33
Pseudo-order From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Pseudo Order

  • Upload
    man

  • View
    35

  • Download
    1

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopediaLexicographic order

Citation preview

Page 1: Pseudo Order

Pseudo-orderFrom Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Page 2: Pseudo Order

Contents

1 Apartness relation 11.1 Description . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.2 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2

2 Binary relation 32.1 Formal definition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3

2.1.1 Is a relation more than its graph? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42.1.2 Example . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4

2.2 Special types of binary relations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42.2.1 Difunctional . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6

2.3 Relations over a set . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62.4 Operations on binary relations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7

2.4.1 Complement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82.4.2 Restriction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82.4.3 Algebras, categories, and rewriting systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9

2.5 Sets versus classes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 92.6 The number of binary relations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 92.7 Examples of common binary relations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102.8 See also . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102.9 Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102.10 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 112.11 External links . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12

3 Indecomposability 133.1 See also . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 133.2 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13

4 Partially ordered set 144.1 Formal definition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154.2 Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154.3 Extrema . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154.4 Orders on the Cartesian product of partially ordered sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 164.5 Sums of partially ordered sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16

i

Page 3: Pseudo Order

ii CONTENTS

4.6 Strict and non-strict partial orders . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 174.7 Inverse and order dual . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 174.8 Mappings between partially ordered sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 174.9 Number of partial orders . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 184.10 Linear extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 184.11 In category theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 194.12 Partial orders in topological spaces . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 194.13 Interval . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 194.14 See also . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 194.15 Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 204.16 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 204.17 External links . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20

5 Pseudo-order 215.1 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21

6 Total order 226.1 Strict total order . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226.2 Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236.3 Further concepts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23

6.3.1 Chains . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236.3.2 Lattice theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236.3.3 Finite total orders . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 246.3.4 Category theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 246.3.5 Order topology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 246.3.6 Completeness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 246.3.7 Sums of orders . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24

6.4 Orders on the Cartesian product of totally ordered sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 256.5 Related structures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 256.6 See also . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 256.7 Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 256.8 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26

7 Trichotomy (mathematics) 277.1 See also . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 277.2 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 277.3 Text and image sources, contributors, and licenses . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29

7.3.1 Text . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297.3.2 Images . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297.3.3 Content license . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30

Page 4: Pseudo Order

Chapter 1

Apartness relation

“Apart” redirects here. For the song by The Cure, see Wish (The Cure album). For the 2011 film, see Apart (film).

In constructive mathematics, an apartness relation is a constructive form of inequality, and is often taken to be morebasic than equality. It is often written as # to distinguish from the negation of equality (the denial inequality) ≠, whichis weaker.

1.1 Description

An apartness relation is a symmetric irreflexive binary relation with the additional condition that if two elements are apart, then any other element is apart from at least one of them (this last property is often called co-transitivity or comparison) .

That is, a binary relation # is an apartness relation if it satisfies:[1]

1. ¬ (x#x)

2. x#y → y#x

3. x#y → (x#z ∨ y#z)

The negation of an apartness relation is an equivalence relation, as the above three conditions become reflexivity,symmetry, and transitivity. If this equivalence relation is in fact equality, then the apartness relation is called tight.That is, # is a tight apartness relation if it additionally satisfies:

¬ (x#y) → x = y

In classical mathematics, it also follows that every apartness relation is the negation of an equivalence relation, andthe only tight apartness relation on a given set is the negation of equality. So in that domain, the concept is not useful.In constructive mathematics, however, this is not the case.The prototypical apartness relation is that of the real numbers: two real numbers are said to be apart if there exists(one can construct) a rational number between them. In other words, real numbers x and y are apart if there existsa rational number z such that x < z < y or y < z < x. The natural apartness relation of the real numbers is then thedisjunction of its natural pseudo-order. The complex numbers, real vector spaces, and indeed any metric space thennaturally inherit the apartness relation of the real numbers, even though they do not come equipped with any naturalordering.If there is no rational number between two real numbers, then the two real numbers are equal. Classically, then, iftwo real numbers are not equal, one would conclude that there exists a rational number between them. However itdoes not follow that one can actually construct such a number. Thus to say two real numbers are apart is a strongerstatement, constructively, than to say that they are not equal, and while equality of real numbers is definable in terms

1

Page 5: Pseudo Order

2 CHAPTER 1. APARTNESS RELATION

of their apartness, the apartness of real numbers cannot be defined in terms of their equality. For this reason, inconstructive topology especially, the apartness relation over a set is often taken as primitive, and equality is a definedrelation.A set endowed with an apartness relation is known as a constructive setoid. A function f : A → B where A and Bare constructive setoids is called a morphism for #A and #B if ∀x, y : A. f(x) #B f(y) ⇒ x #A y .

1.2 References[1] Troelstra, A. S.; Schwichtenberg, H. (2000), Basic proof theory, Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science 43

(2nd ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p. 136, doi:10.1017/CBO9781139168717, ISBN 0-521-77911-1, MR1776976.

Page 6: Pseudo Order

Chapter 2

Binary relation

“Relation (mathematics)" redirects here. For a more general notion of relation, see finitary relation. For a morecombinatorial viewpoint, see theory of relations. For other uses, see Relation § Mathematics.

In mathematics, a binary relation on a set A is a collection of ordered pairs of elements of A. In other words, it is asubset of the Cartesian product A2 = A × A. More generally, a binary relation between two sets A and B is a subsetof A × B. The terms correspondence, dyadic relation and 2-place relation are synonyms for binary relation.An example is the "divides" relation between the set of prime numbers P and the set of integers Z, in which everyprime p is associated with every integer z that is a multiple of p (but with no integer that is not a multiple of p). Inthis relation, for instance, the prime 2 is associated with numbers that include −4, 0, 6, 10, but not 1 or 9; and theprime 3 is associated with numbers that include 0, 6, and 9, but not 4 or 13.Binary relations are used in many branches of mathematics to model concepts like "is greater than", "is equal to", and“divides” in arithmetic, "is congruent to" in geometry, “is adjacent to” in graph theory, “is orthogonal to” in linearalgebra and many more. The concept of function is defined as a special kind of binary relation. Binary relations arealso heavily used in computer science.A binary relation is the special case n = 2 of an n-ary relation R ⊆ A1 × … × An, that is, a set of n-tuples where thejth component of each n-tuple is taken from the jth domain Aj of the relation. An example for a ternary relation onZ×Z×Z is “lies between ... and ...”, containing e.g. the triples (5,2,8), (5,8,2), and (−4,9,−7).In some systems of axiomatic set theory, relations are extended to classes, which are generalizations of sets. Thisextension is needed for, among other things, modeling the concepts of “is an element of” or “is a subset of” in settheory, without running into logical inconsistencies such as Russell’s paradox.

2.1 Formal definition

A binary relation R is usually defined as an ordered triple (X, Y, G) where X and Y are arbitrary sets (or classes), andG is a subset of the Cartesian product X × Y. The sets X and Y are called the domain (or the set of departure) andcodomain (or the set of destination), respectively, of the relation, and G is called its graph.The statement (x,y) ∈ G is read "x is R-related to y", and is denoted by xRy or R(x,y). The latter notation correspondsto viewing R as the characteristic function on X × Y for the set of pairs of G.The order of the elements in each pair ofG is important: if a ≠ b, then aRb and bRa can be true or false, independentlyof each other. Resuming the above example, the prime 3 divides the integer 9, but 9 doesn't divide 3.A relation as defined by the triple (X, Y, G) is sometimes referred to as a correspondence instead.[1] In this case therelation from X to Y is the subset G of X × Y, and “from X to Y" must always be either specified or implied by thecontext when referring to the relation. In practice correspondence and relation tend to be used interchangeably.

3

Page 7: Pseudo Order

4 CHAPTER 2. BINARY RELATION

2.1.1 Is a relation more than its graph?

According to the definition above, two relations with identical graphs but different domains or different codomainsare considered different. For example, ifG = {(1, 2), (1, 3), (2, 7)} , then (Z,Z, G) , (R,N, G) , and (N,R, G) arethree distinct relations, where Z is the set of integers and R is the set of real numbers.Especially in set theory, binary relations are often defined as sets of ordered pairs, identifying binary relations withtheir graphs. The domain of a binary relation R is then defined as the set of all x such that there exists at least oney such that (x, y) ∈ R , the range of R is defined as the set of all y such that there exists at least one x such that(x, y) ∈ R , and the field of R is the union of its domain and its range.[2][3][4]

A special case of this difference in points of view applies to the notion of function. Many authors insist on distin-guishing between a function’s codomain and its range. Thus, a single “rule,” like mapping every real number x tox2, can lead to distinct functions f : R → R and f : R → R+ , depending on whether the images under thatrule are understood to be reals or, more restrictively, non-negative reals. But others view functions as simply sets ofordered pairs with unique first components. This difference in perspectives does raise some nontrivial issues. As anexample, the former camp considers surjectivity—or being onto—as a property of functions, while the latter sees itas a relationship that functions may bear to sets.Either approach is adequate for most uses, provided that one attends to the necessary changes in language, notation,and the definitions of concepts like restrictions, composition, inverse relation, and so on. The choice between the twodefinitions usually matters only in very formal contexts, like category theory.

2.1.2 Example

Example: Suppose there are four objects {ball, car, doll, gun} and four persons {John, Mary, Ian, Venus}. Supposethat John owns the ball, Mary owns the doll, and Venus owns the car. Nobody owns the gun and Ian owns nothing.Then the binary relation “is owned by” is given as

R = ({ball, car, doll, gun}, {John, Mary, Ian, Venus}, {(ball, John), (doll, Mary), (car, Venus)}).

