8
Education The conservation aesthetic and the microscopic aesthetic n 1907, when the noted wildlife management professor and envi- ronmentalist Aldo Leopold (1887-1948) was in college, he com- plained in a letter to his father that he had to "sit four hours a week squinting through a microscope at a little drop of mud all full of wiggly bugs and things, and then draw pic- tures of them and label them with ungodly Latin names" (Meine 1988). This was a rather typical student response to microscopic work, espe- cially for someone like Leopold, who was interested in forestry, not mi- crobiology. It remains true today that ecology and cell biology frequently seem to operate in different biologi- cal worlds. Many ecologists do little laboratory work and see microscopy as something seldom needed in their usual field-based research. Con- versely, many cell biologists and mi- crobiologists who are comfortable with the microscopic world rarely venture outside the laboratory into the macroscopic biological world in the course of their work. This dichotomy exists in many biology departments. Biology ma- jors often come to feel that they must make a choice between these differ- ent approaches to the living world because the approaches seem incom- patible and incapable of being inte- grated. In the case of nonmajors, this carving up of biology makes it diffi- cult for them to appreciate the unity underlying the diversity of the sub- ject. In this article, I attempt to con- struct a bridge between these differ- ing approaches to biology by using aesthetics to demonstrate that the appreciation of the natural world is similar for ecologists and for cell biologists and microbiologists. My argument is that Leopold's "conser- vation aesthetic" can provide guid- ance for teaching students to appre- ciate and understand the microscopic world. The conservation aesthetic Aesthetics is the branch of philoso- phy that deals with the beautiful, both in the natural world and in art. Dewey (1934) argues that any expe- rience, including scientific inquiry, can be aesthetic to the degree that it is an experience-that is, that it in- volves a heightened vitality and ac- tive relationship between the self and the world. Goodman (1968) stresses the cognitive nature of the aesthetic experience; he sees emotion as well as cognition as being involved in under- standing and appreciating the world. He argues that "perception, concep- tion, and feeling intermingle and in- teract" (Goodman 1968). Knowledge, including the factual and the experi- ential, deepens the aesthetic experi- ence and cannot be separated from it; the aesthetic attitude is restless and entails searching and testing. Despite such analyses, aesthetics has not been given much attention in discussions of biological inquiry. One exception is in Leopold's own work- that classic of environmental litera- ture, A Sand County Almanac and Sketches Here and There by Leopold (1949). Callicott (1987) argues that, taking the book as a whole, an ap- propriate aesthetic response to na- ture seems as important to Leopold as an appropriate ethical attitude. Leopold sees aesthetic attraction to nature as a powerful force that needs to be harnessed in efforts to preserve the environment and as a counter- part to his argument for an ethical basis to caring for nature. He con- tends that an approach to nature is right if it preserves not only the in- tegrity and stability of a biotic com- munity but its beauty as well. Sand County has been described as the intellectual touchstone of the environmental movement that blos- somed in the United States in the 1960s and 1970s (Nash 1987). The book is divided into three parts. In the first part, the almanac proper, Leopold chronicles his observations through the seasons on the aban- doned farmland he owned in Sauk County, Wisconsin. Although this discussion is similar to the work of many other nature writers, even in this context Leopold weaves a good deal of ecology into his observa- tions-more than is found in many works of this genre, particularly those published at the time he was writing. The ecological emphasis becomes even more pronounced in the book's second section, in which Leopold ranges more widely, discussing his experiences in nature from Canada to Mexico. In the first essay in this section-on sandhill cranes- Leopold explicitly raises the issue of aesthetics and implies that there are different levels of aesthetic response. This approach is in contrast to the usual treatment of aesthetics in rela- tion to the natural world. Most writ- ers who point to the beauty of nature or of organisms do not delve into what that beauty really involves; that is, they fail to explore the fact that the beauty of nature entails more than just surface beauty. Leopold, on the other hand, notes that "our ability to perceive quality in nature begins, as in art, with the pretty. It expands through succes- sive stages of the beautiful to values as yet uncaptured in language" (Leopold 1949, p. 96). In the appre- ciation of sandhill cranes and their dance, for example, these successive stages come with increased admira- tion for the birds' ecology and evolu- tionary history; knowledge and aes- thetic appreciation are, therefore, linked (Callicott 1987). This con- nection is clear in Leopold's com- by Maura C. Flannery October 1999 801 at Tulane University on October 19, 2014 http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/ Downloaded from

The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

  • Upload
    maura-c

  • View
    226

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

Education

The conservation aesthetic and the

microscopic aesthetic

n 1907, when the noted wildlife management professor and envi- ronmentalist Aldo Leopold

(1887-1948) was in college, he com- plained in a letter to his father that he had to "sit four hours a week squinting through a microscope at a little drop of mud all full of wiggly bugs and things, and then draw pic- tures of them and label them with ungodly Latin names" (Meine 1988). This was a rather typical student response to microscopic work, espe- cially for someone like Leopold, who was interested in forestry, not mi- crobiology. It remains true today that ecology and cell biology frequently seem to operate in different biologi- cal worlds. Many ecologists do little laboratory work and see microscopy as something seldom needed in their usual field-based research. Con- versely, many cell biologists and mi- crobiologists who are comfortable with the microscopic world rarely venture outside the laboratory into the macroscopic biological world in the course of their work.

