe, andthushavingacorrectnesscondition, thatthestatecountsasaformofperceptualawareness.

Thereare reasons forquestioningwhetherKantendorses thecontentassumptionasI’vearticulateditabove.40 Kantseemstodenyseveralclaimswhichareintegraltoit. First, invariousplacesheexplicitlydeniesthatintuition, orthedeliverancesofthesensesmoregenerally, arethekindofthingwhichcouldbecorrectorincorrect(A293–4/B350; An§117:146; cf. LL 24:83ff, 103, 720ff, 825ff). Second, Kant’sconceptionofrepresentationalcontentrequiresanactofmentalunification(Pr4:304; cf. JL §179:101; LL 24:928), somethingwhichKantexplicitlydenies ispresent inanintuition(B129-30; cf. B176-7).41 Finally, Kant’s“modal”conditiononcognition, thatitprovideademonstrationofwhatisreallyactualratherthanmerelylogicallypossible, seemstoprecludeanendorsementofthecontentassumption. However, forthepurposesofunderstanding theconceptulismdebate, wewillassume thatKantdoesendorse thecontentassumption. Thequestionthenishowtounderstandthenatureofthecontentsounderstood.

4.2 ConceptualContent

Inaddition to thecontentassumption, I definedconceptualismascommitted to thecontentofintuitionbeingcompletelycomposedofconcepts. Againstthis, ClintonTol-ley(Tolley(2013), Tolley(2011))hasarguedthattheimmediacy/mediacydistinctionbetweenintuitionandconceptentailsadifferenceinthecontentofintuitionandcon-cept.

39 ThereareagreatmanyotherwaystoarticulatethenotionthatintuitionhascontentwithinthelimitssetbyHannaandMcDowell. Forexample, therearecoherentinterpretationswhichdenythatintuitionhasconceptualcontent, butassertthatitistheresultofanimaginativesynthesis, andholdthattheimageswhichconstituteexperientialconsciousnessareconstructionsaccordingtoconceptualrules. Hence,insofarastheimagespurporttoberepresentationaltheymustbeattributedacontentdeterminedbytherulesoftheirconstruction. Inmyterms, thisamountstoavariationoftheContentassumption. SeeLonguenesse’sdiscussionofconceptsasrules forsensiblesynthesis. Longuenesse(1998), 50ff. Seealso Anderson(2001); Land(2011); Matherne(Unpublished). Watkins (2008), 519-20alsosuggestsanimagisticview, thoughitisnotfullyarticulated. Otherviewsthatseemcompatiblewithsuchanaccountinclude Strawson(1966); Strawson(1970); Sellars(1968); Ginsborg(2006b); Ginsborg(2006a).Schulting(2012)presentsarecentandhelpfuloverviewofmanyoftherelevantissues.

40 See McLear(Forthcomingb)formoreextensivediscussion.41 Kantdoesnot, however, denythatintuitionhas“content”[Inhalt]insomesenseotherthanthatofacorrectnesscondition. Fordiscussionsee Tolley(2011), Tolley(2013); McLear(Forthcomingb).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 15

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

ifweunderstandby“content”…arepresentation’sparticularrelationtoanobject…thenit isclear thatweshouldconcludethatKantacceptsnon-conceptualcontent. This isbecauseKantaccepts that intuitionsputusinarepresentational relation toobjects that isdistinct inkind fromtherelationthatpertainstoconcepts. I argued, furthermore, thatthisisthemeaningthatKanthimselfassignstotheterm“content”. (Tolley(2013),128)

InsofarasKantoftenspeaksofthe“content”[Inhalt]ofarepresentationasconsistinginaparticularkindofrelationtoanobject(Tolley(2013), 112; cf. B83, B87)Tolleythusgivesusakindof“shortargument”foranon-conceptualistreadingofKant:

1. Thecontentofacognition(whetherintuitionorconcept)consistsin—i.e. isnoth-ingbut—arelationtoanobject

2. Conceptsandintuitionsrelatetoobjectsindifferentways—viz. mediatelyandimmediately

3. ∴ Thecontentof intuition isdifferent from thecontentof concepts—i.e. it isnon-conceptual

Tolley’sargumentgivesusgoodreasontorejecttheideathatintuitioncouldhave, inKant’ssenseoftheterm, aconceptasits“content”.42 HoweveritdoesnotdemonstratethatthecontentofwhatKantcallsanintuitionisnotsomethingthat we wouldconstrueasconceptual, inawidersenseof that term. Forexample, bothpureandcomplexdemonstrativeexpressionshaveconceptualform(e.g. thatcolor, thisperson), butarenot, inKant’s terms, “conceptual” since theydonot exhibit the requisite generalitywhich, accordingtoKant, allconceptualrepresentationmust.43

4.3 Conceptualism&Synthesis

If it isn’t textuallyplausible tounderstand thecontentof an intuition in conceptualterms(atleastasKantunderstandsthenotionofaconcept)thenwhatwoulditmeantosaythatKantendorsesconceptualismwithregardtoexperience? Themostplausibleinterpretation, endorsedbyawidevarietyof interpreters, readsKantasarguing thatthegenerationofanintuition, whetherpureorsensory, dependsatleastinpartontheactivityoftheunderstanding. Onthiswayofcarvingthings, conceptualismdoes notconsistinthenarrowclaimthatintuitionshaveconceptsascontentsorcomponents,butratherconsistsinthebroaderclaimthattheoccurrenceofanintuitiondependsat

42 Foropposingviewssee Willaschek(1997); Griffith(2012); Engstrom(2006).43 Forfurtherdiscussionsee McLear(Forthcomingb), §5.2; Thompson(1972).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 16

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

leastinpartonthediscursiveactivityoftheunderstanding.44 ThespecificactivityoftheunderstandingisthatwhichKantcalls“synthesis”, the“runningthrough, andgatheringtogether”ofrepresentations(A99).45

What’smore, the fact that intuitionsaregeneratedaccording toactsof synthesisdirectedbyorotherwisedependentuponconceptualcapacitiesprovidessomebasistoclaimthatwhatevercorrectnessconditionsmightbehadbyintuitionmustbeinaccordwiththeconceptualsynthesiswhichgeneratedthem. ThisseemsnicelyinlinewithKant’smuchquotedclaim,

The same function that gives unity to thedifferent representations in ajudgment alsogivesunitytothemeresynthesisofdifferentrepresentationsinanintuition, which, expressedgenerally, iscalledthepureconceptofunderstanding. (A79/B104-5)

Thelinkbetweenintuition, synthesisinaccordancewithconcepts, andrelationtoanobjectismadeevenclearerbyKant’sclaimin§17oftheB-editionTranscendentalDeductionthat,

Understanding is, generallyspeaking, thefacultyof cognitions. Thesecon-sistinthedeterminaterelationofgivenrepresentationstoanobject. Anobject, however, isthatintheconceptofwhichthemanifoldofagivenintuitionis united. (B137; emphasisintheoriginal)

Howeverelsewearetounderstandthispassage, Kanthereindicatesthattheunityofanintuitionnecessaryforittostandasacognitionofanobjectrequiresasynthesisbytheconcept<object>. Inotherwords, cognitionofanobjectrequiresthatintuitionbeunifiedbyanactoractsoftheunderstanding.