Thus the first element of R is the set of objects, the second is the set of persons, and the last element is a set of orderedpairs of the form (object, owner).The pair (ball, John), denoted by ₐ RJₒ means that the ball is owned by John.Two different relations could have the same graph. For example: the relation

({ball, car, doll, gun}, {John, Mary, Venus}, {(ball, John), (doll, Mary), (car, Venus)})

is different from the previous one as everyone is an owner. But the graphs of the two relations are the same.Nevertheless, R is usually identified or even defined as G(R) and “an ordered pair (x, y) ∈ G(R)" is usually denoted as"(x, y) ∈ R".

2.2 Special types of binary relations

Some important types of binary relations R between two sets X and Y are listed below. To emphasize that X and Ycan be different sets, some authors call such binary relations heterogeneous.[5][6]

Uniqueness properties:

• injective (also called left-unique[7]): for all x and z in X and y in Y it holds that if xRy and zRy then x = z. Forexample, the green relation in the diagram is injective, but the red relation is not, as it relates e.g. both x = −5and z = +5 to y = 25.

• functional (also called univalent[8] or right-unique[7] or right-definite[9]): for all x in X, and y and z in Yit holds that if xRy and xRz then y = z; such a binary relation is called a partial function. Both relations inthe picture are functional. An example for a non-functional relation can be obtained by rotating the red graphclockwise by 90 degrees, i.e. by considering the relation x=y2 which relates e.g. x=25 to both y=−5 and z=+5.

Page 8: Pseudo Order

2.2. SPECIAL TYPES OF BINARY RELATIONS 5

Example relations between real numbers. Red: y=x2. Green: y=2x+20.

• one-to-one (also written 1-to-1): injective and functional. The green relation is one-to-one, but the red is not.

Totality properties:

• left-total:[7] for all x in X there exists a y in Y such that xRy. For example R is left-total when it is a functionor a multivalued function. Note that this property, although sometimes also referred to as total, is differentfrom the definition of total in the next section. Both relations in the picture are left-total. The relation x=y2,obtained from the above rotation, is not left-total, as it doesn't relate, e.g., x = −14 to any real number y.

• surjective (also called right-total[7] or onto): for all y in Y there exists an x in X such that xRy. The greenrelation is surjective, but the red relation is not, as it doesn't relate any real number x to e.g. y = −14.

Uniqueness and totality properties:

Page 9: Pseudo Order

6 CHAPTER 2. BINARY RELATION

• A function: a relation that is functional and left-total. Both the green and the red relation are functions.

• An injective function: a relation that is injective, functional, and left-total.

• A surjective function or surjection: a relation that is functional, left-total, and right-total.

• A bijection: a surjective one-to-one or surjective injective function is said to be bijective, also known asone-to-one correspondence.[10] The green relation is bijective, but the red is not.

2.2.1 Difunctional

Less commonly encountered is the notion of difunctional (or regular) relation, defined as a relation R such thatR=RR−1R.[11]

To understand this notion better, it helps to consider a relation as mapping every element x∈X to a set xR = { y∈Y| xRy }.[11] This set is sometimes called the successor neighborhood of x in R; one can define the predecessorneighborhood analogously.[12] Synonymous terms for these notions are afterset and respectively foreset.[5]

A difunctional relation can then be equivalently characterized as a relation R such that wherever x1R and x2R have anon-empty intersection, then these two sets coincide; formally x1R ∩ x2R ≠ ∅ implies x1R = x2R.[11]

As examples, any function or any functional (right-unique) relation is difunctional; the converse doesn't hold. If oneconsiders a relation R from set to itself (X = Y), then if R is both transitive and symmetric (i.e. a partial equivalencerelation), then it is also difunctional.[13] The converse of this latter statement also doesn't hold.A characterization of difunctional relations, which also explains their name, is to consider two functions f: A → Cand g: B→ C and then define the following set which generalizes the kernel of a single function as joint kernel: ker(f,g) = { (a, b) ∈ A × B | f(a) = g(b) }. Every difunctional relation R ⊆ A × B arises as the joint kernel of two functionsf: A→ C and g: B→ C for some set C.[14]

In automata theory, the term rectangular relation has also been used to denote a difunctional relation. This ter-minology is justified by the fact that when represented as a boolean matrix, the columns and rows of a difunctionalrelation can be arranged in such a way as to present rectangular blocks of true on the (asymmetric) main diagonal.[15]Other authors however use the term “rectangular” to denote any heterogeneous relation whatsoever.[6]

2.3 Relations over a set

If X = Y then we simply say that the binary relation is over X, or that it is an endorelation over X.[16] In computerscience, such a relation is also called a homogeneous (binary) relation.[6][16][17] Some types of endorelations arewidely studied in graph theory, where they are known as simple directed graphs permitting loops.The set of all binary relations Rel(X) on a set X is the set 2X × X which is a Boolean algebra augmented with theinvolution of mapping of a relation to its inverse relation. For the theoretical explanation see Relation algebra.Some important properties of a binary relation R over a set X are:

• reflexive: for all x in X it holds that xRx. For example, “greater than or equal to” (≥) is a reflexive relation but“greater than” (>) is not.

• irreflexive (or strict): for all x in X it holds that not xRx. For example, > is an irreflexive relation, but ≥ is not.

• coreflexive: for all x and y in X it holds that if xRy then x = y. An example of a coreflexive relation is therelation on integers in which each odd number is related to itself and there are no other relations. The equalityrelation is the only example of a both reflexive and coreflexive relation.

The previous 3 alternatives are far from being exhaustive; e.g. the red relation y=x2 from theabove picture is neither irreflexive, nor coreflexive, nor reflexive, since it contains the pair(0,0), and (2,4), but not (2,2), respectively.

• symmetric: for all x and y in X it holds that if xRy then yRx. “Is a blood relative of” is a symmetric relation,because x is a blood relative of y if and only if y is a blood relative of x.

Page 10: Pseudo Order

2.4. OPERATIONS ON BINARY RELATIONS 7

• antisymmetric: for all x and y in X, if xRy and yRx then x = y. For example, ≥ is anti-symmetric (so is >, butonly because the condition in the definition is always false).[18]

• asymmetric: for all x and y in X, if xRy then not yRx. A relation is asymmetric if and only if it is bothanti-symmetric and irreflexive.[19] For example, > is asymmetric, but ≥ is not.

• transitive: for all x, y and z inX it holds that if xRy and yRz then xRz. For example, “is ancestor of” is transitive,while “is parent of” is not. A transitive relation is irreflexive if and only if it is asymmetric.[20]

• total: for all x and y in X it holds that xRy or yRx (or both). This definition for total is different from left totalin the previous section. For example, ≥ is a total relation.

• trichotomous: for all x and y in X exactly one of xRy, yRx or x = y holds. For example, > is a trichotomousrelation, while the relation “divides” on natural numbers is not.[21]

• Right Euclidean: for all x, y and z in X it holds that if xRy and xRz, then yRz.

• Left Euclidean: for all x, y and z in X it holds that if yRx and zRx, then yRz.

• Euclidean: An Euclidean relation is both left and right Euclidean. Equality is a Euclidean relation because ifx=y and x=z, then y=z.

• serial: for all x in X, there exists y in X such that xRy. "Is greater than" is a serial relation on the integers. Butit is not a serial relation on the positive integers, because there is no y in the positive integers (i.e. the naturalnumbers) such that 1>y.[22] However, "is less than" is a serial relation on the positive integers, the rationalnumbers and the real numbers. Every reflexive relation is serial: for a given x, choose y=x. A serial relation canbe equivalently characterized as every element having a non-empty successor neighborhood (see the previoussection for the definition of this notion). Similarly an inverse serial relation is a relation in which every elementhas non-empty predecessor neighborhood.[12]

• set-like (or local): for every x in X, the class of all y such that yRx is a set. (This makes sense only if relationson proper classes are allowed.) The usual ordering < on the class of ordinal numbers is set-like, while its inverse> is not.

A relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive is called an equivalence relation. A relation that is symmetric,transitive, and serial is also reflexive. A relation that is only symmetric and transitive (without necessarily beingreflexive) is called a partial equivalence relation.A relation that is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive is called a partial order. A partial order that is total is calleda total order, simple order, linear order, or a chain.[23] A linear order where every nonempty subset has a least elementis called a well-order.

2.4 Operations on binary relations

If R, S are binary relations over X and Y, then each of the following is a binary relation over X and Y :

• Union: R ∪ S ⊆ X × Y, defined as R ∪ S = { (x, y) | (x, y) ∈ R or (x, y) ∈ S }. For example, ≥ is the union of >and =.

• Intersection: R ∩ S ⊆ X × Y, defined as R ∩ S = { (x, y) | (x, y) ∈ R and (x, y) ∈ S }.

If R is a binary relation over X and Y, and S is a binary relation over Y and Z, then the following is a binary relationover X and Z: (see main article composition of relations)

• Composition: S ∘ R, also denoted R ; S (or more ambiguously R ∘ S), defined as S ∘ R = { (x, z) | there existsy ∈ Y, such that (x, y) ∈ R and (y, z) ∈ S }. The order of R and S in the notation S ∘ R, used here agrees withthe standard notational order for composition of functions. For example, the composition “is mother of” ∘ “isparent of” yields “is maternal grandparent of”, while the composition “is parent of” ∘ “is mother of” yields “isgrandmother of”.

Page 11: Pseudo Order

8 CHAPTER 2. BINARY RELATION

A relation R on sets X and Y is said to be contained in a relation S on X and Y if R is a subset of S, that is, if x R yalways implies x S y. In this case, if R and S disagree, R is also said to be smaller than S. For example, > is containedin ≥.If R is a binary relation over X and Y, then the following is a binary relation over Y and X:

• Inverse or converse: R −1, defined as R −1 = { (y, x) | (x, y) ∈ R }. A binary relation over a set is equal to itsinverse if and only if it is symmetric. See also duality (order theory). For example, “is less than” (<) is theinverse of “is greater than” (>).

