24
THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE Author(s): Jacques-Alain Miller and M. Downing Roberts Source: Qui Parle, Vol. 9, No. 2, Special Issue on Lacan (Spring/Summer 1996), pp. 160-182 Published by: University of Nebraska Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20686051 . Accessed: 26/04/2011 16:40 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=unp. . Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Nebraska Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Qui Parle. http://www.jstor.org

Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLEAuthor(s): Jacques-Alain Miller and M. Downing RobertsSource: Qui Parle, Vol. 9, No. 2, Special Issue on Lacan (Spring/Summer 1996), pp. 160-182Published by: University of Nebraska PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20686051 .Accessed: 26/04/2011 16:40

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unlessyou have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and youmay use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=unp. .

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

University of Nebraska Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Qui Parle.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE*

Jacques-Alain Miller

A small plan of the labyrinth. The will-to-say. Jouissance speaks.

Language, apparatus of jouissance.

Interpretation introduces the impossible.

Interpretation?

speech l'apparole

language lalangue the letter lituraterre

I provided you last time with this small table of orientation, com

posed of six terms,' matched pairs, and divided up into two sets of

three. It is an apparatus, a small assemblage. I can tell you where these six terms come from, for inasmuch

as you may not know this. I repeat it to myself. The first set, vertical, is made of three terms borrowed from

titles by Lacan from the first part of his teaching. You know the "Func

tion and Field of Speech and Language in Psychoanalysis." Take

* Seventh lesson of The Flight of Meaning (1995-96). The Lacanian orientation, teach

ing delivered at the Department of Psychoanalysis of Paris VIII. [French] text estab lished by Catherine Bonningue, and published with the agreeable authorization of J.-A.

Miller. [For details] one should consult the previous lesson published in Les feuillets du Courtil, as well as two other lessons to appear in Quarto and Letterina Archives.

Qui Parle vol. 9, No. 2, Spring/Summer 1996

Page 3: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 161

'speech' and 'language' out. You are also familiar with "The Agency Of The Letter." The first two are the key terms, the founders, of Lacan's

teaching, presented as a return to Freud, making these two terms

work over both the ouvre of Freud and the concept of analytic prac tice.

Some years later, under the heading of the "Agency of the Let

ter," you know that Lacan began a reorientation which resulted in

evacuating intersubjectivity of its references, inscribing these laws

of language that metaphor and metonymy would be alongside the

laws of speech. With these three terms we've got the essential coordinates which

condition both Lacan's teaching and much of what we've retained

of it. With regard to these three terms, I have written three others, more dubious, neologisms of sorts, which fiddle with our vocabu

lary. I adopted these terms from the final or penultimate Lacan, the

Lacan who reorients his teaching in the '70s, giving it a noticeably distinct turn, one all the more surprising if we refer it to his begin

nings.

They are: I'apparole- we are obliged to give an indication of

the way in which it is written, specifying it with "I" and an apostro

phe or with two "p"s in order to mark the difference, since it is pro nounced in the same way as the term under consideration -lalangue, all one word, and lituraterre, the only one of these three terms to

constitute by itself alone a title of one of Lacan's writings. I note these points of reference to indicate that the new turn

Lacan gave to his teaching in its last phase touches on fundamental

coordinates. This new turn imposes a new discipline, to which we

need to be broken in, especially if we are trying to establish the new

regime of analytic interpretation conditioned by it.

Here I could add "interpretation?" - with a question mark.

What happens to interpretation when we meddle with these

original basic coordinates? We must follow Lacan, who was the only one to advance in the direction he took.

We are about to catch something of his design, a design that is not without detours, contradictions, which make it rather difficult to

weave Ariadne's thread in this labyrinth. This is a small plan of the labyrinth still seen from afar.

Page 4: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

162 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

I

Let's try to weigh - as I started to do last time - the gymnas

tics that passing from one of the terms on the left to one of the terms

on the right imposes on us.

Let's begin -

why not? - with the term language. What is

language with respect to what traces itself as lalangue? - a term

whose possibilities I illustrated last time by a reference to Michel

Leiris.