Accordingtotheconceptualistinterpretationwemustunderstandthenotionofarepresentation’scontentasarelationtoanobject, whichinturndependsonaconcep-tuallyguidedsynthesis. Sowecanreviseourinitialdefinitionofconceptualismtoreaditasclaimingthat(i)thecontentof anintuitionisakindofrelationtoanobject; (ii)

44 McLear(Forthcominga)callsthisbroaderposition“Intellectualism”, soastoemphasizetheimportanceoftheunderstanding’sactivity, ratherthanthespecificconceptualcontentofthatactivity.

45 See Grüne(2009), ch. 2foranalternativetaxonomy. Grünedistinguishes“judgment-theoretic”[Urteils-theoretik]from“conceptualist”[Konzeptualist]interpretationsonthebasisofwhethertheinterpretationconstruestheintuitiverepresentationsgeneratedbysensorysynthesisintermsof, orimplying, judgment(Grüne(2009), 111-12). However, sheandI agreethatsuch“judgment-theoretic”viewsarenotdefini-tiveofabroadlyconceptualistinterpretation, andthatwhetheronetakesKantasarguingthatintuitiondependsonaconceptually-guidedsynthesisremainsasignificantdifferencebetweenconceptualistandnon-conceptualistinterpretations(Grüne(2009), §2.4; cf. Grüne(2008)). SoI takethediscussionheretobebroadlycongenialtoherown.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 17

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

therelationtoanobjectdependsonasynthesisdirectedinaccordancewithconcepts;(iii)synthesisinaccordancewithconceptssetscorrectnessconditionsfortheintuition’srepresentationofamind-independentobject.46

5 Objections

Oneof themaincriticismsof theconceptualist readingofKant is that it seeminglycommitshimtothepositionthatperceptualexperienceisconstrainedbythesubject’srepertoireofconcepts. However, HannahGinsborghasarguedthatKant’sconceptual-ismneednotbeconstruedinsuchaway.47 Instead,

thereisroomforalessdemandingconceptionofwhatitisforunderstand-ingtobeinvolvedinperceptualsynthesis, aconceptionwhichdoesnotrequirethatanyconceptsbegraspedantecedentlytoengaginginsynthe-sis. Onthisconception, tosay thatsynthesis involvesunderstanding issimply tosay that it involvesaconsciousnessofnormativity…I want toclaimthatthisconsciousnessofnormativityispossiblewithoutthesub-ject’sfirsthavinggraspedanyconceptgoverninghersynthesis, and, morespecifically, withouthersynthesisneedingtobeguidedbyanyconcept.(Ginsborg(2008), 71)

AccordingtoGinsborg, weneednotreadtheconceptualistasmakingthestrongclaimthat perceptual experience is constrained by conceptual repertoire that the subjectbringswiththemtoexperience. Instead, weneedmerelyseetheissueofconceptu-alizationasoneinwhichthesubjectcombinesanassociationofsomebundleofsenseimpressionswiththesensethatsheisassociatingthemassheought, anditisthiscon-sciousnessofthenormativityofone’scombinationthatisresponsible“fortheobject-directedcharacterofourperceptions” (Ginsborg (2008), 74). Hence, ifGinsborg iscorrect, oneofthemainsourcesforobjectingtoconceptualistreadingsofKant—viz.theirsupposeddenialthatnon-rationalanimalsenjoyperceptualexperiences—wouldberemoved.48

46 Onemightworryhereabouttheobjectofperceptualhallucination. I setthisissuelargelytooneside,thoughitiscompatiblewiththeaccountgivenabovethatthe“objects”towhichoneisimmediatelyre-latedinperceptionarealways“intentional”objects. See Aquila(1983); Pereboom(1988); Longuenesse(1998), 20-6; Aquila(2003), Aquila(2008); Grüne(2009), 42.

47 Foralternativeconstrualsoftheconceptualityofexperiencethatalsoseethemselvesascompatiblewiththeclaimthatexperienceisprimitivesee Gomes(2014); Gomes(Manuscript); Land(2011).

48 Ginsborg’spositionhasbeencriticizedbyscholarsoneithersideof theconceptualismdebate. SeeGrüne(2008); Allais(2009), 401.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 18

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Perhapsthemostobviousobjectiontothenon-conceptualistreadingofKantstemsfromhisfamousstatementthat,

Intuition[Anschauung]andconcepts[Begriffe]thereforeconstitutetheele-mentsofallourcognition[Erkenntnis]…Thoughtswithoutcontent[Inhalt]areempty, intuitionswithoutconceptsareblind. . . . Theunderstand-ingisnotcapableofintuitinganything, andthesensesarenotcapableofthinkinganything. Onlyfromtheirunificationcancognitionarise. (A50–51/B74–75; myemphasis)

Theso-called“blindness”problemraisestwoissues. First, thatintuitionswithoutcon-ceptsorconceptualsynthesisarenotintentionalstates, andsocannotprovidethemindwithrelationtoanobject.49 Second, thatwecannotevenidentifythecognitivecontri-butionmadebysensoryexperienceindependentofitsconceptualization.50

AgainstthefirstpointithasbeenarguedthatifKant’sconcerniswiththemecha-nism(s)thatundergirdsintentionalstates, andhethinksthatpossessionofafacultyofunderstandingisanecessaryconditionforbeinginintentionalstates, thenhewouldbesimplyconfusedinattributingthepossibilityofintentionalstatestonon-rationalani-mals.51 Ithasalsobeenpointedoutthat, totheextentthatKantproblematizestheissueofintentionalrelations, itisatbestintentionalrelationstoexternalmind-independentobjects thatare inquestion, andnot intentional relations (suchas those involved inthinkingofone’sownmentalstates) überhaupt.52

Againstthesecondpoint, LucyAllais(Allais(2009))hasforcefullyarguedthatifwetakeKant’sdefinitionofintuition(andlikewiseofconcepts)seriously, thenwe must beabletoidentifyanindependentcontributionofsensibilitytocognition—viz. singularandimmediaterepresentationofanobject—lestwefailtomakesenseofKant’sdivi-sionbetweenintuitionandconcept.53 ItwouldalsobeextremelyoddofKanttodenythepossibilityofarticulatingthedistinctcontributionmadebysensibilitygiventhathegoessofarastoorganizethestructureofargumentinthefirst Critique aroundthedis-tinctionbetweenthosecontributionsmadebysensibility(theTranscendentalAesthetic)andthosemadebytheunderstanding(theTranscendentalLogic, andinparticular, the

49 Foraclearstatementoftheviewthatconceptualsynthesisisthemechanismbywhichsensorystatesfirstachievethestatusofintentionalstatessee George(1981); Pereboom(1988); cf. Van Cleve(1999),95-7.

50 Falkenstein(1995); McDowell(1996). McDowellfamouslyclaimsthatsensibilitycannotbeeven“no-tionallyseperated”fromcontributionsmadebytheunderstanding(McDowell (1996), 51). Cf. Bird(2006), ch. 7.2.

51 See Naragon(1990); Allais(2009); McLear(2011)andthereferencescitedinnotes 20 and 21 above.52 Cf. George(1981), 233andVanCleve’scriticaldiscussionin Van Cleve(1999), 96.53 Allais(2009), 393-4; cf. Falkenstein(1995), 63.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 19

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Analytic).54 Theclaimof“blindness”, itisargued, shouldnotbeinterpretedassoex-tremeastorenderunintelligiblefundamentalaspectsofKant’sarchitectonic, orofhisrepeatedstatementsconcerningtheindividualcognitiverolesofthefacultiesofsensi-bilityandunderstanding. Finally, atbest, theblindnessproblemseemstoconcernthedifficultiesinvolvedinarticulatingthenatureofsensorycontentwithoutdrawingonconceptsintheprocessofprovidingthearticulation.55 Butthiscanbeconcededwith-outtherebyadmittingthatthereisnosensorycontent(orpositivecognitivecontribution)independentofconceptualarticulation.