If R is a binary relation over X, then each of the following is a binary relation over X:

• Reflexive closure: R =, defined as R = = { (x, x) | x ∈ X } ∪ R or the smallest reflexive relation over X containingR. This can be proven to be equal to the intersection of all reflexive relations containing R.

• Reflexive reduction: R ≠, defined as R ≠ = R \ { (x, x) | x ∈ X } or the largest irreflexive relation over Xcontained in R.

• Transitive closure: R +, defined as the smallest transitive relation over X containing R. This can be seen to beequal to the intersection of all transitive relations containing R.

• Transitive reduction: R −, defined as a minimal relation having the same transitive closure as R.

• Reflexive transitive closure: R *, defined as R * = (R +) =, the smallest preorder containing R.

• Reflexive transitive symmetric closure: R ≡, defined as the smallest equivalence relation over X containingR.

2.4.1 Complement

If R is a binary relation over X and Y, then the following too:

• The complement S is defined as x S y if not x R y. For example, on real numbers, ≤ is the complement of >.

The complement of the inverse is the inverse of the complement.If X = Y, the complement has the following properties:

• If a relation is symmetric, the complement is too.

• The complement of a reflexive relation is irreflexive and vice versa.

• The complement of a strict weak order is a total preorder and vice versa.

The complement of the inverse has these same properties.

2.4.2 Restriction

The restriction of a binary relation on a set X to a subset S is the set of all pairs (x, y) in the relation for which x andy are in S.If a relation is reflexive, irreflexive, symmetric, antisymmetric, asymmetric, transitive, total, trichotomous, a partialorder, total order, strict weak order, total preorder (weak order), or an equivalence relation, its restrictions are too.However, the transitive closure of a restriction is a subset of the restriction of the transitive closure, i.e., in generalnot equal. For example, restricting the relation "x is parent of y" to females yields the relation "x is mother ofthe woman y"; its transitive closure doesn't relate a woman with her paternal grandmother. On the other hand, thetransitive closure of “is parent of” is “is ancestor of"; its restriction to females does relate a woman with her paternalgrandmother.

Page 12: Pseudo Order

2.5. SETS VERSUS CLASSES 9

Also, the various concepts of completeness (not to be confused with being “total”) do not carry over to restrictions.For example, on the set of real numbers a property of the relation "≤" is that every non-empty subset S of R with anupper bound in R has a least upper bound (also called supremum) in R. However, for a set of rational numbers thissupremum is not necessarily rational, so the same property does not hold on the restriction of the relation "≤" to theset of rational numbers.The left-restriction (right-restriction, respectively) of a binary relation between X and Y to a subset S of its domain(codomain) is the set of all pairs (x, y) in the relation for which x (y) is an element of S.

2.4.3 Algebras, categories, and rewriting systems

Various operations on binary endorelations can be treated as giving rise to an algebraic structure, known as relationalgebra. It should not be confused with relational algebra which deals in finitary relations (and in practice also finiteand many-sorted).For heterogenous binary relations, a category of relations arises.[6]

Despite their simplicity, binary relations are at the core of an abstract computation model known as an abstractrewriting system.

2.5 Sets versus classes

Certain mathematical “relations”, such as “equal to”, “member of”, and “subset of”, cannot be understood to be binaryrelations as defined above, because their domains and codomains cannot be taken to be sets in the usual systems ofaxiomatic set theory. For example, if we try to model the general concept of “equality” as a binary relation =, wemust take the domain and codomain to be the “class of all sets”, which is not a set in the usual set theory.In most mathematical contexts, references to the relations of equality, membership and subset are harmless becausethey can be understood implicitly to be restricted to some set in the context. The usual work-around to this problemis to select a “large enough” set A, that contains all the objects of interest, and work with the restriction =A instead of=. Similarly, the “subset of” relation ⊆ needs to be restricted to have domain and codomain P(A) (the power set ofa specific set A): the resulting set relation can be denoted ⊆A. Also, the “member of” relation needs to be restrictedto have domain A and codomain P(A) to obtain a binary relation ∈A that is a set. Bertrand Russell has shown thatassuming ∈ to be defined on all sets leads to a contradiction in naive set theory.Another solution to this problem is to use a set theory with proper classes, such as NBG or Morse–Kelley set theory,and allow the domain and codomain (and so the graph) to be proper classes: in such a theory, equality, membership,and subset are binary relations without special comment. (A minor modification needs to be made to the concept ofthe ordered triple (X, Y, G), as normally a proper class cannot be a member of an ordered tuple; or of course onecan identify the function with its graph in this context.)[24] With this definition one can for instance define a functionrelation between every set and its power set.

2.6 The number of binary relations

The number of distinct binary relations on an n-element set is 2n2 (sequence A002416 in OEIS):Notes:

• The number of irreflexive relations is the same as that of reflexive relations.

• The number of strict partial orders (irreflexive transitive relations) is the same as that of partial orders.

• The number of strict weak orders is the same as that of total preorders.

• The total orders are the partial orders that are also total preorders. The number of preorders that are neithera partial order nor a total preorder is, therefore, the number of preorders, minus the number of partial orders,minus the number of total preorders, plus the number of total orders: 0, 0, 0, 3, and 85, respectively.

• the number of equivalence relations is the number of partitions, which is the Bell number.

Page 13: Pseudo Order

10 CHAPTER 2. BINARY RELATION

The binary relations can be grouped into pairs (relation, complement), except that for n = 0 the relation is its owncomplement. The non-symmetric ones can be grouped into quadruples (relation, complement, inverse, inverse com-plement).

2.7 Examples of common binary relations

• order relations, including strict orders:

• greater than• greater than or equal to• less than• less than or equal to• divides (evenly)• is a subset of

• equivalence relations:

• equality• is parallel to (for affine spaces)• is in bijection with• isomorphy

• dependency relation, a finite, symmetric, reflexive relation.

• independency relation, a symmetric, irreflexive relation which is the complement of some dependency relation.

2.8 See also

• Confluence (term rewriting)

• Hasse diagram

• Incidence structure

• Logic of relatives

• Order theory

• Triadic relation

2.9 Notes[1] Encyclopedic dictionary of Mathematics. MIT. 2000. pp. 1330–1331. ISBN 0-262-59020-4.

[2] Suppes, Patrick (1972) [originally published by D. van Nostrand Company in 1960]. Axiomatic Set Theory. Dover. ISBN0-486-61630-4.

[3] Smullyan, Raymond M.; Fitting, Melvin (2010) [revised and corrected republication of the work originally published in1996 by Oxford University Press, New York]. Set Theory and the Continuum Problem. Dover. ISBN 978-0-486-47484-7.

[4] Levy, Azriel (2002) [republication of the work published by Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg and New York in 1979].Basic Set Theory. Dover. ISBN 0-486-42079-5.

[5] Christodoulos A. Floudas; PanosM. Pardalos (2008). Encyclopedia of Optimization (2nd ed.). Springer Science&BusinessMedia. pp. 299–300. ISBN 978-0-387-74758-3.

Page 14: Pseudo Order

2.10. REFERENCES 11

[6] Michael Winter (2007). Goguen Categories: A Categorical Approach to L-fuzzy Relations. Springer. pp. x–xi. ISBN978-1-4020-6164-6.

[7] Kilp, Knauer and Mikhalev: p. 3. The same four definitions appear in the following:

• Peter J. Pahl; Rudolf Damrath (2001). Mathematical Foundations of Computational Engineering: A Handbook.Springer Science & Business Media. p. 506. ISBN 978-3-540-67995-0.

• Eike Best (1996). Semantics of Sequential and Parallel Programs. Prentice Hall. pp. 19–21. ISBN 978-0-13-460643-9.

• Robert-Christoph Riemann (1999). Modelling of Concurrent Systems: Structural and Semantical Methods in the HighLevel Petri Net Calculus. Herbert Utz Verlag. pp. 21–22. ISBN 978-3-89675-629-9.

[8] Gunther Schmidt, 2010. Relational Mathematics. Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-76268-7, Chapt. 5

[9] Mäs, Stephan (2007), “Reasoning on Spatial Semantic Integrity Constraints”, Spatial Information Theory: 8th InternationalConference, COSIT 2007, Melbourne, Australia, September 19–23, 2007, Proceedings, Lecture Notes in Computer Science4736, Springer, pp. 285–302, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-74788-8_18

[10] Note that the use of “correspondence” here is narrower than as general synonym for binary relation.

[11] Chris Brink; Wolfram Kahl; Gunther Schmidt (1997). Relational Methods in Computer Science. Springer Science &Business Media. p. 200. ISBN 978-3-211-82971-4.

[12] Yao, Y. (2004). “Semantics of Fuzzy Sets in Rough Set Theory”. Transactions on Rough Sets II. Lecture Notes in ComputerScience 3135. p. 297. doi:10.1007/978-3-540-27778-1_15. ISBN 978-3-540-23990-1.

[13] William Craig (2006). Semigroups Underlying First-order Logic. American Mathematical Soc. p. 72. ISBN 978-0-8218-6588-0.

[14] Gumm, H. P.; Zarrad, M. (2014). “Coalgebraic Simulations and Congruences”. Coalgebraic Methods in Computer Science.Lecture Notes in Computer Science 8446. p. 118. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-44124-4_7. ISBN 978-3-662-44123-7.

[15] Julius Richard Büchi (1989). Finite Automata, Their Algebras and Grammars: Towards a Theory of Formal Expressions.Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 35–37. ISBN 978-1-4613-8853-1.

[16] M. E. Müller (2012). Relational Knowledge Discovery. Cambridge University Press. p. 22. ISBN 978-0-521-19021-3.