This dichotomy exists in many biology departments. Biology ma- jors often come to feel that they must make a choice between these differ- ent approaches to the living world because the approaches seem incom- patible and incapable of being inte- grated. In the case of nonmajors, this carving up of biology makes it diffi- cult for them to appreciate the unity underlying the diversity of the sub- ject. In this article, I attempt to con- struct a bridge between these differ- ing approaches to biology by using aesthetics to demonstrate that the appreciation of the natural world is similar for ecologists and for cell biologists and microbiologists. My argument is that Leopold's "conser- vation aesthetic" can provide guid-

ance for teaching students to appre- ciate and understand the microscopic world.

The conservation aesthetic

Aesthetics is the branch of philoso- phy that deals with the beautiful, both in the natural world and in art. Dewey (1934) argues that any expe- rience, including scientific inquiry, can be aesthetic to the degree that it is an experience-that is, that it in- volves a heightened vitality and ac- tive relationship between the self and the world. Goodman (1968) stresses the cognitive nature of the aesthetic experience; he sees emotion as well as cognition as being involved in under- standing and appreciating the world. He argues that "perception, concep- tion, and feeling intermingle and in- teract" (Goodman 1968). Knowledge, including the factual and the experi- ential, deepens the aesthetic experi- ence and cannot be separated from it; the aesthetic attitude is restless and entails searching and testing.

Despite such analyses, aesthetics has not been given much attention in discussions of biological inquiry. One exception is in Leopold's own work- that classic of environmental litera- ture, A Sand County Almanac and Sketches Here and There by Leopold (1949). Callicott (1987) argues that, taking the book as a whole, an ap- propriate aesthetic response to na- ture seems as important to Leopold as an appropriate ethical attitude. Leopold sees aesthetic attraction to nature as a powerful force that needs to be harnessed in efforts to preserve the environment and as a counter- part to his argument for an ethical basis to caring for nature. He con- tends that an approach to nature is right if it preserves not only the in- tegrity and stability of a biotic com- munity but its beauty as well.

Sand County has been described

as the intellectual touchstone of the environmental movement that blos- somed in the United States in the 1960s and 1970s (Nash 1987). The book is divided into three parts. In the first part, the almanac proper, Leopold chronicles his observations through the seasons on the aban- doned farmland he owned in Sauk County, Wisconsin. Although this discussion is similar to the work of many other nature writers, even in this context Leopold weaves a good deal of ecology into his observa- tions-more than is found in many works of this genre, particularly those published at the time he was writing.

The ecological emphasis becomes even more pronounced in the book's second section, in which Leopold ranges more widely, discussing his experiences in nature from Canada to Mexico. In the first essay in this section-on sandhill cranes- Leopold explicitly raises the issue of aesthetics and implies that there are different levels of aesthetic response. This approach is in contrast to the usual treatment of aesthetics in rela- tion to the natural world. Most writ- ers who point to the beauty of nature or of organisms do not delve into what that beauty really involves; that is, they fail to explore the fact that the beauty of nature entails more than just surface beauty.

Leopold, on the other hand, notes that "our ability to perceive quality in nature begins, as in art, with the pretty. It expands through succes- sive stages of the beautiful to values as yet uncaptured in language" (Leopold 1949, p. 96). In the appre- ciation of sandhill cranes and their dance, for example, these successive stages come with increased admira- tion for the birds' ecology and evolu- tionary history; knowledge and aes- thetic appreciation are, therefore, linked (Callicott 1987). This con- nection is clear in Leopold's com- by Maura C. Flannery

October 1999 801

University of California Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve, and extend access to

BioSciencewww.jstor.org

®

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from

Page 2: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

ment that the crane's "tribe stems out of the remote Eocene. The other members of the fauna in which he originated are long since entombed within the hills. When we hear his call we hear no mere bird. We hear the trumpet in the orchestra of evo- lution" (Leopold 1949, p. 96).

Leopold also recounts the history of the marshland-how it developed from a lake formed as an Ice Age glacier receded. The lake was even- tually drained by a river, and the residual lagoons and then marshes attracted cranes; settlers later drained the land and tried to grow crops on it. Their attempts were ultimately unsuccessful; the peat beds were not suited to agriculture. They dried out and fed smoldering fires that could be quenched only by reflooding the land, which made it more suitable, once again, for cranes. Such com- plex evolutionary and ecological sto- ries underlie and deepen apprecia- tion of the visual beauty of the cranes' dance.

It is the third section of Sand County, entitled "The Upshot," that has had the greatest impact on envi- ronmentalists. In this section, Leopold outlines the different kinds of relationships people have with the land and how these relationships af- fect nature. He calls for broadening ethical principles to include an envi- ronmental ethic, which he sums up in the often-quoted lines: "A thing is right when it tends to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community. It is wrong when it tends otherwise" (Leopold 1949, p. 225). The first essay in "The Up- shot" is entitled "Conservation Es- thetic," and the last is called "The Land Ethic." The inclusion of both aesthetics and ethics in this section indicates that Leopold accepted the philosophical position that relates these concepts: There is a connection between the beautiful and the good, and attraction to the beautiful is associated with a proper moral stance. He explores this relationship in "Conservation Esthetic," in which he observes that people go to nature for many reasons because there are many ways to enjoy the land. Conse- quently, there are many approaches to the conservation aesthetic. Leopold argues that there are five categories to this aesthetic, each of

which constitutes a different ap- proach to nature and has varying effects on the natural world. These five categories are the quest for tro- phies, isolation, change of scene, perception, and husbandry.