A significantfurthersourceofcriticismofthenon-conceptualistreadingisthatitatbestrendersineffectualKant’sapparentstrategyfordemonstratingthelegitimacyofthecategoriesintheargumentoftheTranscendentalDeduction, andatworstshowsKanttobetotallyconfusedinhisargumentativestrategy.56

A key text for this readingcomes in theconclusion to the secondor“B-edition”versionoftheargumentoftheTranscendentalDeduction.

[E]verythingthatmayevercomebeforeoursensesmuststandunderthelawsthatarise apriori fromtheunderstandingalone(B160). . . Conse-quentlyallsynthesis, thoughwhichevenperceptionitselfbecomespossi-ble, standsunderthecategories, andsinceexperienceiscognitionthoughconnectedperceptions, thecategoriesareconditionsofthepossibilityofexperience, andarethusalsovalid apriori ofallobjectsofexperience.(B161)

What thispassageanditscontextsuggest is that theculminationofKant’sargumentdemonstratingthelegitimacyoftheaprioriconceptshecallsthe“categories”requiresshowingthatallperceptiondependsonasynthesisviathecategories. Here, however, itisimportanttonotethatKantisusing“perception”[Wahrnehmung]inhisowntechnicalsense, asdiscussedin§2above, ratherthanourcontemporaryEnglishsense. Sohearguesherethatthecategoriesarenecessaryforconsciousnessofthecomplexcontentofanintuition. Butit isn’tclearthatthisisequivalenttobeingnecessaryforhavinganintuition, andthusforhavingasensoryexperienceinthecontemporarysensewithwhichwe’vebeenconcerned.

A further, andmuchdiscussed, text in theB-editionTranscendentalDeduction isalsooftentakenassupportingaconceptualistinterpretation. ThereKantsays,

Space, presentedasobject(asweareactuallyrequiredtorepresentitinge-ometry), containsmorethan[the]mereformofintuition—viz. itcontains

54 Bird(2006), 12755 Bird(2006), 129-30.56 Cf. Ginsborg(2008), 68-9; Griffith(2012). Forcriticismsee Allais(2009); Tolley(2013); McLear(Forth-cominga).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 20

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

alsothegathering-together[Zusammenfassung]ofthemanifoldgivenac-cordingtotheformofsensibility, inanintuitiverepresentation—sothattheformofintuitiongivesusmerelyamanifold, butformalintuitiongivesusunityofrepresentation. IntheTranscendentalAestheticI hadmerelyin-cludedthisunitywithsensibility, wantingonlytopointoutthatitprecedesanyconcept. Butthisunityindeedpresupposesasynthesiswhichdoesnotbelongtothesenses, throughwhichallconceptsofspaceandtimefirstbecomepossible. Forthroughthisunity(inasmuchasunderstandingde-terminessensibility)spaceortimearefirstgivenasintuitions, andhencetheunityofthisintuitionbelongs apriori tospaceandtime, andnottotheconceptofunderstanding(see§24)(B160-1, note).

Here theconceptualist takesKant to “complete” theargumentof theDeductionbyarguing that even the existenceof space and time aspure intuitions dependson asynthesisbythecategories.57 Theconceptualistideahereisthat, bymakingspaceandtimethemselvesdependonacategorialsynthesis, Kantassureshisdesiredconclusion—viz. thatallpossibleempiricalintuitionmustdependonthecategories, andthusthatallpossibleobjectsofempiricalintuitionmustfallunderthecategories. Theconceptualistthus takes thisasproof thatanon-conceptualistapproach toreading theDeductionmustmaketheargumenttherehopelessandKant’sstrategydeeplyconfused.58

One thing to note about the footnote passage is that, in thefirst sentence, Kantexplicitlyinvokesthenotionofspaceasanobjectofgeometry. Butitisn’tobviousthatKantidentifiestheconditionsunderwhichasubjectmayrepresentspacegeometricallywiththeconditionsforrepresentingspace simpliciter. Infact, Kant’sdistinctioninthefootnotebetweentheformsofintuitionandformalintuitionsuggeststhathedeniesanysuchidentification. SoKantcanconsistentlyholdthattheunityoftherepresentationofthepureformsofintuition—spaceandtime—isindependentofanysynthesis, whileacknowledging, ashedoesinthelastsentenceofthenote, thattherepresentationoftheseentitiesasobjects, aswedoin the formal intuitionsrequiredformathematics,requiresapre-conceptualsynthesiscarriedoutbytheimagination.59

57 ThesourceofthisinterpretationseemstobeHegel. See Hegel(1977), 69-72. Forrelevantdiscussionsee Pippin(1989), 29-31; Waxman(1991), 79ff; Longuenesse(1998), ch. 8; Keller(1998), 107-12, 254;McDowell(2003), McDowell(2007); McLear(Forthcominga); Messina(2014).

58 Longuenesse(1998); Wenzel(2005); Gomes(2010); Land(2011); Griffith(2012); Gomes(2014). Notallnon-conceptualiststakeupthischallenge. Hanna(2011b)simplyacceptsthisasaconsequenceofKant’snon-conceptualistposition, andconstruesKantasdeeplydividedinhisownviewsonthematter.ForobjectionstoHanna’spositionsee Grüne(2011); Schulting(2012). ForanextensivediscussionoftheB160-1footnoteanddefenseofanon-conceptulistreadingofitsee OnofandSchulting(Forthcoming).

59 Cf. thediscussionin McLear(Forthcominga), §2.1.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 21

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

We’vealsoseenonenon-conceptulistargument, above, thatKant’sargumentativestrategyintheDeductioncannotdependonmakingtheunityofintuitionitselfdepen-dentonsynthesisbecauseitjeopardizeshisargumentsintheTranscendentalAesthetic.SuchaninterpretationwouldalsodirectlycontradictKant’scharacterizationofthefinitenatureofhumanintellectualactivity(CJ 5:407; cf. B72; CJ 5:251-2, 253-4).60 Othernon-conceptualrepliestothisconceptualistreadingincludedenyingthatthesynthe-sisrequiredfortheunityofperceptualintuitionisitselfconceptual,61 anddistinguish-ingbetween the having ofan intuition, and the representationof thecontentof anintuition—wherethelatterisunderstoodasadeterminaterepresentationalrelationtosomeobject.62

Finally, andperhapsmostcentrallyforsomeconceptualistreadings(mostnotablySellars’sandMcDowell’s), theroleofconceptsinthegenerationofperceptualexperi-enceissupposedtohelpexplainhowperceptioncanplayajustificatoryratherthanmerelyacausal role in thefixationofbelief. Non-conceptualism, so theobjectiongoes, cannotaccountforthejustificatoryroleofperceptualexperienceinthefixationofempiricalbelief. Versionsofthisobjectionhaveoften, sinceWilfredSellars’sfamouspaper, goneunderthemonikerofthe“MythoftheGiven”.63 WhileitisnotentirelyobvioushowKant’stextsorargumentsyieldanysubstantiveconnectionwiththecon-cernsarticulatedbySellars, I shallsuggestbelowthreepossiblewaysinwhichsuchaconnectionmightbeunderstood.