[17] Peter J. Pahl; Rudolf Damrath (2001). Mathematical Foundations of Computational Engineering: A Handbook. SpringerScience & Business Media. p. 496. ISBN 978-3-540-67995-0.

[18] Smith, Douglas; Eggen, Maurice; St. Andre, Richard (2006),ATransition to AdvancedMathematics (6th ed.), Brooks/Cole,p. 160, ISBN 0-534-39900-2

[19] Nievergelt, Yves (2002), Foundations of Logic and Mathematics: Applications to Computer Science and Cryptography,Springer-Verlag, p. 158.

[20] Flaška, V.; Ježek, J.; Kepka, T.; Kortelainen, J. (2007). Transitive Closures of Binary Relations I (PDF). Prague: Schoolof Mathematics – Physics Charles University. p. 1. Lemma 1.1 (iv). This source refers to asymmetric relations as “strictlyantisymmetric”.

[21] Since neither 5 divides 3, nor 3 divides 5, nor 3=5.

[22] Yao, Y.Y.; Wong, S.K.M. (1995). “Generalization of rough sets using relationships between attribute values” (PDF).Proceedings of the 2nd Annual Joint Conference on Information Sciences: 30–33..

[23] Joseph G. Rosenstein, Linear orderings, Academic Press, 1982, ISBN 0-12-597680-1, p. 4

[24] Tarski, Alfred; Givant, Steven (1987). A formalization of set theory without variables. American Mathematical Society. p.3. ISBN 0-8218-1041-3.

2.10 References• M. Kilp, U. Knauer, A.V. Mikhalev, Monoids, Acts and Categories: with Applications to Wreath Products andGraphs, De Gruyter Expositions in Mathematics vol. 29, Walter de Gruyter, 2000, ISBN 3-11-015248-7.

• Gunther Schmidt, 2010. Relational Mathematics. Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-76268-7.

Page 16: Pseudo Order

Chapter 3

Indecomposability

For other uses, see Indecomposable.

In constructive mathematics, indecomposability or indivisibility (German: Unzerlegbarkeit, from the adjectiveunzerlegbar) is the principle that the continuum cannot be partitioned into two nonempty pieces. This principlewas established by Brouwer in 1928 using intuitionistic principles, and can also be proven using Church’s thesis.The analogous property in classical analysis is the fact that any continuous function from the continuum to {0,1} isconstant.It follows from the indecomposability principle that any property of real numbers that is decided (each real numbereither has or does not have that property) is in fact trivial (either all the real numbers have that property, or else noneof them do). Conversely, if a property of real numbers is not trivial, then the property is not decided for all realnumbers. This contradicts the law of the excluded middle, according to which every property of the real numbers isdecided; so, since there are many nontrivial properties, there are many nontrivial partitions of the continuum.In CZF, it is consistent to assume the universe of all sets is indecomposable—so that any class for which membershipis decided (every set is either a member of the class, or else not a member of the class) is either empty or the entireuniverse.

3.1 See also• Indecomposable continuum

3.2 References• Dalen, Dirk van (1997). “How Connected is the Intuitionistic Continuum?" (PDF). The Journal of SymbolicLogic 62 (4): 1147–1150.

• Kleene, Stephen Cole; Vesley, Richard Eugene (1965). The Foundations of Intuitionistic Mathematics. North-Holland. p. 155.

• Rathjen, Michael (2010). “Metamathematical Properties of Intuitionistic Set Theories with Choice Principles”(PDF). In Cooper; Löwe; Sorbi. New Computational Paradigms. New York: Springer. ISBN 9781441922632.

13

Page 17: Pseudo Order

Chapter 4

Partially ordered set

{x,y,z}

{y,z}{x,z}{x,y}

{y} {z}{x}

Ø

The Hasse diagram of the set of all subsets of a three-element set {x, y, z}, ordered by inclusion. Sets on the same horizontal leveldon't share a precedence relationship. Other pairs, such as {x} and {y,z}, do not either.

In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (or poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitiveconcept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together witha binary relation that indicates that, for certain pairs of elements in the set, one of the elements precedes the other.Such a relation is called a partial order to reflect the fact that not every pair of elements need be related: for somepairs, it may be that neither element precedes the other in the poset. Thus, partial orders generalize the more familiartotal orders, in which every pair is related. A finite poset can be visualized through its Hasse diagram, which depictsthe ordering relation.[1]

A familiar real-life example of a partially ordered set is a collection of people ordered by genealogical descendancy.Some pairs of people bear the descendant-ancestor relationship, but other pairs bear no such relationship.

14

Page 18: Pseudo Order

4.1. FORMAL DEFINITION 15

4.1 Formal definition

A (non-strict) partial order[2] is a binary relation "≤" over a set P which is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive,i.e., which satisfies for all a, b, and c in P:

• a ≤ a (reflexivity);

• if a ≤ b and b ≤ a then a = b (antisymmetry);

• if a ≤ b and b ≤ c then a ≤ c (transitivity).

In other words, a partial order is an antisymmetric preorder.A set with a partial order is called a partially ordered set (also called a poset). The term ordered set is sometimesalso used, as long as it is clear from the context that no other kind of order is meant. In particular, totally ordered setscan also be referred to as “ordered sets”, especially in areas where these structures are more common than posets.For a, b, elements of a partially ordered set P, if a ≤ b or b ≤ a, then a and b are comparable. Otherwise they areincomparable. In the figure on top-right, e.g. {x} and {x,y,z} are comparable, while {x} and {y} are not. A partialorder under which every pair of elements is comparable is called a total order or linear order; a totally orderedset is also called a chain (e.g., the natural numbers with their standard order). A subset of a poset in which no twodistinct elements are comparable is called an antichain (e.g. the set of singletons {{x}, {y}, {z}} in the top-rightfigure). An element a is said to be covered by another element b, written a<:b, if a is strictly less than b and no thirdelement c fits between them; formally: if both a≤b and a≠b are true, and a≤c≤b is false for each c with a≠c≠b. Amore concise definition will be given below using the strict order corresponding to "≤". For example, {x} is coveredby {x,z} in the top-right figure, but not by {x,y,z}.

4.2 Examples

Standard examples of posets arising in mathematics include:

• The real numbers ordered by the standard less-than-or-equal relation ≤ (a totally ordered set as well).

• The set of subsets of a given set (its power set) ordered by inclusion (see the figure on top-right). Similarly, theset of sequences ordered by subsequence, and the set of strings ordered by substring.

• The set of natural numbers equipped with the relation of divisibility.

• The vertex set of a directed acyclic graph ordered by reachability.

• The set of subspaces of a vector space ordered by inclusion.

• For a partially ordered set P, the sequence space containing all sequences of elements from P, where sequencea precedes sequence b if every item in a precedes the corresponding item in b. Formally, (an)n∈ℕ ≤ (bn) ∈ℕif and only if a ≤ b for all n in ℕ, i.e. a componentwise order.

• For a set X and a partially ordered set P, the function space containing all functions from X to P, where f ≤ gif and only if f(x) ≤ g(x) for all x in X.

• A fence, a partially ordered set defined by an alternating sequence of order relations a < b > c < d ...

4.3 Extrema

There are several notions of “greatest” and “least” element in a poset P, notably:

Page 19: Pseudo Order

16 CHAPTER 4. PARTIALLY ORDERED SET

• Greatest element and least element: An element g in P is a greatest element if for every element a in P, a ≤ g.An element m in P is a least element if for every element a in P, a ≥ m. A poset can only have one greatest orleast element.

• Maximal elements and minimal elements: An element g in P is a maximal element if there is no element a inP such that a > g. Similarly, an element m in P is a minimal element if there is no element a in P such that a <m. If a poset has a greatest element, it must be the unique maximal element, but otherwise there can be morethan one maximal element, and similarly for least elements and minimal elements.

• Upper and lower bounds: For a subset A of P, an element x in P is an upper bound of A if a ≤ x, for eachelement a in A. In particular, x need not be in A to be an upper bound of A. Similarly, an element x in P is alower bound of A if a ≥ x, for each element a in A. A greatest element of P is an upper bound of P itself, anda least element is a lower bound of P.

For example, consider the positive integers, ordered by divisibility: 1 is a least element, as it divides all other elements;on the other hand this poset does not have a greatest element (although if one would include 0 in the poset, whichis a multiple of any integer, that would be a greatest element; see figure). This partially ordered set does not evenhave any maximal elements, since any g divides for instance 2g, which is distinct from it, so g is not maximal. If thenumber 1 is excluded, while keeping divisibility as ordering on the elements greater than 1, then the resulting posetdoes not have a least element, but any prime number is a minimal element for it. In this poset, 60 is an upper bound(though not a least upper bound) of the subset {2,3,5,10}, which does not have any lower bound (since 1 is not in theposet); on the other hand 2 is a lower bound of the subset of powers of 2, which does not have any upper bound.

4.4 Orders on the Cartesian product of partially ordered sets

In order of increasing strength, i.e., decreasing sets of pairs, three of the possible partial orders on the Cartesianproduct of two partially ordered sets are (see figures):

• the lexicographical order: (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if a < c or (a = c and b ≤ d);

• the product order: (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if a ≤ c and b ≤ d;

• the reflexive closure of the direct product of the corresponding strict orders: (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if (a < c and b < d)or (a = c and b = d).

All three can similarly be defined for the Cartesian product of more than two sets.Applied to ordered vector spaces over the same field, the result is in each case also an ordered vector space.See also orders on the Cartesian product of totally ordered sets.

4.5 Sums of partially ordered sets

Another way to combine two posets is the ordinal sum[3] (or linear sum[4]), Z = X ⊕ Y, defined on the union of theunderlying sets X and Y by the order a ≤Z b if and only if:

• a, b ∈ X with a ≤X b, or

• a, b ∈ Y with a ≤Y b, or

• a ∈ X and b ∈ Y.