By comparing Leopold's conser- vation aesthetic to an appreciation of the microscopic world, it becomes clear that the five categories of aes- thetic appreciation of the natural world that he describes can also char- acterize appreciation of the micro- scopic world. At first there may seem to be little resemblance between the experience of forests, prairies, and deserts and that of cells and microor- ganisms. But I will make the case that there are basic similarities be- tween the aesthetic experience of these different levels of biological organization and will show that a focus on these similarities can help students appreciate both the natural and microscopic worlds more fully. In particular, such a focus can make the microscopic world more vividly present to students, leading to a deeper appreciation of this world and, ultimately, a desire to under- stand it more fully.

I should note that I have used the terms natural world and microscopic world as if they were mutually exclu- sive, when the natural world obvi- ously includes much of the micro- scopic world. Nevertheless, when most people refer to the natural world, they usually mean the macroscopic natu- ral world, as Clark (1976) notes in Landscape into Art. It is this sense of the natural world to which Leopold is referring as well-the world that the senses can appreciate directly, without the need for instruments.

Trophy. The first category of Leo- pold's conservation aesthetic is the idea of trophy, the pleasure "in the seeking as well as in the getting...of a bird's egg, a mess of trout, a basket of mushrooms, the photograph of a bear, the pressed specimen of a wild flower, or a note tucked into the cairn on a mountain peak" (Leopold 1949). Leopold sees each of these items as a "certificate" that attests to its owner having "been somewhere and done something" (Leopold 1949).

I see such experiences as similar to the experiences of many neophytes with the microscope. Often in an in-

troductory biology course, one of the first laboratory exercises is the use of this instrument. The activity usually includes observing several specimens and perhaps drawing them. The sighting of the cells in an onion root tip or of a paramecium in a drop of pond water is a trophy in the sense that Leopold uses the word. The drawings of these specimens are like the pressed flower or the photo- graph; they indicate that the student has been somewhere-to the micro- scopic world-and has done some- thing-correctly adjusted the micro- scope and learned to look through the eyepiece well enough to view the activities in that world. This accom- plishment is impressive, particularly for someone who has not used a microscope before, so it is not sur- prising that a student often feels a sense of elation when she finally makes the adjustments correctly and sees something clearly enough to draw it. For some students, this ac- complishment is on a par with a hike in the woods with a camera or a couple of hours fishing. These expe- riences provide students with a sense of ownership-the individual can go home with something, some indica- tion of the journey, some trophy.

For many people, trophy seeking is as far as their appreciation of the land-or of the microscopic world- goes. They may be infrequent hunt- ers or bird watchers-or infrequent users of the microscope. Similarly, after his initial exercise with the mi- croscope, a student might use this instrument only three or four more times in a semester or year of general biology. With these low levels of interaction with the land and with the microscope, it is not surprising that appreciation does not grow much deeper than the thrill of acqui- sition, that it remains on the level of what Erich Fromm (1976) calls "hav- ing" rather than "being."

Isolation. The next category of Leo- pold's conservation aesthetic requires time and a sense of communion with nature. Leopold argues that this cat- egory, the feeling of isolation in na- ture, is more "subtle and complex" than trophy seeking (Leopold 1949). This sense of isolation means isola- tion not from nature, but from other human beings. The feeling of being

802 BioScience Vol. 49 No. 10

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from

Page 3: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

in close contact with the microscopic world also usually comes only to those who spend extended periods of time in that world. In a phenom- enological analysis of microscope use, Heelan (1977) describes the sen- sation, which comes with continued operation of the microscope, that the microscope becomes an exten- sion of the viewer's own body. When the microscope becomes part of the viewer, the microscopic world be- comes more present to the viewer, who is "down" in that world and thus isolated from the macroscopic world.

Many people do not fully appreci- ate the feeling of isolation in nature on their first encounter with a natu- ral environment-or their hundredth, for that matter. This appreciation not only takes time but requires lis- tening to oneself and being willing to appreciate what is going on, both inside onself and in the natural envi- ronment. With such attention, the aesthetic appreciation of the macro- scopic-or the microscopic-world changes, and it becomes not a matter of having that world, of collecting trophies from it, but of being in that world and feeling kinship with it. Some instrumentation allows com- munal viewing of a microscopic speci- men on a video screen or with a device designed for multiple view- ing, and collaborative work in the student laboratory is always impor- tant for student learning. But look- ing through a conventional light mi- croscope-the kind most commonly found in teaching laboratories-in- volves, by the very nature of the activity, separation from other people. Continuing to talk while look- ing at a specimen can make the act of viewing less satisfactory because full attention is not on the specimen. An awareness of oneness, whether with nature or with the microscopic world, requires isolation.

Although Leopold focuses on the idea of isolation as attractive in it- self, the feeling of connection with the natural world that grows out of the isolation is also rewarding. The isolation of microscope viewing can lead to greater understanding of the specimen; a communion with one- self can lead to discoveries arising from the depths of connection to a specimen in isolation. The biologist

Barbara McClintock's experience is an example of this kind of under- standing. Her descriptions of explo- rations at the microscopic level are most revealing about her connection with her work. She tells of being down in the cells, being part of the chromosomes: "I was part of the system.... I actually felt as if I were right down there and these were my friends" (as quoted in Keller 1983, p. 117). It was from this unity that she came to understand what was going on in the cell.