Theexactnatureofobjectionstothesupposedlymythical“Given”vary.64 Oneob-jection, madebySellars, isthatjustifiersforbeliefmusthaveacertainkindofstructure—viz. afact-likestructurethatmirrorsthepropositionalstructureofbelief. Incontrast,sensoryexperiences(construedassensations)areparticularsratherthanfacts, andsocannotplayanyjustificatoryrole.65 This“premiseprinciple”, asithasbeencalledincontemporaryepistemology, thusplaysasignificantroleinmotivatingtherejectionofexperience, insofarasit lacksrepresentationalcontent, asapotentialjustifierforbe-

60 Forfurtherdiscussionofthispointsee McLear(Forthcominga).61 Rohs(2001), 220-1; Allais(2009), 395-6, 406-7; cf. Tolley(2013). Willaschek(1997)arguesthatin-tuition causally relatestoitsobjectindependentofconcepts, butonlyhasintentional content givenaconceptualsyntheis. Hannatakesanothertackandarguesthatsensibilityhasitsownformofsponta-neoussynthesisdistinctfromtheunderstanding’s(cf. Hanna(2008), 62).

62 Tolley(2013), 122-24.63 Sellars(1956), reprintedin Sellars(1963); cf. McDowell(1996); McDowell(1998a), McDowell(1998b),McDowell(1998c); Abela(2002)

64 Cf. Watkins(2008); Watkins(2012).65 Sellars(1956), reprintedin Sellars(1963), 128. Allfurtherpagereferenceswillbetothereprint. Cf.BonJour(1985), ch. 4.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 22

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

lief.66 Forexample, JohnMcDowellarguesthat

TheideaoftheGivenistheideathatthespaceofreasons, thespaceofjus-tifications’orwarrants, extendsmorewidelythantheconceptualsphere.Butwecannotreallyunderstandtherelationsinvirtueofwhichajudgmentiswarrantedexceptasrelationswithinthespaceofconcepts: relationssuchasimplicationorprobabilification, whichholdbetweenpotentialex-ercisesofconceptualcapacities67

ThepassageinKanttypicallyadducedinsupportofthispointisthe“samefunction”passageat(A79/B104-5)quotedin§4.3above.68 Thus, accordingtothisconceptualistreadingofKant, senseexperience would havetherequisiteproposition-likestructure,andthusbecapableofstandinginjustificatoryrelationstobeliefs, sincethesameca-pacitiesthatstructurethecontentsofjudgmentforKant(viz. thecategories)wouldalsostructuresensoryexperience. WhilesuchinterpretersaresurelycorrectthatKant’saim,asexemplifiedinthispassage, istoshowthattheverysamecognitivecapacitieswhichconnectrepresentationsinamentalactofjudgingarealsoinplayintheconnectionofrepresentationsinasensoryexperience, itisnotobvioushowthepassagedirectlysupportsanyargumentconcerningtheepistemicsignificanceofperceptualexperiencetoknowledge. Endorsementofthepremiseprincipleisasubstantiveepistemologicalcommitment, anddespitewhatKantsaysintheA79/B104-5passageconcerningtheunityofjudgmentandintuition, itisnotatallobviousthatKantendorsestheprinci-ple.69 HencefurtherworkneedstobedonetoshowthatKantactuallyendorsesorevenarticulatesthisargument.

A secondobjectionagainsttheGiven, thatmightbeattributedtoKant, isthatthemereoccurrenceofasensoryexperiencecannotlicenseanyparticularbelief. Instead,sensoryexperiencecanonlyplayitsjustificatoryroleagainstabackgroundofconceptspossessedbytheexperiencingsubject.70 Thisconnects toKantat least inthesensethat, if theconceptualist reading is correct, there is aparticularbatteryof concepts

66 See Pryor(2005); SiegelandSilins(Forthcoming); McLear(Forthcomingb), §4.3fordiscussion.67 McDowell(1996), 7; cf. BonJour(1985),78; Davidson(1986), 310; Brewer(1999), 15468 Seee.g. Sellars(1968), 4-5; McDowell(2003), 79; Haag(2007), 150-1, 199, andch. 8; Kalderon(2011),235-6. Cf. Pippin(1982), 99-101; Heidegger(1997), 45-6; Longuenesse(1998), 200; Grüne(2009),107-11.

69 Forexample, accordingtoatleastoneprominentinterpretationofKant’sepistemology, Kantendorsesanatleastpartly“externalist”positionconcerningepistemicjustification, andthusdoesnotendorsethepremiseprincipleinthemannerrequiredtoplausiblyattributetohimthisversionofthe“MythoftheGiven”argument. See Chignell(2007b), 49-50; McLear(Forthcomingb), §4.3.

70 Sellars(1963), 170; McDowell(1998a), 435-6.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 23

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

necessaryforanyperceptualexperiencetoplayaroleinjustificationortheacquisitionofempiricalknowledge—viz. thecategories.71

Againthough, onemightworryaboutattributingtheaboveargumenttoKant. Cer-tainlyKantthoughtthatempiricalintuitionalonewasinsufficienttocountasempiricalknowledgeandthatthelegitimateapplicationofthecategorieswasnecessaryforanysuchknowledge. Butmuchmorewouldneedtobesaidregardingwhetherorhowin-tuitionmightstandinepistemicrelationstobeliefs.72 ThereisnostraightforwardroutefromKant’sargumentconcerningtheroleofthecategoriesinempiricalknowledgetotheconclusionthattheepistemologicalstatusofintuitiondependsonthecategories.Indeed, theremaybereasonstothinkthatKantwouldrejectsuchaclaim.

Forexample, Kantseemstoholdthatinintuitionwe“provethepossibility”ofthesubjectmatterofourthoughts. KantmakesthispointexplicitlyintheprefacetotheB-editionofthefirst Critique.

To cognize anobject, it is required that I be able toprove its possibil-ity(whetherbythetestimonyofexperiencefromitsactualityor apriorithroughreason). ButI can think whateverI like, aslongasI donotcon-tradictmyself, i.e., aslongasmyconceptisapossiblethought, evenifIcannotgiveanyassurancewhetherornotthereisacorrespondingobjectsomewherewithinthesumtotalofallpossibilities. Butinordertoascribeobjectivevalidity to suchaconcept (realpossibility, for thefirst sortofpossibilitywasmerelylogical)somethingmoreisrequired(Bxxvi).

HereKantcontrastsmerelylogicallypossiblethought, inwhichonebringstogetherlog-icallycompossibleconcepts, withthekindofrealempiricalpossibilitynecessaryforcognition. Kantdistinguishesbetweenthesetwosortsofpossibilityintermsoftheno-tionofcancellation[Aufhebung]. Thesubjectmatterofathoughtis logically possibleifthethought’sconstituentconceptsmaybecombinedinjudgementwithoutcontradic-tion, andthuswithoutbeinglogicallycancelledout(A151/B190; NM 2:171–2). Thesubjectmatterofathoughtis really possible, incontrast, ifitcanbeshownthatthesub-jectmattertowhichthethoughtcorrespondsconsistsofpropertieswhicharemutuallyempiricallycompossibleandnot, inKant’sterms, “reallyrepugnant.” Kantoftenillus-tratesthisideawithexamplesinvolvingphysicalforces(e.g. oppositemotions, opposing

71 McDowell(1996); Ginsborg(2006b), Ginsborg(2008). Itisnotactuallyclearthatonlytheconceptualistreadingcanaccommodate thisaspectofKant’sview. A non-conceptualistmaywellagree that thecategoriesarenecessaryforempiricalknowledgewhileneverthelessdenyingthattheyarenecessaryinaccountingfortheintentionalityofperceptualexperience. Cf. Hanna(2001), 46-65, Hanna(2005), 256-7; Bird(2006), 193-207; Watkins(2008); Allais(2009), 392-4; Watkins(2012); Tolley(2013); McLear(Forthcominga), §3; McLear(Forthcomingb), §5.2.