If two posets are well-ordered, then so is their ordinal sum.[5]

Page 20: Pseudo Order

4.6. STRICT AND NON-STRICT PARTIAL ORDERS 17

4.6 Strict and non-strict partial orders

In some contexts, the partial order defined above is called a non-strict (or reflexive, orweak) partial order. In thesecontexts, a strict (or irreflexive) partial order "<" is a binary relation that is irreflexive, transitive and asymmetric,i.e. which satisfies for all a, b, and c in P:

• not a < a (irreflexivity),

• if a < b and b < c then a < c (transitivity), and

• if a < b then not b < a (asymmetry; implied by irreflexivity and transitivity[6]).

There is a 1-to-1 correspondence between all non-strict and strict partial orders.If "≤" is a non-strict partial order, then the corresponding strict partial order "<" is the irreflexive kernel given by:

a < b if a ≤ b and a ≠ b

Conversely, if "<" is a strict partial order, then the corresponding non-strict partial order "≤" is the reflexive closuregiven by:

a ≤ b if a < b or a = b.

This is the reason for using the notation "≤".Using the strict order "<", the relation "a is covered by b" can be equivalently rephrased as "a<b, but not a<c<b forany c". Strict partial orders are useful because they correspond more directly to directed acyclic graphs (dags): everystrict partial order is a dag, and the transitive closure of a dag is both a strict partial order and also a dag itself.

4.7 Inverse and order dual

The inverse or converse ≥ of a partial order relation ≤ satisfies x≥y if and only if y≤x. The inverse of a partialorder relation is reflexive, transitive, and antisymmetric, and hence itself a partial order relation. The order dual of apartially ordered set is the same set with the partial order relation replaced by its inverse. The irreflexive relation > isto ≥ as < is to ≤.Any one of the four relations ≤, <, ≥, and > on a given set uniquely determines the other three.In general two elements x and y of a partial order may stand in any of four mutually exclusive relationships to eachother: either x < y, or x = y, or x > y, or x and y are incomparable (none of the other three). A totally ordered set is onethat rules out this fourth possibility: all pairs of elements are comparable and we then say that trichotomy holds. Thenatural numbers, the integers, the rationals, and the reals are all totally ordered by their algebraic (signed) magnitudewhereas the complex numbers are not. This is not to say that the complex numbers cannot be totally ordered; wecould for example order them lexicographically via x+iy < u+iv if and only if x < u or (x = u and y < v), but this is notordering by magnitude in any reasonable sense as it makes 1 greater than 100i. Ordering them by absolute magnitudeyields a preorder in which all pairs are comparable, but this is not a partial order since 1 and i have the same absolutemagnitude but are not equal, violating antisymmetry.

4.8 Mappings between partially ordered sets

Given two partially ordered sets (S,≤) and (T,≤), a function f: S → T is called order-preserving, or monotone,or isotone, if for all x and y in S, x≤y implies f(x) ≤ f(y). If (U,≤) is also a partially ordered set, and both f: S→ T and g: T → U are order-preserving, their composition (g∘f): S → U is order-preserving, too. A function f:S → T is called order-reflecting if for all x and y in S, f(x) ≤ f(y) implies x≤y. If f is both order-preserving andorder-reflecting, then it is called an order-embedding of (S,≤) into (T,≤). In the latter case, f is necessarily injective,since f(x) = f(y) implies x ≤ y and y ≤ x. If an order-embedding between two posets S and T exists, one says that Scan be embedded into T. If an order-embedding f: S → T is bijective, it is called an order isomorphism, and the

Page 21: Pseudo Order

18 CHAPTER 4. PARTIALLY ORDERED SET

partial orders (S,≤) and (T,≤) are said to be isomorphic. Isomorphic orders have structurally similar Hasse diagrams(cf. right picture). It can be shown that if order-preserving maps f: S → T and g: T → S exist such that g∘f and f∘gyields the identity function on S and T, respectively, then S and T are order-isomorphic. [7]

For example, a mapping f: ℕ → ℙ(ℕ) from the set of natural numbers (ordered by divisibility) to the power set ofnatural numbers (ordered by set inclusion) can be defined by taking each number to the set of its prime divisors. Itis order-preserving: if x divides y, then each prime divisor of x is also a prime divisor of y. However, it is neitherinjective (since it maps both 12 and 6 to {2,3}) nor order-reflecting (since besides 12 doesn't divide 6). Takinginstead each number to the set of its prime power divisors defines a map g: ℕ → ℙ(ℕ) that is order-preserving, order-reflecting, and hence an order-embedding. It is not an order-isomorphism (since it e.g. doesn't map any number tothe set {4}), but it can be made one by restricting its codomain to g(ℕ). The right picture shows a subset of ℕ and itsisomorphic image under g. The construction of such an order-isomorphism into a power set can be generalized to awide class of partial orders, called distributive lattices, see "Birkhoff’s representation theorem".

4.9 Number of partial orders

Partially ordered set of set of all subsets of a six-element set {a, b, c, d, e, f}, ordered by the subset relation.

Sequence A001035 in OEIS gives the number of partial orders on a set of n labeled elements:The number of strict partial orders is the same as that of partial orders.If we count only up to isomorphism, we get 1, 1, 2, 5, 16, 63, 318, … (sequence A000112 in OEIS).

4.10 Linear extension

A partial order ≤* on a set X is an extension of another partial order ≤ on X provided that for all elements x and yof X, whenever x ≤ y, it is also the case that x ≤* y. A linear extension is an extension that is also a linear (i.e., total)order. Every partial order can be extended to a total order (order-extension principle).[8]

In computer science, algorithms for finding linear extensions of partial orders (represented as the reachability ordersof directed acyclic graphs) are called topological sorting.

Page 22: Pseudo Order

4.11. IN CATEGORY THEORY 19

4.11 In category theory

Every poset (and every preorder) may be considered as a category in which every hom-set has at most one element.More explicitly, let hom(x, y) = {(x, y)} if x ≤ y (and otherwise the empty set) and (y, z)∘(x, y) = (x, z). Posets areequivalent to one another if and only if they are isomorphic. In a poset, the smallest element, if it exists, is an initialobject, and the largest element, if it exists, is a terminal object. Also, every preordered set is equivalent to a poset.Finally, every subcategory of a poset is isomorphism-closed.

4.12 Partial orders in topological spaces

Main article: Partially ordered space

If P is a partially ordered set that has also been given the structure of a topological space, then it is customary toassume that {(a, b) : a ≤ b} is a closed subset of the topological product space P ×P . Under this assumption partialorder relations are well behaved at limits in the sense that if ai → a , bi → b and ai ≤ bi for all i, then a ≤ b.[9]

4.13 Interval

For a ≤ b, the closed interval [a,b] is the set of elements x satisfying a ≤ x ≤ b (i.e. a ≤ x and x ≤ b). It contains atleast the elements a and b.Using the corresponding strict relation "<", the open interval (a,b) is the set of elements x satisfying a < x < b (i.e. a< x and x < b). An open interval may be empty even if a < b. For example, the open interval (1,2) on the integers isempty since there are no integers i such that 1 < i < 2.Sometimes the definitions are extended to allow a > b, in which case the interval is empty.The half-open intervals [a,b) and (a,b] are defined similarly.A poset is locally finite if every interval is finite. For example, the integers are locally finite under their natural order-ing. The lexicographical order on the cartesian product ℕ×ℕ is not locally finite, since e.g. (1,2)≤(1,3)≤(1,4)≤(1,5)≤...≤(2,1).Using the interval notation, the property "a is covered by b" can be rephrased equivalently as [a,b] = {a,b}.This concept of an interval in a partial order should not be confused with the particular class of partial orders knownas the interval orders.

4.14 See also

• antimatroid, a formalization of orderings on a set that allows more general families of orderings than posets

• causal set

• comparability graph

• complete partial order

• directed set

• graded poset

• incidence algebra

• lattice

• locally finite poset

• Möbius function on posets

• ordered group

Page 23: Pseudo Order

20 CHAPTER 4. PARTIALLY ORDERED SET

• poset topology, a kind of topological space that can be defined from any poset

• Scott continuity - continuity of a function between two partial orders.

• semilattice

• semiorder

• series-parallel partial order

• stochastic dominance

• strict weak ordering - strict partial order "<" in which the relation “neither a < b nor b < a" is transitive.

• Zorn’s lemma

4.15 Notes[1] Merrifield, Richard E.; Simmons, Howard E. (1989). Topological Methods in Chemistry. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

p. 28. ISBN 0-471-83817-9. Retrieved 27 July 2012. A partially ordered set is conveniently represented by a Hassediagram...

[2] Simovici, Dan A. & Djeraba, Chabane (2008). “Partially Ordered Sets”. Mathematical Tools for Data Mining: Set Theory,Partial Orders, Combinatorics. Springer. ISBN 9781848002012.

[3] Neggers, J.; Kim, Hee Sik (1998), “4.2 Product Order and Lexicographic Order”, Basic Posets, World Scientific, pp. 62–63,ISBN 9789810235895

[4] Davey & Priestley, Introduction to Lattices and Order (Second Edition), 2002, p. 17-18

[5] P. R. Halmos (1974). Naive Set Theory. Springer. p. 82. ISBN 978-1-4757-1645-0.

[6] Flaška, V.; Ježek, J.; Kepka, T.; Kortelainen, J. (2007). Transitive Closures of Binary Relations I (PDF). Prague: Schoolof Mathematics - Physics Charles University. p. 1. Lemma 1.1 (iv). Note that this source refers to asymmetric relationsas “strictly antisymmetric”.