Change of scene. The third of Leo- pold's categories of the conservation aesthetic is "fresh-air and change of scene" (Leopold 1949). For many people, going into the country or forming an attachment to nature is something done on the weekends or on vacation; it provides a change from the ordinary life of indoor work, often in an urban setting. Although time spent looking into a microscope does not provide fresh air, it does involve a change of scene-one per- haps more radical than that of going into the country because it entails not just a change in location but a change of scale. The microscope pro- vides entry into a world that is more totally different from the everyday world than any trip to the country could provide. This is a world where, among other things, organisms have fanciful shapes not seen in larger organisms and where the effect of gravity on organisms is negligible. Of looking into a microscope, Dillard (1974) notes: "I have been almost knocked off my kitchen chair on several occasions when, as I was fol- lowing with strained eyes the tiny career of a monostyla rotifer, an enor- mous red roundworm whipped into the scene, blocking everything, and writhing in huge, flapping convul- sions that seemed to sweep my face and fill the kitchen" (p. 123).

If one of the advantages of a change of scene is that it provides detachment from the stresses of ev- eryday life, then time spent in the microscopic world could be even more rejuvenating because of the great dissimilarity between that world and everyday existence. Anton van Leeuwenhoek's descriptions of his "trips" to the microbial world of pond water or saliva make this point

strongly (Ruestow 1996). This new world was an exciting one for Leeuwenhoek, one that was hard for him to draw himself away from. Nor was Leeuwenhoek alone in taking refuge in the minute world. Micro- scope viewing was the rage in the seventeenth and eighteenth centu- ries, when it was compared to ex- ploring new worlds. In the preface to Micrographia, Robert Hooke (1665) writes that he can introduce readers to terra incognita; in the same vein, Stafford (1991) notes that the exten- sion of vision by the microscope per- mitted a new form of travel.

Just as many writers throughout the ages have found inspiration in nature and in a change of scene, so seventeenth-century and eighteenth- century writers found inspiration in the microscopic world (Nicolson 1956). It was a place to travel to, to wonder at, and to be renewed in. This interest in the microscopic world may seem extreme today, perhaps because we have so many sources of images at the macroscopic level that the microscopic world is just one choice among many far glitzier ones in movie theaters and on computer screens. Also, the microscope is no longer viewed as an instrument of recreation; it is, instead, seen as an instrument of science used in the seri- ous business of scientific inquiry. Nev- ertheless, the microscope remains a vehicle for travel into unseen worlds.

Perception. Leopold's fourth category of the conservation aesthetic is "na- ture study," or "the perception of the natural processes by which the land and the living things upon it have achieved their characteristic forms (evolution) and by which they maintain their existence (ecology)" (Leopold 1949). This category deals with the relationship between aes- thetic experience and knowledge. It involves coming to appreciate the natural world by learning about it. This knowledge can be gained from books and deepened by direct obser- vation and involvement; it includes not only information that can be put into words but also the non- verbalizable "feel" for a topic that Polanyi (1962) calls "tacit knowl- edge" and Pantin (1954) calls "aes- thetic recognition." Leopold notes that promoting appreciation of na-

October 1999 803

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from

Page 4: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

ture entails building perceptions, not roads. In other words, it requires not traveling to remote, unspoiled areas but rather active involvement with the natural world, wherever it may be found.

Implicit in this category of the conservation aesthetic is an inter- play between knowledge, observa- tion, and aesthetic experience; sand- hill cranes, for instance, become more beautiful when their evolutionary history and ecology are explored. Knowledge influences observation and can increase the curiosity to learn more; spending time with nature can extend both knowledge and aesthetic awareness. This reciprocal influence is true of the microscopic world as well, but the problem is that most people do not spend enough time there to experience the interplay be- tween knowledge and experience. To those who do devote enough time, subtle differences in amoeboid be- havior or in cell structure become much more obvious. Microscopic studies lead to appreciation of the responsiveness of microorganisms to subtle changes in the chemistry, light levels, and temperature of their envi- ronment; they also lead to an under- standing of the effect of the proper- ties of water on the behavior of macromolecules and microorgan- isms. As with macroscopic nature, there is a relationship between spend- ing time in that world and the devel- opment of perception. Like isola- tion, perception can lead to a feeling of connection at the microscopic level as well as at the level of macroscopic nature. The more a person knows about the microscopic world, the more at home she is likely to feel in it, and the closer her relationship to it will be.

Husbandry. Husbandry is the fifth of Leopold's categories in the con- servation aesthetic: "The sense of husbandry...is realized only when some art of management is applied to land by some person of percep- tion" (Leopold 1949, p. 175). As an individual comes to understand the land, he is more likely to want to conserve it, more likely to under- stand what conservation means and how it might be accomplished. It is in this way that Leopold's aesthetics and ethics meet, that the conserva-

tion aesthetic becomes a land ethic. Spending time with nature and com- ing to understand it makes it more likely that one will revere nature, see its value, and want to keep this value from deteriorating. But what does husbandry have to do with the mi- croscopic world? This world hardly seems in danger of destruction. There are untold numbers of cells to look at, and because every drop of water in the environment teems with life, there does not seem to be a need for a relationship between a deepening un- derstanding and appreciation of this world and the desire to preserve it.