72 For discussion see Stevenson (2003); Chignell (2007a), Chignell (2007b); Watkins (2008), Watkins(2012).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 24

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

attractiveandrepulsiveforces; cf. A264–5/B320–1). Moreover, Kantconsideredafur-therkindofrepugnance, whereinthesubjectitselfis“cancelledout”. Inotherwords, itwouldbeimpossibleforanybeingtoexistthatwouldinstantiatesuchrepugnantprop-erties.73 Inorderforknowledgetobepossible, thedemonstrationoftherealpossibilityoftheobjectofknowledgemustbesecured. Ifthisiscorrectthenthereseemstobeatleasta primafacie tensionbetweenattributingtoKantboththeclaimthatpossessionofsomebatteryofconceptsisnecessaryforintuitiontohaveepistemicstanding, andtheclaimthat it isvia intuitionthatone’sconcepts (or thejudgmentsconstitutedbythem)firstattainepistemiclegitimacy. Howcouldaconceptconferepistemicstandingtointuitionpriortothatconcept’sbeingshowntobelegitimate? TheymaywellbeaKantianbasisforansweringthisquestion, butmoreneedstobesaidbytheconceptu-alisttodefendthesupposedKantianprovenanceofthissecondversionofthe“MythoftheGiven”argument.74

Finally, bothSellarsandMcDowellclaimthat it issimplyamistaketo thinkthatmentalstateswhicharepurelytheupshotofcausalinteractionswiththeworldcouldthemselvesstandasreasonsforempiricalbelief. Sellarsremarksthatsuchamistakeis“ofapiecewiththeso-called’naturalisticfallacy’inethics”(Sellars(1963), 146). Sellarshimselfgivesnoclearargumentforthisclaim.75 McDowellfocusesonthedistinctionbetweenthekindsofmentalstates, theoccurrenceofwhichweareresponsiblefor, suchasjudgment, andthosewhichsimply happen tous, inthewaythat, e.g. afitofsneezingmighthappentoone.76 Onceagain, wecanseethesuggestedparallelinaconceptu-alistreadingofKant. Ifconceptualcapacities, suchasthecategories, arenecessaryfortheoccurrenceofperceptualexperiencethenexperienceisnotmerelysomethingthatcausally happens tothesubject, butratherissomethingthatthesubjectherselfpartiallyaccountsfor, inmuchthesamewaythatsheaccountsforherendorsementofthecon-tentofpropositionaljudgment. ItisnotclearthatthisargumentisconstruedasanythingmorethanKantianinspirit. Certainlythough, theredoesseemtobeadeeplyKantianpointbehindthenotionthatreasoningis thinkingforoneself, andthatthisrequiresthatthestructureofone’sthoughtsbe, insomesense, determinedbyoneself.77

73 Fordiscussionsee Chignell(2011), 144–5; Chignell(2014); McLear(Forthcomingb), §§4.3and5.2.74 A further possibility is thatKant’s views are genuinely dividedhere, and that subsequentmoves inGermanidealismreflectthisfact. See Pippin(1989), ch. 2andthesourcescitedinnote 57 above.

75 Watkins(2008); Watkins(2012).76 McDowell(1996), ch. 1-2; McDowell(1998a), 433-4; McDowell(2003), 80-5; cf. Engstrom(2006),8-13.

77 ThissuggeststhatKant’sviewsofpracticalandtheoreticalreasonhaveabroaderunity. Foroneclassicstatementofsuchaninterpretationsee O’Neill(1989), ch. 1; cf. Stevenson(2004); McDowell(2009),chs. 4, 5, and7.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 25

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

[O]necannotpossiblythinkofareasonthatwouldconsciouslyreceivedirectionfromanyotherquarterwithrespecttoitsjudgments; sincethesubjectwouldthenattributethedeterminationofhisjudgment, nottohisreasonbuttoanimpulse. Reasonmustregarditselfastheauthorofitsprinciplesindependentlyofalieninfluences. (G 4:448)

WhetherornotKanthimselfintendedhisargumentsconcerningtheroleofconceptsinexperiencetobetakeninthewaysthatSellars, McDowell, andothershavesuggested,itisclearthathehasbeenacentralsourceofinspirationforthesepositions. Needlesstosay, thedisputeastoKant’sexactpositionregardingthesematterscontinues.78

Summary

To say thatKant is aconceptualist is, aswehave seen, to say thathe thinks (i) thecontentofanintuition(i.e. an“experience”inourcontemporarysense)isakindofrep-resentationalrelationtoanobject; (ii)suchrelationtoanobjectdependsonasynthesisdirectedinaccordancewithconcepts; (iii)synthesisinaccordancewithconceptssetscorrectnessconditionsfortheintuition’srepresentationofamind-independentobject.TheconceptualistreadingpromisestomakesenseofKant’sargumentintheTranscen-dentalDeductionbyshowinghowperceptualexperiencedependsonasynthesisbythecategories. Assumingthatwehavesuchexperience, if thecategoriesareneces-saryforperceptualexperience, thentheyhavelegitimateapplicationtotheobjectsofexperience. Inthismannerconceptualismpurportstohaveaninterpretiveadvantageovernon-conceptualistreadings. Conceptualistsfurtherclaimthattheirreadingbestexplainshowperceptualexperiencecouldplaya justificatory role in thefixationofbelief.

However, wehavealsoseenseveralapparentproblemsfortheconceptualistread-ing. First, thoughmuchofwhat theconceptualist saysmaybe trueofKant’sviewsconcerning“cognition”[Erkenntnis](or“experience”[Erfahrung]asheoftenusestheterm)it islessclearthatit istrueofperceptualexperienceorintuition. Second, theconceptualistmustbeabletoaccountforthemoreprimitiverolethatperceptionseemstoplayinKant’scognitivetheory, aswellastheseemingfactthatheacknowledgesthatperceptualexperienceissomethingwesharewithnon-rationalanimals. Third, concep-tualistreadingsseemtothreatenthecoherenceoftheargumentsoftheTranscendentalAesthetic, andthusthecoherenceofKant’sbroadercriticalposition. Fourth, Kant’sownphilosophyofmathematicsmayrequirethatintuitionbeunderstoodasaformofnon-conceptualrepresentation. Finally, itisnotatallclearthat, forKant, intuitionshave

78 Hanna(2011a)disputestheideathatKantiscentrallyconcernedwithdenyingtheroleoftheGiveninthewaysuggestedbySellarsandMcDowell. Seealsothereferencescitedinnote 71 above.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 26

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

correctnessconditions. Thisisabasicassumptionoftheconceptualistpositionandispresupposedbyitsothercommitments.