[7] Davey, B. A.; Priestley, H. A. (2002). “Maps between ordered sets”. Introduction to Lattices and Order (2nd ed.). NewYork: Cambridge University Press. pp. 23–24. ISBN 0-521-78451-4. MR 1902334.

[8] Jech, Thomas (2008) [1973]. The Axiom of Choice. Dover Publications. ISBN 0-486-46624-8.

[9] Ward, L. E. Jr (1954). “Partially Ordered Topological Spaces”. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 5 (1):144–161. doi:10.1090/S0002-9939-1954-0063016-5

4.16 References• Deshpande, Jayant V. (1968). “On Continuity of a Partial Order”. Proceedings of the American MathematicalSociety 19 (2): 383–386. doi:10.1090/S0002-9939-1968-0236071-7.

• Schröder, Bernd S. W. (2003). Ordered Sets: An Introduction. Birkhäuser, Boston.

• Stanley, Richard P.. Enumerative Combinatorics 1. Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics 49. Cam-bridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-66351-2.

4.17 External links• A001035: Number of posets with n labeled elements in the OEIS

• A000112: Number of posets with n unlabeled elements in the OEIS

Page 24: Pseudo Order

Chapter 5

Pseudo-order

In constructive mathematics, a pseudo-order is a constructive generalisation of a linear order to the continuouscase. The usual trichotomy law does not hold in the constructive continuum because of its indecomposability, so thiscondition is weakened.A pseudo-order is a binary relation satisfying the following conditions:

1. It is not possible for two elements to each be less than the other. That is, ∀x, y : ¬ (x < y ∧ y < x) .2. For all x, y, and z, if x < y then either x < z or z < y. That is, ∀x, y, z : x < y → (x < z ∨ z < y) .3. Every two elements for which neither one is less than the other must be equal. That is, ∀x, y : ¬ (x < y ∨ y <

x) → x = y

This first condition is simply antisymmetry. It follows from the first two conditions that a pseudo-order is transitive.The second condition is often called co-transitivity or comparison and is the constructive substitute for trichotomy. Ingeneral, given two elements of a pseudo-ordered set, it is not always the case that either one is less than the other orelse they are equal, but given any nontrivial interval, any element is either above the lower bound, or below the upperbound.The third condition is often taken as the definition of equality. The natural apartness relation on a pseudo-ordered setis given by

x#y ↔ x < y ∨ y < x

and equality is defined by the negation of apartness.The negation of the pseudo-order is a partial order which is close to a total order: if x ≤ y is defined as the negationof y < x, then we have

¬ (¬ (x ≤ y) ∧ ¬ (y ≤ x)).

Using classical logic one would then conclude that x ≤ y or y ≤ x, so it would be a total order. However, this inferenceis not valid in the constructive case.The prototypical pseudo-order is that of the real numbers: one real number is less than another if there exists (onecan construct) a rational number greater than the former and less than the latter. In other words, x < y if there existsa rational number z such that x < z < y.

5.1 References• Arend Heyting (1966) Intuitionism: An introduction. Second revised edition North-Holland Publishing Co.,Amsterdam.

http://books.google.com/books/about/Intuitionism.html?id=4rhLAAAAMAAJ

21

Page 25: Pseudo Order

Chapter 6

Total order

In mathematics, a linear order, total order, simple order, or (non-strict) ordering is a binary relation on someset X, which is transitive, antisymmetric, and total (this relation is denoted here by infix ≤). A set paired with a totalorder is called a totally ordered set, a linearly ordered set, a simply ordered set, or a chain.If X is totally ordered under ≤, then the following statements hold for all a, b and c in X:

If a ≤ b and b ≤ a then a = b (antisymmetry);If a ≤ b and b ≤ c then a ≤ c (transitivity);a ≤ b or b ≤ a (totality).

Antisymmetry eliminates uncertain cases when both a precedes b and b precedes a.[1] A relation having the property of“totality” means that any pair of elements in the set of the relation are comparable under the relation. This also meansthat the set can be diagrammed as a line of elements, giving it the name linear.[2] Totality also implies reflexivity, i.e.,a ≤ a. Therefore, a total order is also a partial order. The partial order has a weaker form of the third condition. (Itrequires only reflexivity, not totality.) An extension of a given partial order to a total order is called a linear extensionof that partial order.

6.1 Strict total order

For each (non-strict) total order ≤ there is an associated asymmetric (hence irreflexive) relation <, called a strict totalorder, which can equivalently be defined in two ways:

• a < b if and only if a ≤ b and a ≠ b• a < b if and only if not b ≤ a (i.e., < is the inverse of the complement of ≤)

Properties:

• The relation is transitive: a < b and b < c implies a < c.• The relation is trichotomous: exactly one of a < b, b < a and a = b is true.• The relation is a strict weak order, where the associated equivalence is equality.

We can work the other way and start by choosing < as a transitive trichotomous binary relation; then a total order ≤can equivalently be defined in two ways:

• a ≤ b if and only if a < b or a = b• a ≤ b if and only if not b < a

Two more associated orders are the complements ≥ and >, completing the quadruple {<, >, ≤, ≥}.We can define or explain the way a set is totally ordered by any of these four relations; the notation implies whetherwe are talking about the non-strict or the strict total order.

22

Page 26: Pseudo Order

6.2. EXAMPLES 23

6.2 Examples

• The letters of the alphabet ordered by the standard dictionary order, e.g., A < B < C etc.

• Any subset of a totally ordered set, with the restriction of the order on the whole set.

• Any set of cardinal numbers or ordinal numbers (more strongly, these are well-orders).

• If X is any set and f an injective function from X to a totally ordered set then f induces a total ordering on Xby setting x1 < x2 if and only if f(x1) < f(x2).

• The lexicographical order on the Cartesian product of a set of totally ordered sets indexed by an ordinal, isitself a total order. For example, any set of words ordered alphabetically is a totally ordered set, viewed as asubset of a Cartesian product of a countable number of copies of a set formed by adding the space symbol tothe alphabet (and defining a space to be less than any letter).

• The set of real numbers ordered by the usual less than (<) or greater than (>) relations is totally ordered, hencealso the subsets of natural numbers, integers, and rational numbers. Each of these can be shown to be the unique(to within isomorphism) smallest example of a totally ordered set with a certain property, (a total order A isthe smallest with a certain property if whenever B has the property, there is an order isomorphism from A to asubset of B):

• The natural numbers comprise the smallest totally ordered set with no upper bound.• The integers comprise the smallest totally ordered set with neither an upper nor a lower bound.• The rational numbers comprise the smallest totally ordered set which is dense in the real numbers. Thedefinition of density used here says that for every 'a' and 'b' in the real numbers such that 'a' < 'b', there isa 'q' in the rational numbers such that 'a' < 'q' < 'b'.

• The real numbers comprise the smallest unbounded totally ordered set that is connected in the ordertopology (defined below).

• Ordered fields are totally ordered by definition. They include the rational numbers and the real numbers.

6.3 Further concepts

6.3.1 Chains

While chain is sometimes merely a synonym for totally ordered set, it can also refer to a totally ordered subset ofsome partially ordered set. The latter definition has a crucial role in Zorn’s lemma. The height of a poset denotes thecardinality of its largest chain in this sense.For example, consider the set of all subsets of the integers partially ordered by inclusion. Then the set { In : n is anatural number}, where In is the set of natural numbers below n, is a chain in this ordering, as it is totally orderedunder inclusion: If n≤k, then In is a subset of Ik.

6.3.2 Lattice theory

One may define a totally ordered set as a particular kind of lattice, namely one in which we have

{a ∨ b, a ∧ b} = {a, b} for all a, b.

We then write a ≤ b if and only if a = a ∧ b . Hence a totally ordered set is a distributive lattice.

Page 27: Pseudo Order

24 CHAPTER 6. TOTAL ORDER

6.3.3 Finite total orders

A simple counting argument will verify that any non-empty finite totally ordered set (and hence any non-empty subsetthereof) has a least element. Thus every finite total order is in fact a well order. Either by direct proof or by observingthat every well order is order isomorphic to an ordinal one may show that every finite total order is order isomorphicto an initial segment of the natural numbers ordered by <. In other words, a total order on a set with k elementsinduces a bijection with the first k natural numbers. Hence it is common to index finite total orders or well orderswith order type ω by natural numbers in a fashion which respects the ordering (either starting with zero or with one).

6.3.4 Category theory

Totally ordered sets form a full subcategory of the category of partially ordered sets, with the morphisms being mapswhich respect the orders, i.e. maps f such that if a ≤ b then f(a) ≤ f(b).A bijective map between two totally ordered sets that respects the two orders is an isomorphism in this category.

6.3.5 Order topology

For any totally ordered set X we can define the open intervals (a, b) = {x : a < x and x < b}, (−∞, b) = {x : x < b},(a, ∞) = {x : a < x} and (−∞, ∞) = X. We can use these open intervals to define a topology on any ordered set, theorder topology.When more than one order is being used on a set one talks about the order topology induced by a particular order.For instance if N is the natural numbers, < is less than and > greater than we might refer to the order topology onN induced by < and the order topology on N induced by > (in this case they happen to be identical but will not ingeneral).The order topology induced by a total order may be shown to be hereditarily normal.

6.3.6 Completeness

A totally ordered set is said to be complete if every nonempty subset that has an upper bound, has a least upperbound. For example, the set of real numbers R is complete but the set of rational numbers Q is not.There are a number of results relating properties of the order topology to the completeness of X:

• If the order topology on X is connected, X is complete.

• X is connected under the order topology if and only if it is complete and there is no gap in X (a gap is twopoints a and b in X with a < b such that no c satisfies a < c < b.)

• X is complete if and only if every bounded set that is closed in the order topology is compact.