But husbandry can, in fact, play a role in a relationship with the micro- scopic world. Husbandry connotes value: people husband, preserve, and care for that which they value. And the microscopic world is indeed a valuable one. It is at the base of all ecosystems and essential for the func- tioning of larger life forms. It is also valuable because it extends the field of perception, offering a whole new world to connect with, to be alone in, and to come to understand. And it is valuable as all life is valuable: small size does not diminish this value, although it may make it less obvious. But for most people, these values of the microscopic world are not apparent because they may visit it only a few times during their school years, briefly and without much in- terest beyond trophy collecting. It is seen by most students as a necessary but not very exciting or meaningful part of education-comparable to the multiplication tables or spelling rules, but less useful than either.

A progression. At the end of his essay, Leopold indicates that he sees the five categories of the conserva- tion aesthetic as a progression from a less to a more rich and enlightened view of nature. He notes that "the trophy-hunter is the cave man re- born. Trophy-hunting is the preroga- tive of youth" (Leopold 1949, p. 176). Leopold goes on to discuss the prob- lems of the "trophy-recreationist," im- plying that these two approaches to the conservation aesthetic are the least mature and rich. The implica- tion of progression is seen in his comment that "the disquieting thing in the modern picture is that of the trophy-hunter who never grows up,

in whom the capacity for isolation, perceptions, and husbandry is unde- veloped" (Leopold 1949).

Leopold's five categories can be seen as an inclusive progression; moving from one to another does not necessarily involve totally aban- doning the pleasures of the other levels. A person may continue to bird watch, or take note of particu- lar cellular structures-in other words, trophy hunt-while also seek- ing isolation, recreation, and deep- ening perceptions. It is not that the lower levels are transcended but rather that they are enriched by the greater depth of relationship that can and should evolve. Leopold him- self continued to hunt until near the end of his life and participated in other outdoor recreational activities with his family and friends, but he also valued the hours before dawn for quiet observation of nature. In several of the Sand County essays, he writes of taking his coffee cup and notebook and sitting outside his shack to listen to the birds and see what animals make an appearance in the early morning. In fact, on the morning of the day he died of a heart attack, he had made notes on just such observations.

As I have outlined the microscopic aesthetic, it also involves a progres- sion from a more superficial to a deeper relationship, in this case with the microscopic world. With the microscopic aesthetic, as with the conservation aesthetic, the progres- sion results from greater knowledge and understanding. And here, too, the progression is inclusive. Trophy hunting-finding a particular organ- ism or a particular cellular struc- ture-still has its appeal even after a person has come to also appreciate the joys of spending time in the mi- croscopic world and learning more about it.

Other views

The metaphor I have developed to connect an appreciation of the natu- ral and microscopic worlds reflects a comment made by one of Leopold's own students, H. Albert Hochbaum, who also saw a connection between the experience of nature and of the microscopic. Hochbaum managed the Delta Waterfowl Research Sta-

804 BioScience Vol. 49 No. 10

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from

Page 5: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

tion in Manitoba, Canada, which Leopold had helped to establish. Hochbaum was also one of the people Leopold relied on for advice while writing Sand County. In a 4 Febru- ary 1944 letter to Leopold about one of the essays for the book, Hochbaum noted: "What you write about is a state of mind, probably common to all men. For some, like yourself, it is found in the wilderness; but it isn't the wilderness. What you may feel in the heart of the Sawtooth Moun- tains may be found by another on lower Manhattan before sunrise, by another at the prow of a ship, or on a microscope slide, or in the melody of a song. As such this is indestruc- tible as long as there is life on earth, although certain mediums, such as the wilderness, may be destroyed" (Meine 1988, p. 454). Thus, Hoch- baum also saw that the essence of the experience in the mountains that Leopold describes is something com- mon to all experiences with the liv- ing world, whatever the level of or- ganization.

There may be no better exemplar of the microscopic aesthetic that Hochbaum alluded to than Barbara McClintock. McClintock won the Nobel Prize for Physiology or Medi- cine in 1983 for her work in corn cytogenetics, in which she showed that chromosomes are not unchange- able units of DNA; instead, genes can move from one position to an- other. Her work involved crossing various strains of corn, examining the ears that grew from these crosses, and studying the cells in the corn kernels to figure out how the chro- mosome configurations seen under the microscope correlated with the color patterns in the kernels. McClintock's research therefore re- quired a constant movement between the macroscopic and microscopic worlds to work out the relationship between them-that is, to discover how the microscopic level influences the macroscopic level. Through years of such observation and intimacy, McClintock developed a profound respect for the corn plant and its cells and for their biological secrets. She said that she knew every plant in the field intimately and that she found great pleasure in knowing them. A colleague remarked of McClintock that she would have been able to

write the autobiography of each plant she worked with (Keller 1983). McClintock's connection with her plant cells could indeed be called a sense of husbandry that values the organism as it is.

But McClintock is hardly the only researcher to articulate the micro- scopic aesthetic. Joshua Lederberg spoke of the feeling of being down in a bacterial cell and of becoming part of a chromosome, and he saw this experience as leading to his discov- eries in bacterial genetics (Judson 1980). Goodfield (1981) and Levi- Montalcini (1988) both write about the satisfaction that comes from the experience of examining specimens under a microscope. They comment on the rewards of patient and quiet observation, in terms both of the discoveries made in this way and of their feelings of connection with the cells being viewed.

The rewards of the microscopic aesthetic

Many people's lives, including those of students, would be richer if they followed McClintock and other re- searchers into the microscopic world. Although it is unlikely that micro- scope viewing will again become the fad it was in earlier centuries, the microscopic "land" is a beautiful one that is worthy of prolonged in- vestigation. I am not arguing for a mere trophy relationship with this world. With deeper, more solitary encounters, students could learn things about the microscopic world in the same way that bird watchers learn about the habits of crows or hikers learn of the relationship be- tween plant cover and altitude.