Goingforward, conceptualismneedstoclarifyhowitsreadingiscompatiblewithKant’sarguments in theTranscendentalAesthetic, aswellashisviewsregardingthecognitivecapacitiesofnon-rationalanimals. Italsoneedstodomoretomotivatecon-fidenceinthegenuinelyKantianprovenanceofthefamilyofargumentsthatgounderthemonikerofcriticismsofthe“MythoftheGiven.” Similarly, thenon-conceptualistreadingwouldbegreatlyhelpedbyamoreextensiveaccountofthecompatibilityofnon-conceptualismwiththeargumentoftheTranscendentalDeduction. Bothsidesofthedebateneedalso toaccount forobjections to thecontentassumption. MuchofthefuroroverKant’sendorsementordenialofconceptualismhastrackedcontempo-raryissuesinthephilosophyofperception. Butwhateverthefortunesofconceptualismandnon-conceptualismascontemporaryphilosophicaldoctrines, ourunderstandingofKant’sphilosophy, andinparticularhistheoryofcognition, hasbeengreatlyextendedbythedebate.79

References

Abela, Paul(2002). Kant’sEmpiricalRealism. NewYork: OxfordUniversityPress(p. 22).Adams, Robert Merrihew(1994). Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist. Oxford: Oxford

UniversityPress(p. 9).Allais, Lucy(2009). “Kant, Non-ConceptualContentandtheRepresentationofSpace”.

In: JournaloftheHistoryofPhilosophy 47.3, pp. 383–413. doi: 10.1353/hph.0.0134 (pp. 8, 13, 18–20, 22, 24).

Anderson, R. Lanier (2001). “Synthesis, CognitiveNormativity, and theMeaning ofKant’sQuestion, ’HowAreSyntheticCognitionsaPrioriPossible?’” In: EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 9.3, pp. 275–305(p. 15).

— (2004). “ItAddsupafterAll: Kant’sPhilosophyofArithmeticinLightoftheTradi-tionalLogic”. In: PhilosophyandPhenomenologicalResearch 69.3, pp. 501–540(p. 10).

— (2005). “TheWolffianParadigmandItsDiscontents: KantsContainmentDefinitionofAnalyticityinHistoricalContext”. In: ArchivfürGeschichtederPhilosophie 87.7,pp. 22–74(p. 10).

Aquila, Richard E. (1983). RepresentationalMind: AStudyofKant’sTheoryofKnowl-edge. en. Bloomington: IndianaUniversityPress(p. 18).

— (2003). “HansVaihingerandSomeRecentIntentionalistReadingsofKant”. In: Jour-naloftheHistoryofPhilosophy 41.2, pp. 231–250(p. 18).

79 ThankstoDerkPereboom, ClintonTolley, andtheparticipantsinmygraduateseminaronconceptualismattheUniversityofNebraska–Lincolninthefallof2013forhelpfuldiscussionandcomments.

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 27

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Aquila, Richard E. (2008). “IntentionalObjectsandKantianAppearances”. In: Philo-sophicalTopics 12.2, pp. 9–37(p. 18).

Bird, Graham(2006). TheRevolutionaryKant: ACommentaryontheCritiqueofPureReason. Peru, IL: OpenCourtPublishingCompany(pp. 19, 20, 24).

BonJour, Laurence(1985). TheStructureofEmpiricalKnowledge. en. Cambridge, MA:HarvardUniversityPress(pp. 22, 23).

Brewer, Bill(1999). PerceptionandReason. NewYork: OxfordUniversityPress(p. 23).Brook, Andrew(2013). “KantandTime-OrderIdealism”. en. In:ACompaniontothePhi-

losophyofTime. Ed. byAdrian BardonandHeather Dyke. Oxford:Wiley-Blackwell,pp. 120–134(p. 3).

Burge, Tyler (2003). “PerceptualEntitlement”. In: PhilosophyandPhenomenologicalResearch 67.3, pp. 503–548(pp. 11, 13).

Byrne, Alex(2009). “ExperienceandContent”. In: ThePhilosophicalQuarterly 59.236,pp. 429–451. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2009.614.x (p. 5).

Carson, Emily(1997). “KantonIntuitionandGeometry”. In: CanadianJournalofPhi-losophy 27.4, pp. 489–512(p. 10).

— (1999). “KantontheMethodofMathematics”. In: JournaloftheHistoryofPhilos-ophy 37.4, pp. 629–652. doi: 10.1353/hph.2008.0905 (p. 10).

Chignell, Andrew (2007a). “Belief in Kant”. In: The Philosophical Review 116.3,pp. 323–360. doi: 10.1215/00318108-2007-001 (p. 24).

— (2007b). “Kant’sConceptsofJustification”. In: Noûs 41.1, pp. 33–63(pp. 23, 24).— (2011). “RealRepugnanceandOurIgnoranceofThings-in-Themselves: ALockean

ProbleminKantandHegel”. de. In: InternationalesJahrbuchdesDeutschenIdeal-ismus2009: GlaubeundVernunft. Ed. byFred Rush, Jürgen Stolzenberg, andPaulW. Franks. Berlin: WalterdeGruyter, pp. 135–159(p. 25).

— (2014). “Kantandthe’Monstrous’GroundofPossibility”. In: KantianReview 19.1,pp. 53–69. doi: 10.1017/S1369415413000290 (p. 25).

Davidson, Donald(1986). “ACoherenceTheoryofTruthandKnowledge”. In: TruthandInterpretation: PerspectivesonthePhilosophyofDonaldDavidson. Ed. byErnestLePore. Oxford: BasilBlackwell, pp. 307–319(p. 23).

Engstrom, Stephen(2006). “UnderstandingandSensibility”. In: Inquiry 49.1, pp. 2–25(pp. 16, 25).

Evans, Gareth(1982). TheVarietiesofReference. Ed. byJohn McDowell. Oxford: Ox-fordUniversityPress(p. 11).

Falkenstein, Lorne(1995). Kant’sIntuitionism: ACommentaryontheTranscendentalAesthetic. en. Toronto: UniversityofTorontoPress(p. 19).

Friedman, Michael(1992). KantandtheExactSciences. en. Cambridge: HarvardUni-versityPress(p. 10).

— (2012). “KantonGeometryandSpatialIntuition”. en. In: Synthese 186.1, pp. 231–255. doi: 10.1007/s11229-012-0066-2 (pp. 9, 10).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 28

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

George, Rolf(1981). “Kant’sSensationism”. In: Synthese 47.2, pp. 229–255. doi: 10.1007/BF01064346 (p. 19).

Ginsborg, Hannah(2006a). “EmpiricalConceptsandtheContentofExperience”. In:EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 14.3, pp. 349–372(pp. 8, 15).

— (2006b). “Kant and theProblemof Experience”. In: Philosophical Topics 34.12,pp. 59–106. doi: 10.5840/philtopics2006341/24 (pp. 5, 8, 15, 24).

— (2008). “WasKantaNonconceptualist?” In: PhilosophicalStudies 137.1, pp. 65–77. doi: 10.1007/s11098-007-9163-3 (pp. 8, 18, 20, 24).

Gomes, Anil (2010). “Is Kant’s Transcendental Deduction of the Categories Fitfor Purpose?” In: Kantian Review 15.02, pp. 118–137. doi: 10 . 1017 /S1369415400002466 (p. 21).

— (2014). “Kant on Perception: Naıv̈e Realism, Non-Conceptualism and the B-Deduction”. In: ThePhilosophicalQuarterly 64.254, pp. 1–19. doi: 10.1093/pq/pqt019 (pp. 2, 8, 18, 21).

— (Manuscript). “InKantianPhrase”(p. 18).Griffith, Aaron M. (2012). “Perceptionand theCategories: AConceptualistReading

ofKant’s CritiqueofPureReason”. en. In: EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 20.2,pp. 193–222. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0378.2010.00404.x (pp. 2, 9, 16, 20, 21).