A totally ordered set (with its order topology) which is a complete lattice is compact. Examples are the closed intervalsof real numbers, e.g. the unit interval [0,1], and the affinely extended real number system (extended real number line).There are order-preserving homeomorphisms between these examples.

6.3.7 Sums of orders

For any two disjoint total orders (A1,≤1) and (A2,≤2) , there is a natural order ≤+ on the set A1 ∪ A2 , which iscalled the sum of the two orders or sometimes just A1 +A2 :

For x, y ∈ A1 ∪A2 , x ≤+ y holds if and only if one of the following holds:

1. x, y ∈ A1 and x ≤1 y

2. x, y ∈ A2 and x ≤2 y

3. x ∈ A1 and y ∈ A2

Page 28: Pseudo Order

6.4. ORDERS ON THE CARTESIAN PRODUCT OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS 25

Intutitively, this means that the elements of the second set are added on top of the elements of the first set.More generally, if (I,≤) is a totally ordered index set, and for each i ∈ I the structure (Ai,≤i) is a linear order,where the sets Ai are pairwise disjoint, then the natural total order on

∪i Ai is defined by

For x, y ∈∪

i∈I Ai , x ≤ y holds if:

1. Either there is some i ∈ I with x ≤i y

2. or there are some i < j in I with x ∈ Ai , y ∈ Aj

6.4 Orders on the Cartesian product of totally ordered sets

In order of increasing strength, i.e., decreasing sets of pairs, three of the possible orders on the Cartesian product oftwo totally ordered sets are:

• Lexicographical order: (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if a < c or (a = c and b ≤ d). This is a total order.

• (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if a ≤ c and b ≤ d (the product order). This is a partial order.

• (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if (a < c and b < d) or (a = c and b = d) (the reflexive closure of the direct product ofthe corresponding strict total orders). This is also a partial order.

All three can similarly be defined for the Cartesian product of more than two sets.Applied to the vector space Rn, each of these make it an ordered vector space.See also examples of partially ordered sets.A real function of n real variables defined on a subset of Rn defines a strict weak order and a corresponding totalpreorder on that subset.

6.5 Related structures

A binary relation that is antisymmetric, transitive, and reflexive (but not necessarily total) is a partial order.A group with a compatible total order is a totally ordered group.There are only a few nontrivial structures that are (interdefinable as) reducts of a total order. Forgetting the orientationresults in a betweenness relation. Forgetting the location of the ends results in a cyclic order. Forgetting both dataresults in a separation relation.[3]

6.6 See also

• Order theory

• Well-order

• Suslin’s problem

• Countryman line

• Prefix order – a downward total partial order

6.7 Notes[1] Nederpelt, Rob (2004). “Chapter 20.2: Ordered Sets. Orderings”. Logical Reasoning: A First Course. Texts in Computing

3 (3rd, Revised ed.). King’s College Publications. p. 325. ISBN 0-9543006-7-X.

Page 29: Pseudo Order

26 CHAPTER 6. TOTAL ORDER

[2] Nederpelt, Rob (2004). “Chapter 20.3: Ordered Sets. Linear orderings”. Logical Reasoning: A First Course. Texts inComputing 3 (3rd, Revisied ed.). King’s College Publications. p. 330. ISBN 0-9543006-7-X.

[3] Macpherson, H. Dugald (2011), “A survey of homogeneous structures” (PDF),DiscreteMathematics, doi:10.1016/j.disc.2011.01.024,retrieved 28 April 2011

6.8 References• George Grätzer (1971). Lattice theory: first concepts and distributive lattices. W. H. Freeman and Co. ISBN0-7167-0442-0

• John G. Hocking and Gail S. Young (1961). Topology. Corrected reprint, Dover, 1988. ISBN 0-486-65676-4

Page 30: Pseudo Order

Chapter 7

Trichotomy (mathematics)

In mathematics, the law of trichotomy states that every real number is either positive, negative, or zero.[1] Moregenerally, trichotomy is the property of an order relation < on a set X that for any x and y, exactly one of thefollowing holds: x < y, x = y , or x > y .In mathematical notation, this is

∀x ∈ X ∀y ∈ X ((x < y ∧¬(y < x)∧¬(x = y) )∨ (¬(x < y)∧ y < x∧¬(x = y) )∨ (¬(x < y)∧¬(y < x)∧x = y )) .

Assuming that the ordering is irreflexive and transitive, this can be simplified to

∀x ∈ X ∀y ∈ X ((x < y) ∨ (y < x) ∨ (x = y)) .

In classical logic, this axiom of trichotomy holds for ordinary comparison between real numbers and therefore alsofor comparisons between integers and between rational numbers. The law does not hold in general in intuitionisticlogic.In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory and Bernays set theory, the law of trichotomy holds between the cardinal numbersof well-orderable sets even without the axiom of choice. If the axiom of choice holds, then trichotomy holds betweenarbitrary cardinal numbers (because they are all well-orderable in that case).[2]

More generally, a binary relation R on X is trichotomous if for all x and y in X exactly one of xRy, yRx or x=y holds.If such a relation is also transitive it is a strict total order; this is a special case of a strict weak order. For example, inthe case of three element set {a,b,c} the relation R given by aRb, aRc, bRc is a strict total order, while the relation Rgiven by the cyclic aRb, bRc, cRa is a non-transitive trichotomous relation.In the definition of an ordered integral domain or ordered field, the law of trichotomy is usually taken as morefoundational than the law of total order.A trichotomous relation cannot be reflexive, since xRx must be false. If a trichotomous relation is transitive, it istrivially antisymmetric and also asymmetric, since xRy and yRx cannot both hold.

7.1 See also• Dichotomy

• Law of noncontradiction

• Law of excluded middle

7.2 References[1] http://mathworld.wolfram.com/TrichotomyLaw.html

27

Page 31: Pseudo Order

28 CHAPTER 7. TRICHOTOMY (MATHEMATICS)

[2] Bernays, Paul (1991). Axiomatic Set Theory. Dover Publications. ISBN 0-486-66637-9.

Page 32: Pseudo Order

7.3. TEXT AND IMAGE SOURCES, CONTRIBUTORS, AND LICENSES 29

7.3 Text and image sources, contributors, and licenses

7.3.1 Text• Apartness relation Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Apartness_relation?oldid=626240334 Contributors: Zundark, Toby Bartels,

Greenrd, Rich Farmbrough, MarSch, Salix alba, Chris the speller, Cydebot, David Eppstein, U66230200227, Bovineboy2008, Classi-calecon, Trivialist, Tassedethe, Unzerlegbarkeit, Erik9bot, XxTimberlakexx, I dream of horses, TheHappiestCritic, WebTV3 and Anony-mous: 5

• Binary relation Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Binary_relation?oldid=684344533 Contributors: AxelBoldt, Bryan Derksen, Zun-dark, Tarquin, Jan Hidders, Roadrunner, Mjb, Tomo, Patrick, Xavic69, Michael Hardy, Wshun, Isomorphic, Dominus, Ixfd64, Takuya-Murata, Charles Matthews, Timwi, Dcoetzee, Jitse Niesen, Robbot, Chocolateboy, MathMartin, Tobias Bergemann, Giftlite, Fropuff,Dratman, Jorge Stolfi, Jlr~enwiki, Andycjp, Quarl, Guanabot, Yuval madar, Slipstream, Paul August, Elwikipedista~enwiki, Shanes,EmilJ, Randall Holmes, Ardric47, Obradovic Goran, Eje211, Alansohn, Dallashan~enwiki, Keenan Pepper, PAR, Adrian.benko, OlegAlexandrov, Joriki, Linas, MFH, Dpv, Pigcatian, Penumbra2000, Fresheneesz, Chobot, YurikBot, Hairy Dude, Koffieyahoo, Trova-tore, Bota47, Arthur Rubin, Netrapt, SmackBot, Royalguard11, SEIBasaurus, Cybercobra, Jon Awbrey, Turms, Lambiam, Dbtfz, MrStephen, Mets501, Dreftymac, Happy-melon, Petr Matas, CRGreathouse, CBM, Yrodro, WillowW, Xantharius, Thijs!bot, Egriffin,Rlupsa, JAnDbot, MER-C, Magioladitis, Vanish2, Avicennasis, David Eppstein, Robin S, Akurn, Adavidb, LajujKej, Owlgorithm, Djjrjr,Policron, DavidCBryant, Quux0r, VolkovBot, Boute, Vipinhari, Anonymous Dissident, PaulTanenbaum, Jackfork, Wykypydya, Dmcq,AlleborgoBot, AHMartin, Ocsenave, Sftd, Paradoctor, Henry Delforn (old), MiNombreDeGuerra, DuaneLAnderson, Anchor Link Bot,CBM2, Classicalecon, ClueBot, Snigbrook, Rhubbarb, Hans Adler, SilvonenBot, BYS2, Plmday, Addbot, LinkFA-Bot, Tide rolls, Jar-ble, Legobot, Luckas-bot, Yobot, Ht686rg90, Pcap, Labus, Nallimbot, Reindra, FredrikMeyer, AnomieBOT, Floquenbeam, Royote,Hahahaha4, Materialscientist, Belkovich, Citation bot, Racconish, Jellystones, Xqbot, Isheden, Geero, GhalyBot, Ernsts, Howard Mc-Cay, Constructive editor, Mark Renier, Mfwitten, RandomDSdevel, NearSetAccount, SpaceFlight89, Yunshui, Miracle Pen, Bramble-clawx, RjwilmsiBot, Nomen4Omen, Chharvey, SporkBot, OnePt618, Sameer143, Socialservice, ResearchRave, ClueBot NG,Wcherowi,Frietjes, Helpful Pixie Bot, Koertefa, ChrisGualtieri, YFdyh-bot, Dexbot, Makecat-bot, ScitDei, Lerutit, Jochen Burghardt, Jodosma,Karim132, Monkbot, Pratincola, , Some1Redirects4You, The Quixotic Potato and Anonymous: 102