Although the microscopic world can provide experiences that are, in many ways, similar to experiences with the natural world, many biol- ogy teachers neglect to lure students into the world of the small. Yes, equipment is required to perceive this world, but the same is true of camping. Yes, some acquaintance with this world is required to be- come comfortable in it, but the same is true of bird watching. And al- though it may be that using a micro- scope is not as healthful and rejuve- nating as a day in the woods, it may-for some people, at least-be

as invigorating. The microscopic world may pro-

vide more of a refuge as it becomes more and more difficult to experi- ence nature in the way in which Henry David Thoreau and John Muir did. The combination of less and less wilderness, and more and more people wanting to partake of it, leads to the paradox that Leopold touched on in "Conservation Esthetic": the more people who want to connect to nature, the less natural the land be- comes. As truly natural places be- come more inaccessible, alternative ways of relating to the living world must be considered to allow students the enlarging experience of develop- ing a relationship with nature with- out destroying it in the process. Look- ing through a microscope is obviously not the same as viewing the Grand Canyon, but the very fact that it can be done in solitude, unlike visiting the Grand Canyon, is a point in fa- vor of cell watching. Writing of deeply moving experiences in the natural world, Bateson (1994) notes: "More and more, I believe, we will learn to look for epiphanies by look- ing through microscopes" because of the move toward greater urban- ization and destruction of natural environments.

Exploring the metaphor One of the problems with any meta- phor is the danger of similarity being mistaken for identity. The experi- ence of the microscopic world is clearly not the same as the experi- ence of the natural world. Neverthe- less, these worlds have something in common: both are aesthetically rich and therefore worth exploring. At the moment, the natural world is the focus of a great deal more attention from the public than the microscopic world, and this imbalance is likely always to be the case. But biology teachers can encourage more partici- pation in the rewards of the micro- scopic aesthetic by discussing this aesthetic, allowing more time for explorations with the microscope, and inviting students to reflect on what they are seeing and how their experiences of the microscopic world have changed as they have become more proficient in the use of the microscope. Not only would the mi-

October 1999 805

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from

Page 6: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

croscopic aesthetic enrich students' lives, but it might take some pressure off the natural world. So coming to husband-to value-the microscopic world may lead to a husbanding of the natural world as well.

A comparison between the con- servation aesthetic and the micro- scopic aesthetic may help to make the microscopic world more ap- proachable. Most students have at least some appreciation for the natu- ral world, and many have experienced some approaches to the conservation aesthetic-fishing, swimming, or sightseeing. This familiarity might make it easier for them to under- stand that it is possible to develop a similar aesthetic for the microscopic world and that there is more to look- ing in a microscope than finding tro- phies and identifying organisms and structures. The microscopic world is foreign to most students because it is a world with which they have had almost no direct contact and with which any contact must be mediated by instrumentation. It is no wonder that many students do not feel com- fortable in this world and do not see it as a desirable place in which to spend time. The comparison with the natural world may help to make the microscopic world seem a little less foreign.

Through the metaphor of the mi- croscopic aesthetic as similar to the conservation aesthetic, it becomes more obvious that the personal ful- fillment associated with contact with nature can likewise be achieved through other kinds of meaningful contact with living things. Also, there can arise an enlarged view of the concept of husbandry. Husbandry is a word usually linked to farming, but it can be associated with valuing life at all levels. In addition, the microscopic aesthetic can also deepen students' appreciation for the con- servation aesthetic. Black (1955) ar- gues that a metaphor changes one's perception of both subjects in the metaphor, not just that of the pri- mary term, which in this case would be the microscopic aesthetic. There- fore, this metaphor not only changes perceptions of the microscopic aes- thetic by making it more personally significant, but also changes percep- tions of the conservation aesthetic. When it is considered in relation to

the microscopic world, the conser- vation aesthetic can seem more in- tense and more focused and involv- ing the small things in nature, as well as the large.

It is not surprising that students have difficulty making a connection between the microscopic and the macroscopic levels because cells and ecology are usually covered at oppo- site ends of an introductory biology course. Leading students to the valu- ing of both macroscopic and micro- scopic nature may result not only in a greater respect for the environment but also in a better sense of the inter- relationship of life at the macro- scopic and microscopic levels. Such an interrelationship was what Tho- mas (1974) had in mind in describ- ing a similarity between the or- ganelles in a cell and life on Earth as a whole. He writes of cell organelles such as mitochondria and chloro- plasts as living entities, active beings to which he is closely connected. Having described the connection between cells and organelles, he com- pares it to the connections among all living things on Earth. These con- nections are myriad and include re- lationships between the macroscopic and microscopic worlds: Microor- ganisms in the soil are essential to plant growth, plankton are at the base of aquatic food chains, micro- scopic life closes most biogeochemi- cal cycles and is essential for bio- remediation of polluted water-to say nothing of the effect of cellular chemistry on physiology or the ef- fects of disease-causing microorgan- isms on plants and animals, and, indirectly, on ecological interactions. Thus, the natural world that is di- rectly obvious to our senses is highly dependent on the microscopic world.