Grüne, Stefanie(2008). “BegriffealsRegelnderWahrnehmung”. In: RechtundFriedenin der Philosophie Kants: Akten des X Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Ed. byValerio Rohden et al. Berlin: Walter deGruyter, pp. 267–278. doi: 10 . 1515 /9783110210347.2.267 (pp. 17, 18).

— (2009). BlindeAnschauung. FrankfurtamMain: VittorioKlostermann(pp. 4–6, 17,18, 23).

— (2011). “IsThereaGapinKantsBDeduction?” In: InternationalJournalofPhilo-sophicalStudies 19.3, pp. 465–490(p. 21).

Gunther, York H., ed. (2003). EssaysonNonconceptualContent. en. Cambridge: MITPress(p. 1).

Haag, Johannes(2007). ErfahrungundGegenstand. FrankfurtamMain: VittorioKloster-mann(p. 23).

Hanna, Robert(2001). KantandtheFoundationsofAnalyticPhilosophy. Oxford: Ox-fordUniversityPress(p. 24).

— (2002). “MathematicsforHumans: Kant’sPhilosophyofArithmeticRevisited”. In:EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 10.3, pp. 328–352. doi: 10.1111/1468-0378.00165 (p. 10).

— (2005). “KantandNonconceptualContent”. In: European JournalofPhilosophy13.2, pp. 247–290. doi: 10.1111/j.0966-8373.2005.00229.x (pp. 8, 13, 14,24).

— (2006). Kant, Science, andHumanNature. Oxford: ClarendonPress(p. 14).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 29

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Hanna, Robert(2008). “KantianNon-Conceptualism”. In: PhilosophicalStudies 137.1,pp. 41–64. doi: 10.1007/s11098-007-9166-0 (pp. 13, 14, 22).

— (2011a). “BeyondtheMythoftheMyth: AKantianTheoryofNon-ConceptualCon-tent”. In: InternationalJournalofPhilosophicalStudies 19.3, pp. 323–398(pp. 8,14, 26).

— (2011b). “Kant’sNon-Conceptualism, RogueObjects, and theGap in theBDe-duction”. In: InternationalJournalofPhilosophicalStudies 19.3, pp. 399–415. doi:10.1080/09672559.2011.595188 (pp. 13, 14, 21).

Heck, Richard G. (2000). “NonconceptualContentandthe”SpaceofReasons””. In:ThePhilosophicalReview 109.4, pp. 483–523(p. 13).

Hegel, G. W. F. (1977). Hegel: FaithandKnowledge: AnEnglishtranslationofG. W.F. Hegel’sGlaubenundWissen. en. Ed. byWalter CerfandHenry Silton Harris.Albany: SUNYPress(p. 21).

Heidegger, Martin(1997). KantandtheProblemofMetaphysics. en. Bloomington: In-dianaUniversityPress(p. 23).

Hinton, John Michael(1973). Experiences: AnInquiryIntoSomeAmbiguities. en. Ox-ford: OxfordUniversityPress(p. 5).

Howell, Robert(1973). “Intuition, Synthesis, andIndividuationinthe CritiqueofPureReason”. In: Noûs 7.3. ArticleType: research-article/Fullpublicationdate: Sep.,1973/Copyright©1973Wiley, pp. 207–232. doi: 10.2307/2214348 (p. 14).

Janiak, Andrew(2012). “Kant’sViewsonSpaceandTime”. In: TheStanfordEncyclope-diaofPhilosophy. Ed. byEdward N. Zalta. Winter2012(p. 9).

Kalderon, Mark Eli(2011). “BeforetheLaw”. en. In: PhilosophicalIssues 21.1, pp. 219–244. doi: 10.1111/j.1533-6077.2011.00202.x (p. 23).

Keller, Pierre (1998). Kant and theDemandsof Self-Consciousness. en. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress(p. 21).

La Rocca, Claudio(2008a). “DerdunkleVerstand: UnbewussteVorstellungenundSelb-stbewusstseinbeiKant”. In: RechtundFriedeninderPhilosophieKants. AktendesX. InternationalenKant-Kongresses 2, pp. 447–458(p. 5).

— (2008b). “UnbewußtesundBewußtseinbeiKant”. In: Kant-Lektionen: ZurPhiloso-phieKantsundzuAspektenihrerWirkungsgeschichte. Ed. byManfred Kugelstadt.Würzburg: Königshausen Neumann, pp. 47–68(p. 5).

Land, Thomas (2011). “Kantian Conceptualism”. In: Rethinking Epistemology 1,pp. 197–239(pp. 15, 18, 21).

Longuenesse, Béatrice (1998). KantandtheCapacity to Judge. Princeton: PrincetonUniversityPress(pp. 9, 10, 15, 18, 21, 23).

MacFarlane, John(2002). “Frege, Kant, andtheLogicinLogicism”. In: PhilosophicalReview 111.1, pp. 25–65. doi: 10.1215/00318108-111-1-25. eprint: http://philreview.dukejournals.org/cgi/reprint/111/1/25.pdf (p. 10).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 30

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Matherne, Samantha(Unpublished). “ImagesandKant’sTheoryofPerception”. Unpub-lishedmanuscript(pp. 2, 15).

McDowell, John(1996). MindandWorld: WithaNewIntroduction. Cambridge, MA:HarvardUniversityPress(pp. 8, 11, 12, 19, 22–25).

— (1998a). “LectureI: SellarsonPerceptualExperience”. In: TheJournalofPhilosophy95.9, pp. 431–450(pp. 22, 23, 25).

— (1998b). “LectureII: TheLogicalFormofanIntuition”. In: TheJournalofPhilosophy95.9, pp. 451–470(p. 22).

— (1998c). “Lecture III: IntentionalityasaRelation”. In: The JournalofPhilosophy95.9, pp. 471–491(p. 22).

— (2003). “HegelandtheMythoftheGiven”. In: DasInteressedesDenkens: HegelausheutigerSicht. Ed. byWolfgang WelschandKlaus Vieweg. München: WilhelmFinkVerlag, pp. 75–88(pp. 21, 23, 25).

— (2007). “Hegel’sIdealismasRadicalizationofKant”. In: InternationalesJahrbuchdesdeutschenIdealismus=InternationalYearbookofGermanIdealism 5. ReprintedinMcDowell2009, 69–89, pp. 157–175(p. 21).

— (2008). “AvoidingtheMythoftheGiven”. In: JohnMcDowell: Experience, NormandNature. Ed. byJakob Lindgaard. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 1–14(p. 14).

— (2009). HavingtheWorldinView: EssaysonKant, Hegel, andSellars. Cambridge:HarvardUniversityPress(p. 25).

— (2013). “PerceptualExperience: BothRelationalandContentful”. en. In: EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 21.1, pp. 144–157. doi: 10.1111/ejop.12005 (p. 14).

McLear, Colin(2011). “KantonAnimalConsciousness”. In: Philosophers’Imprint 11.15,pp. 1–16(pp. 5, 8, 19).

— (Forthcominga). “TwoKindsofUnityinthe CritiqueofPureReason”. In: JournaloftheHistoryofPhilosophy (pp. 8, 9, 17, 20–22, 24).

— (Forthcomingb). “KantonPerceptualContent”. In: Mind (pp. 2, 8, 13, 15, 16, 23–25).

Messina, James(2014). “KantontheUnityofSpaceandtheSyntheticUnityofApper-ception”. In: Kant-Studien 105.1, pp. 5–40. doi: 10.1515/kant-2014-0002 (pp. 9,21).