Let's begin by saying, as we often do, some simple things. Lan

guage, as Lacan approaches it at the beginning of his teaching, is a

structure. What does that mean? An interdependent whole of differ

ential elements, with diacritic elements, relative to each other, so

that any variation in one element affects the others and brings about

attendant changes. That will do for the moment. It holds together, it's tight, rigor

ous. It evidently doesn't have as its object the plasticity of lalangue. We must say more. The way Lacan proposes it at the begin

ning of his teaching, structure is par excellence linguistic structure.

Lacan began by formulating that the unconscious was structured like a language

- which means at least three things.

Firstly, the unconscious is structure. It is not a matter of a con

stant, imperceptible flux, nor of a storehouse of heterogeneous things,

independent of each other, put together in a sort of sack. We discern

elements in it, and these elements make up a system.

Secondly, the unconscious is language. These discernible ele

ments are precisely those of language.

Thirdly, the unconscious is structured like a Saussurean lan

guage. We can distinguish within it signifier and signified. We are formed by, broken in by, accustomed to this object

language, which, when we approach it as structure, implies a sus

pension, and even a methodical foreclosure of the temporal, or

diachronic, factor. The perspective taken on object-language is es

sentially that of synchrony, which presupposes, when it is referred to

history, that we make a cut, a synchronic cut. We are dealing with a

state that Saussure called language [/a langue].

Page 5: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 163

This perspective is also essentially trans-individual -

synchronic and trans-individual. This definition of language implies that it have an Other, that it be correlative to another concept, the

concept of speech [/a parole] which, itself, is essentially diachronic

and individual.

This concept is Saussurian, but while Lacan essentially takes

his reference to la langue from the ceuvre of Saussure, he dresses up his reference to la parole, and even organizes it, orders it as Hegelian

speech -

fundamentally intersubjective, hence always dialogical, marked by the structure of dialogue

- even when Lacan superim

poses on his Hegel his own version of Austin's speech-act. As for the letter - I brought this up quickly last time - which

designates, at least in "The Agency of the Letter," the signifier in its

isolated structure, the letter introduces with respect to the function

of speech -that it thereby belittles -the function of writing, which

is completely at the center of this paper, "The Agency Of The Letter."

The structure in question conditions one phenomenon and only one - perhaps this is saying a lot - an essential, initial phenom enon and by virtue of that, determinative for whatever this phenom enon can attract like a magnet. This essential phenomenon is the

phenomenon of meaning [sens] that Lacan's "Agency of the Letter"

sends back to being in the position of an effect.

This triad - speech, language, the letter - has as a primary consequence that the essential phenomenon thus conditioned is put back into place as an effect. On this account, structure, as Lacan uses the term, is essentially the relation among signifiers, under the two forms of combination and substitution, meaning [sens] appear

ing as the effect of this or that combination, or of this or that substi

tution, as a restrained effect [effet retenu] in metonymy, a positive

emergent effect, in metaphor. Within these coordinates -which I mention briefly, but firmly,

in order to assure our grasp of them, before entering a more uncer

tain zone - interpretation doesn't pose a problem. Interpretation is

a matter of the signifier. The question is that of knowing which signi fier must be added, brought, injected, by the interlocutor-analyst.

Which meaning-effect this gives rise to - that remains to be seen.

Page 6: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

164 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

But the problematic of interpretation plays between this signifying addition and the specific modality of an anticipated meaning-effect which is variously described in Lacan's teaching.

Here is where we need to be a bit careful. Especially when it's

very simple, astutely perceived, appropriately placed, pleasantly ar

ranged and structured.

Structuring presumes discernment in placing the elements, set

ting some beside others, putting them into their proper relationships. Here, we must ask ourselves if it suffices, if it is persuasive enough,

despite all the support that we can find for it in Lacan's teaching on

this subject, only to place meaning at the end of the chain, in the

position of effect, the way we find it in "The Agency of the Letter."

There are signifiers here which are combined or are substituted, and

then - I'm simplifying - a certain effect of meaning, which either

finds itself held in check or else finds itself emerging.

f(S ... S')S ~ S(-) s

f S ~S(+) s

Is this enough? Does it account for what the triad at the begin ning implies?

Well, it is misleading to present things thus, to present mean

ing only as an effect, whereas, in necessity - a necessity that Lacan

doesn't misrecognize at all - meaning is initial as much as it is

terminal.