The aesthetic of biology Another benefit of focusing on both the conservation and microscopic aesthetics is that greater attention will be paid to the aesthetic aspects of both biological inquiry and the study of biology. One reason why Sand County has been such an influ- ential piece of environmental litera- ture is that Leopold clearly articu- lated many reasons for valuing the land (Buell 1995). He recognized the importance of economic, cultural,

and ethical issues, but he also gave attention to the aesthetic as an influ- ence on people's relationship with the land. Yet the aesthetic dimension is sometimes overlooked in discus- sions of why nature should be con- served, and a similar neglect of the aesthetics of biology also occurs in biology education. The excitement of discovery, the pleasure of research, and the satisfaction of developing a relationship with some part of the living world are rarely discussed in classes.

This omission is unfortunate for both science majors and nonmajors. Because nonmajors are not given a glimpse of what is so wonderful about biological inquiry, they may go through life considering biology, and science in general, as an intimidating area of human knowledge. They may even view scientists who enjoy dwell- ing in such an intellectual land as being extraordinary people with whom it would be impossible to iden- tify. More attention to the aesthetic may also be advantageous in the edu- cation of science majors; for example, it might help to retain students who are lost to science because they see it as such a cerebral and unfeeling disci- pline. Focus on the aesthetic in biology may give all students a greater appre- ciation for what scientific inquiry is really about, that is, its subjective as well as its objective aspects.

Aesthetics can also highlight the underlying unity of biology because it can be a bridge linking cell biology and microbiology with ecology. Teach- ers of introductory biology courses are always trying to find ways to re- veal the unity within the discipline because emphasizing coherence in the subject will lead to coherence of thought and create a basic founda- tion on which to build the specifics of the subject matter. The most obvi- ous unifying theme for biology is evolution, but aesthetics can also be a theme that unites the process of biological inquiry at all scales. Sci- ence educators often pay lip service to the importance of having students understand "process" while at the same time continuing to emphasize "product" in their teaching. Focus- ing on the aesthetic provides an op- portunity to make at least one ele- ment of process more central to students' experiences of biology. This

806 BioScience Vol. 49 No. 10

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from

Page 7: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

focus would not be at the expense of a concept-oriented unifying theme such as evolution but rather a comple- ment to it.

The aesthetic can be a way to emphasize both the "ognitive and affective experiences of biology be- cause, as Ralston (1987) notes, the aesthetic experience must be partici- patory-that is, it engages the intel- lect and the emotions. Biologists tend to take the aesthetic for granted in teaching, assuming that the beauty of the subject will become obvious to students as they become familiar with the material. Therefore, biologists do not articulate this aspect of bio- logical inquiry or the fruits of that inquiry-what we know about the living world-and the aesthetic as- pects of biology remain hidden from students not familiar with the sub- ject. Moreover, students may be so overwhelmed by all they have to learn that the beauty of the subject is ob- scured. Because knowledge and aes- thetic sensibility are indeed linked, this beauty does become much more obvious with deep knowledge of a field, and there is ultimately no sub- stitute for such knowledge in terms of appreciation of biology. But bi- ologists should at least let students know that such an experience is con- ceivable-that it is possible, for ex- ample, to derive joy from micro- scopic work.

Something as simple as articulat- ing the microscopic aesthetic is a first step in making students aware of the aesthetic dimension of sci- ence. Asking them to describe how they feel when they have mastered the use of the microscope or gained an understanding of mitosis can help them to see the relationship between knowledge and aesthetic experience. Again, I am advocating not a radical restructuring of the curriculum to make the aesthetic a major focus, but rather a subtle change of empha- sis, something as elementary as al- lowing students time to savor the experience of looking through the microscope and encouraging view- ing even after all the necessary tro- phies have been acquired.

Also helpful in teaching would be the use of more biologically and aes- thetically rich material-pond or creek water instead of a purchased sample containing a single species. A

discussion of the "Conservation Es- thetic" essay could follow microscopic examination of such complex water samples, with students invited to make links between the conserva- tion aesthetic and their experiences with the microscope. This discussion could lead to an exploration of how affective responses influence deci- sion-making about environmental issues. Ultimately, this analysis could provoke discussion of how aesthetic qualities such as balance, rhythm, pattern, and form affect scientific judgment, albeit sometimes detri- mentally. In the history of micros- copy, there are several examples of biologists being seduced by the forms they saw under the microscope and positing structures that turned out to be nonexistent (Ritterbush 1968).

Advocating the introduction of material involving the affective sphere brings up issues of assess- ment. An attitudinal pre-test admin- istered at the beginning of the semes- ter or of a microscopy unit, followed by a post-test given at the end, is one way to measure affective change. But more traditional testing methods can also be used to emphasize the aes- thetic, such as essay questions that ask for discussion of the importance of rhythm, symmetry, order, or other aesthetic qualities in biology. In terms of the conservation aesthetic, stu- dents could be asked which of Leopold's categories best describes their approach to the natural world and to justify their answer. A similar question could be framed concern- ing the microscopic aesthetic. Intro- ducing the aesthetic into assessment not only provides a way to determine how effective teaching strategies have been but also sends a clear message to students that the aesthetic is an important dimension of biological inquiry.