Naragon, Steve(1990). “KantonDescartesandtheBrutes”. In: Kant-Studien 81.1, pp. 1–23(pp. 8, 19).

O’Neill, Onora(1989). ConstructionsofReason: ExplorationsofKant’sPracticalPhilos-ophy. en. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress(p. 25).

Onof, ChristianandDennis Schulting(Forthcoming). “SpaceasFormofIntuitionandasFormalIntuition. OntheNotetoB160inKant’s CritiqueofPureReason”. In: ThePhilosophicalReview (pp. 9, 21).

Parsons, Charles (1964). “InfinityandKant’sConceptionof the”PossibilityofExperi-ence””. In: ThePhilosophicalReview 73.2. ArticleType: research-article/Fullpub-

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 31

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

licationdate: Apr., 1964/Copyright©1964DukeUniversityPress, pp. 182–197.doi: 10.2307/2183335 (p. 10).

Parsons, Charles(1992). “TheTranscendentalAesthetic”. In: TheCambridgeCompan-iontoKant. Ed. byPaul Guyer. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress. Chap. 2,pp. 62–100(p. 10).

Peacocke, Christopher(1992). AStudyofConcepts. Cambridge, MA: MITPress(p. 11).Pereboom, Derk(1988). “KantonIntentionality”. In: Synthese 77.3, pp. 321–352. doi:

10.1007/BF00869290 (pp. 18, 19).Pereira, Roberto Horácio de Sá(2013). “WhatisnonconceptualisminKant’sphiloso-

phy?” en. In: PhilosophicalStudies 164.1, pp. 233–254. doi: 10.1007/s11098-011-9851-x (p. 14).

Pippin, Robert B. (1982). Kant’sTheoryofForm: AnEssayontheCritiqueofPureRea-son. en. NewHaven: YaleUniversityPress(p. 23).

— (1989). Hegel’sIdealism: TheSatisfactionsofSelf-Consciousness. en. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress(pp. 21, 25).

Pryor, James(2005). “ThereisImmediateJustification”. In: ContemporaryDebatesinEpistemology. Ed. byMatthias SteupandErnest Sosa. Oxford: Blackwell. Chap. 7,pp. 181–202(p. 23).

Rohs, Peter (2001). “BeziehtsichnachKantdieAnschauungunmittelbaraufGegen-stände?” In: Aktendes9. InternationalenKant-Kongresses. Vol. II. Berlin: WalterDeGruyter, pp. 214–28(p. 22).

Schulting, Dennis(2012). “Kant, Non-ConceptualContentandthe‘SecondStep’oftheB-Deduction”. In: KantStudiesOnline, pp. 51–92(pp. 15, 21).

Sellars, Wilfrid(1956). “EmpiricismandthePhilosophyofMind”. In:Minnesotastudiesinthephilosophyofscience 1, pp. 253–329(p. 22).

— (1963). Science, Perception, andReality. Atascadero, CA: RidgeviewPublishingCompany(pp. 22, 23, 25).

— (1968). ScienceandMetaphysics: Variations onKantianThemes. London: Rout-ledge&KeeganPaul(pp. 15, 23).

Shabel, Lisa(2006). “Kant’sPhilosophyofMathematics”. In: TheCambridgeCompan-ion toKantandModernPhilosophy. Ed. byPaul Guyer. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress, pp. 94–128(p. 10).

Siegel, Susanna(2010). “TheContentsofPerception”. In: TheStanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy. Ed. byEdward N. Zalta. Fall2013(p. 1).

Siegel, SusannaandNicholas Silins(Forthcoming). “TheEpistemologyofPerception”.In:OxfordHandbookofPhilosophyofPerception. Ed. byMohan Matthen. Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress(p. 23).

Smit, Houston(2000). “KantonMarksandtheImmediacyofIntuition”. In: ThePhilo-sophicalReview 109.2, pp. 235–266(p. 4).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 32

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Speaks, Jeff(2005). “IsThereaProblemaboutNonconceptualContent?” In: ThePhilo-sophicalReview 114.3, pp. 359–398(p. 13).

Stevenson, Leslie(2003). “Opinion, BelieforFaith, andKnowledge”. In: KantianReview7.1, pp. 72–101(p. 24).

— (2004). “FreedomofJudgementinDescartes, Hume, SpinozaandKant”. In: Britishjournalforthehistoryofphilosophy 12.2, pp. 223–246(p. 25).

Strawson, Peter Frederick(1966). TheBoundsofSense. London: Routledge(p. 15).— (1970). “ImaginationandPerception”. In: ExperienceandTheory. Ed. byLawrence

FosterandJoe William Swanson. Amherst: UniversityofMassachusetsPress(p. 15).Sturm, Thomas and Falk Wunderlich (2010). “Kant and the Scientific StudyofCon-

sciousness”. In: Historyof thehumansciences 23.3, pp. 48–71. doi: 10.1177/0952695110363355 (p. 5).

Sutherland, Daniel(2008). “ArithmeticfromKanttoFrege: Numbers, PureUnits, andtheLimitsofConceptualRepresentation”. In: KantandPhilosophyofScienceTo-day. Ed. byMichela Massimi. Vol. 63. 1. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress,pp. 135–164. doi: 10.1017/S1358246108000088 (p. 10).

Thompson, Manley(1972). “SingularTermsandIntuitionsinKant’sEpistemology”. In:TheReviewofMetaphysics 26.2, pp. 314–343(p. 16).

Tolley, Clinton (2011). “Kanton theContentofCognition”. In: European JournalofPhilosophy, n/a–n/a. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0378.2011.00483.x (pp. 13, 15).

— (2013). “TheNon-ConceptualityoftheContentofIntuitions: ANewApproach”. In:KantianReview 18.01, pp. 107–136. doi: 10.1017/S1369415412000313 (pp. 8,13, 15, 16, 20, 22, 24).

Van Cleve, James(1999). ProblemsfromKant. Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress(pp. 3,5, 19).

— (2012). “DefiningandDefendingNonconceptualContentsandStates”. In: Philo-sophicalPerspectives 26.1, pp. 411–430(p. 1).

Watkins, Eric(2008). “KantandtheMythoftheGiven”. In: Inquiry 51.5, pp. 512–531(pp. 15, 22, 24, 25).

— (2012). “Kant, Sellars, andtheMythoftheGiven”. en. In: ThePhilosophicalForum43.3, pp. 311–326. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9191.2012.00427.x (pp. 22, 24, 25).

Waxman, Wayne(1991). Kant’sModeloftheMind: ANewInterpretationofTranscen-dentalIdealism. en. Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress(p. 21).

Wenzel, Christian Helmut (2005). “SpielennachKantdieKategorien schonbeiderWahrnehmungeineRolle? PeterRohsundJohnMcDowell”. In: Kant-Studien 96.4,pp. 407–426(p. 21).

Willaschek, Marcus (1997). “DerTranszendentale Idealismus und die Idealität vonRaumundZeit”. In: Zeitschrift fürphilosophischeForschung 51.4, pp. 537–564(pp. 16, 22).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 33

TheKantian(Non)-ConceptualismDebate ColinMcLear

Williams, J. J. (2012). “HowConceptuallyGuidedAreKantianIntuitions?” In: HistoryofPhilosophyQuarterly 29.1, pp. 57–78(p. 2).

Wunderlich, Falk(2005). KantunddieBewußtseinstheoriendes18. Jahrhunderts. de.Berlin: WalterdeGruyter(pp. 5, 6).

July21, 2014—Forthcomingin PhilosophyCompass 34