• Indecomposability Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indecomposability?oldid=632854039 Contributors: Michael Hardy, Pmander-son, Bender235, MZMcBride, FlaBot, Aholtman, RussBot, CBM, Cydebot, Sam Staton, Reedy Bot, Daniel5Ko, JackSchmidt, Addbot,Unzerlegbarkeit and Anonymous: 4

• Partially ordered set Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Partially_ordered_set?oldid=683860112 Contributors: Bryan Derksen, Zun-dark, Tomo, Patrick, Bcrowell, Chinju, TakuyaMurata, GTBacchus, AugPi, Charles Matthews, Timwi, Dcoetzee, Dysprosia, Doradus,Maximus Rex, Fibonacci, Tobias Bergemann, Giftlite, Markus Krötzsch, Fropuff, Peruvianllama, Jason Quinn, Neilc, Gubbubu, De-fLog~enwiki, MarkSweep, Urhixidur, TheJames, Paul August, Zaslav, Spoon!, Porton, Haham hanuka, DougOrleans, Msh210, OlegAlexandrov, Daira Hopwood, MFH, Salix alba, FlaBot, Vonkje, Chobot, Laurentius, Dmharvey, Vecter, JosephSilverman, Sanguinity,Modify, RDBury, IncnisMrsi, Brick Thrower, Cesine, Zanetu, Jcarroll, Nbarth, Jdthood, Javalenok, Kjetil1001, Dreadstar, Esoth~enwiki,Mike Fikes, A. Pichler, Vaughan Pratt, CRGreathouse, L'œuf, CBM, Werratal, Rlupsa, CZeke, Ill logic, JAnDbot, MER-C, BrotherE,Tbleher, A3nm, David Eppstein, SlamDiego, Bissinger, Haseldon, Daniel5Ko, GaborLajos, NewEnglandYankee, Orphic, RobertDanielE-merson, TXiKiBoT, Digby Tantrum, PaulTanenbaum, Arcfrk, SieBot, Mochan Shrestha, TheGhostOfAdrianMineha, Thehotelambush,Megaloxantha, Peiresc~enwiki, Cheesefondue, Jludwig, ClueBot, Morinus, Justin W Smith, Methossant, Pi zero, Jonathanrcoxhead,Watchduck, ComputerGeezer, He7d3r, Hans Adler, Jtle515, Palnot, Marc van Leeuwen, Ankan babee, Addbot, Download, Luckyz,Legobot, Kilom691, AnomieBOT, Erel Segal, Citation bot, SteveWoolf, Undsoweiter, FrescoBot, Nicolas Perrault III, Confluente, Ri-cardo Ferreira de Oliveira, Throw it in the Fire, Gnathan87, Setitup, EmausBot, John of Reading, Febuiles, Thecheesykid, ZéroBot,Chharvey, The man who was Friday, SporkBot, Zfeinst, Rathgemz, CocuBot, Vdamanafshan, Mesoderm, MerlIwBot, Wbm1058, Jak-shap, Paolo Lipparini, ElphiBot, Larion Garaczi, Aabhis, Jochen Burghardt, Mark viking, Eamonford, Sgbmyr, K401sTL3, Tudor987,Victor Lesyk, Some1Redirects4You and Anonymous: 80

• Pseudo-order Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pseudo-order?oldid=537194190 Contributors: Toby Bartels, Cydebot, David Epp-stein, Unzerlegbarkeit, Yobot, DrilBot, EefeG0hi and Anonymous: 1

• Total order Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Total_order?oldid=687367088 Contributors: Damian Yerrick, AxelBoldt, Zundark,XJaM, Fritzlein, Patrick, Michael Hardy, Dori, AugPi, Dysprosia, Jitse Niesen, Greenrd, Zoicon5, Hyacinth, VeryVerily, Fibonacci,McKay, Aleph4, Gandalf61, MathMartin, Rursus, Tobias Bergemann, Giftlite, Mshonle~enwiki, Markus Krötzsch, Lethe, Waltpohl, De-fLog~enwiki, Alberto da Calvairate~enwiki, Quarl, Elroch, Paul August, Susvolans, Army1987, Func, Cmdrjameson, Tsirel, Msh210,Pion, Joriki, MattGiuca, Yurik, OneWeirdDude, Salix alba, VKokielov, Mathbot, Margosbot~enwiki, Wastingmytime, Chobot, YurikBot,Hede2000, Tetracube, Rdore, Melchoir, Gelingvistoj, Mhss, Chris the speller, Bazonka, Jdthood, Javalenok, Michael Kinyon, Loadmas-ter, Mets501, Iridescent, JRSpriggs, George100, CRGreathouse, CBM, Thomasmeeks, Oryanw~enwiki, VectorPosse, JAnDbot, A3nm,David Eppstein, Infovarius, Osquar F, PaulTanenbaum, SieBot, Ceroklis, Anchor Link Bot, Heinzi.at, WurmWoode, Universityuser,Palnot, Marc van Leeuwen, Addbot, Tanhabot, AsphyxiateDrake, Luckas-bot, Yobot, Charlatino, White gecko, 1exec1, Infvwl, Grou-choBot, Jsjunkie, Quondum, D.Lazard, SporkBot, Wcherowi, CocuBot, BG19bot, YumOooze, YFdyh-bot, Austinfeller, Mark viking,नितीश् चन्द्र and Anonymous: 51

• Trichotomy (mathematics) Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Trichotomy_(mathematics)?oldid=682670477Contributors: Zundark,Patrick, Michael Hardy, Arthur Frayn, Casu Marzu, Henrygb, UtherSRG, Tobias Bergemann, Macrakis, Paul August, Oleg Alexandrov,VKokielov, Michael Slone, Bota47, JJL, SmackBot, Mhss, Colonies Chris, Jdthood, Cybercobra, Courcelles, JRSpriggs, Meng.benjamin,Gregbard, Difluoroethene, David Cherney, AntiVandalBot, Indeed123, Minnnnng, YohanN7, Mild Bill Hiccup, MilesAgain, Addbot,Luckas-bot, AnomieBOT, Götz, Xqbot, Constructive editor, ComputScientist, Þjóðólfr, Tkuvho, SporkBot, Paulmiko, Helpful Pixie Bot,Zorglub x and Anonymous: 23

7.3.2 Images• File:Ambox_important.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/b/b4/Ambox_important.svg License: Public do-

main Contributors: Own work, based off of Image:Ambox scales.svg Original artist: Dsmurat (talk · contribs)

Page 33: Pseudo Order

30 CHAPTER 7. TRICHOTOMY (MATHEMATICS)

• File:Birkhoff120.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/7/7c/Birkhoff120.svg License: Public domain Contrib-utors: Own work Original artist: David Eppstein

• File:CardContin.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/7/75/CardContin.svg License: Public domain Contrib-utors: en:Image:CardContin.png Original artist: en:User:Trovatore, recreated by User:Stannered

• File:Commons-logo.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/en/4/4a/Commons-logo.svg License: ? Contributors: ? Origi-nal artist: ?

• File:Graph_of_non-injective,_non-surjective_function_(red)_and_of_bijective_function_(green).gif Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/b/b0/Graph_of_non-injective%2C_non-surjective_function_%28red%29_and_of_bijective_function_%28green%29.gif License: CC BY-SA 3.0 Contributors: Own work Original artist: Jochen Burghardt

• File:Hasse_diagram_of_powerset_of_3.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/e/ea/Hasse_diagram_of_powerset_of_3.svg License: CC-BY-SA-3.0 Contributors: self-made using graphviz's dot. Original artist: KSmrq

• File:Hasse_diagram_of_powerset_of_3_no_greatest_or_least.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/9/9e/Hasse_diagram_of_powerset_of_3_no_greatest_or_least.svg License: CC-BY-SA-3.0 Contributors: Based on File:Hasse diagram ofpowerset of 3.svg Original artist: User:Fibonacci, User:KSmrq

• File:Infinite_lattice_of_divisors.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/e/e6/Infinite_lattice_of_divisors.svgLicense: Public domain Contributors: w:de:Datei:Verband TeilerN.png Original artist: Watchduck (a.k.a. Tilman Piesk)

• File:Lexicographic_order_on_pairs_of_natural_numbers.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/8/8a/Lexicographic_order_on_pairs_of_natural_numbers.svg License: CC BY-SA 3.0 Contributors: Own work Original artist: Jochen Burghardt

• File:Monotonic_but_nonhomomorphic_map_between_lattices.gif Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/8/8c/Monotonic_but_nonhomomorphic_map_between_lattices.gif License: CC BY-SA 3.0 Contributors: Own work Original artist: JochenBurghardt

• File:N-Quadrat,_gedreht.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/1/13/N-Quadrat%2C_gedreht.svgLicense: CC0Contributors: Own work Original artist: Mini-floh

• File:Poset6.jpg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/en/1/12/Poset6.jpg License: PD Contributors: ? Original artist: ?• File:Question_book-new.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/en/9/99/Question_book-new.svg License: Cc-by-sa-3.0Contributors:Created from scratch in Adobe Illustrator. Based on Image:Question book.png created by User:Equazcion Original artist:Tkgd2007

• File:Strict_product_order_on_pairs_of_natural_numbers.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/8/88/Strict_product_order_on_pairs_of_natural_numbers.svg License: CC BY-SA 3.0 Contributors: Own work Original artist: Jochen Burghardt

• File:Wiki_letter_w_cropped.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/1/1c/Wiki_letter_w_cropped.svg License:CC-BY-SA-3.0 Contributors:

• Wiki_letter_w.svg Original artist: Wiki_letter_w.svg: Jarkko Piiroinen

7.3.3 Content license• Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 3.0