In writing of the place of wildlife education in the instruction of those not planning a career in conserva- tion, Leopold (1943) himself notes a connection between learning and the aesthetic. He writes that his object is to teach the student to see the land, to understand what he sees, and to enjoy what he understands. He adds that the sciences and arts are taught as if they were separate, but "they are separate only in the classroom. Step out of the classroom and they are

immediately fused" (Leopold 1943, p. 8). The aesthetic is one antidote to dismemberment, not only of one part of biology from another, but, as Leopold argues, of the sciences and arts. The aesthetic experience is some- thing the arts and sciences have in common; creativity in both areas involves judgments based on aes- thetic qualities such as unity, bal- ance, and form (Root-Bernstein 1984). Because discussions of aes- thetics usually involve the arts, em- phasis on the aesthetic in science can make a contribution to the kind of integration of disciplines for which calls are often heard today. Empha- sis on the aesthetic in biology teach- ing can therefore have implications well outside of science.

Acknowledgments The initial version of this paper was presented at the 1997 National En- dowment for the Humanities Summer Institute on the Environmental Imagi- nation held at Vassar College, Poughkeepsie, New York. I would like to thank the Institute's director, Daniel Peck, and the participants for their insights and support; St. John's Uni- versity for research support; and the reviewers of this manuscript for their perceptive and useful comments.

References cited Bateson MC. 1994. Peripheral Visions. New

York: HarperCollins. Black M. 1955. Metaphor. Proceedings of

the Aristotelian Society 55: 273-294. Buell L. 1995. The Environmental Imagina-

tion: Thoreau, Nature Writing, and the Formation of American Culture. Cam- bridge (MA): Harvard University Press.

Callicott JB. 1987. The land aesthetic. Pages 157-171 in Callicott JB, ed. Companion to A Sand County Almanac: Interpretive and Critical Essays. Madison (WI): Uni- versity of Wisconsin Press.

Clark K. 1976. Landscape Into Art. New York: Harper & Row.

Dewey J. 1934. Art and Experience. New York: Putnam.

Dillard A. 1974. Pilgrim at Tinker Creek. New York: Harper's Magazine Press.

Fromm E. 1976. To Have and To Be? New York: Harper & Row.

Goodfield J. 1981. An Imagined World: A Story of Scientific Discovery. New York: Harper & Row.

Goodman N. 1968. Languages of Art. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.

Heelan P. 1977. Hermeneutics of experimen- tal science in the context of the life-world. Pages 7-50 in Ihde D, Zaner R, eds. Inter-

October 1999 807

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from

Page 8: The Conservation Aesthetic and the Microscopic Aesthetic

AlItheyneed is math atid science

0

to change their course 0

tin hi*stor Y Developing countries depend on developing minds. And

that takes g(xxi teaching. As a Peace Corps Volunteer

teaching math or science, your experience is needed to

prepare students for higher education and future jobs that can help a developing country join the technological revolution.

For further infon-nation on this project or any one

of many other projects volunteers are needed for in

today's Peace Corps, call toll-free 800-424-8580. And put

your expenence to xvork where it can do a xvorld of good.

U-S-PeaceCorps. The toughest job you'l I ever love.

A Public Service of This Publicafion nuk I

disciplinary Phenomenology. The Hague (The Netherlands): Martinus Nijhoff.

Hooke R. 1665. Micrographia: Or Some Physiological Descriptions of Minute Bod- ies Made By Magnifying Glasses With Observations and Inquires Thereupon. London: James Allestry.

Judson HF. 1980. The Search for Solutions. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Keller EF. 1983. A Feeling for the Organism. New York: Freeman.

Leopold A. 1943. The role of wildlife in a liberal education. Michigan Conservation 12: 8.

. 1949. A Sand County Almanac and Sketches Here and There. New York: Oxford University Press.

Levi-Montalcini R. 1988. In Praise of Imper- fection: My Life and Work. New York: Basic Books.

Meine C. 1988. Aldo Leopold: His Life and Work. Madison (WI): University of Wis- consin Press.

Nash R. 1987. Aldo Leopold's intellectual heritage. Pages 63-88 in Callicott JB, ed. Companion to A Sand County Almanac: Interpretive and Critical Essays. Madison (WI): University of Wisconsin Press.

Nicolson M. 1956. Science and Imagination. Ithaca (NY): Cornell University Press.

Pantin CFA. 1954. The recognition of spe- cies. Science Progress 42: 587-598.

Polanyi M. 1962. Personal Knowledge. Chi- cago: University of Chicago Press.

Ralston H. 1987. Duties to ecosystems. Pages 246-274 in Callicott JB, ed. Companion to A Sand County Almanac: Interpretive and Critical Essays. Madison (WI): Uni- versity of Wisconsin Press

Ritterbush P. 1968. The Art of Organic Form. Washington (DC): Smithsonian Institu- tion Press.

Root-Bernstein R. 1984. Creative process as a unifying theme of human cultures. Daedalus 113: 197-219.

Ruestow E. 1996. The Microscope in the Dutch Republic. Cambridge (UK): Cam- bridge University Press.

Stafford B. 1991. Body Criticism: Imaging the Unseen in Enlightenment Art and Medicine. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.

Thomas L. 1974. The Lives of a Cell: Notes of a Biology Watcher. New York: Viking.

Maura C. Flannery (e-mail: flannerm@ stjohns.edu) is a professor of biology and assistant director of the Center for Teach- ing and Learning at St. John's University, Jamaica, NY 11439. She studies ap- proaches to communicating biology to nonscientists. ? 1999 American Institute of Biological Sciences.

BioScience Vol. 49 No. 10

at Tulane U

niversity on October 19, 2014

http://bioscience.oxfordjournals.org/D

ownloaded from