There are bound to be some people here who have thought about what Lacan calls his graph of desire. We cannot fail to notice

what is clearly acknowledged in the construction of this graph which

organizes the elements determined by the first triad. This graph is established as a schema of communication.

Page 7: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 165

However complex, refined, varied, it may be, the structure of

this graph is no more than a variation on intersubjective communi

cation, a variation on the structure of dialogue. This structure is still

driven, at its point of departure - because there is a point of depar

ture, and only one, fundamental point -

by what Lacan himself

calls the intention of signification. This machinery, this apparatus -

as Lacan himself will call it at the moment when he separates him

self off from it - won't function for even one second if this initial intention of signification is missing.

What does that mean? It means that the energy of the begin

ning, necessary for the functioning and the animation of this graph, is furnished by a wanting-to-say [vouloir-dire].2 From whatever angle

we take it, we cannot do without this wanting-to-say. And the phe

nomenology of the elementary analytic experience supports it.

It's not worth entering analytic experience if we don't want-to

say. We believe we want-to-say, and when we perceive, from within, that we don't want to say, that we express ourselves as wanting-not to-say, well, the analyst is there in order to point out that this want

ing-not-to-say is all the same a wanting-to-say. Try to convince yourself of this.

Meaning [vouloir dire] has a certain materiality - it is not a

fiction - even a certain self-evidence. This evidence circulates in

Lacan's teaching. The wanting-to-say takes us back to the subject, the complete subject, the barred subject, the split subject, the di vided subject. The subject wants to say [veut dire]. And the subject,

Page 8: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

166 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

complexified, multiplied, and canceled by Lacan, remains a will-to

say [volont6-de-dire]. Here I insist strongly. It is necessary to insist strongly in order to

transmit something in the mass of the commentaries, signifiers,

signifieds which cover all this up. I'm not treading lightly here. I'm

pacing off this ground laboriously. Later on, our steps will begin to

be more muddled, so I'll take advantage of this to lay out the ques tion.

Doubtless, Lacan's barred subject is not the will to recogni tion, as it is at the very beginning. As long as the essential point for

Lacan is the intersubjective relationship, the subject is will to recog nition by the Other, and desire for recognition. All of which Lacan

questions, and finally disproves. But the subject remains a will-to

say to the Other, the Other with a big "0" - a point that changes

nothing - or will-to-say for the Other, toward the Other, and even

from the Other - and even if this big 0 Other such as Lacan comes to define it is no longer, itself, defined as a subject. That doesn't

prevent the subject, who speaks, from being a will-to-say as a func tion of this Other.

The heart of the function of speech is given by what I am call

ing today the will-to-say. Speech always carries with it a strategy which envelops the Other, insofar as the partner of the subject, which is always there, is this big 0 Other. It is on this support (which puts in place both the subject and its wanting-to-say in speech, and the

Other, its partner), that, for example, demand and desire can be dis

tinguished. But speech, when we begin from these premises, is always an

affair of question and answer. The interpretation of the analyst al

ways appears in this configuration as a reply. Lacan can say rightly that this interpretative response, the interpretive response par excel

lence, is a question, it is the famous Che Vuoi? The "What do you want?" would be the minimal interpretation, what an interpretation

always means, even when it assumes other expressions. We can rightly say that the answer is a question, a question

about desire. The formula "What do you want?" is one of the formu las particularly suggested in this graph, a formula which would give

Page 9: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 167

the minimal text of the analytic interpretation as long as it were to

revolve around desire.

Here a principal, central path to the clinic suggests itself, which

consists of wondering about what the speech of the subject reduces

the other, its partner, to; or which figure of the Other the subject has

for its explicit, implicit partner in this dialogue. This is really a very

large part of analytic consideration, of the study that can be made of

clinical cases, even in the framework of case supervison, which passes

through these assessments. I am not there in order to say - it's not

working, it's all a put-on. I am there to indicate, on the contrary, how

it holds together, how it makes a system.

Speech, the speech of that first triad, is always taken in by such

a strategy of the Other, always decipherable as a strategy of meaning [sens].

Let's take some examples. Begin thinking from this starting point. What can we say about hysteric speech? Hysteric speech is the

speech of the analysand par excellence, insofar as it is that speech which makes itself enigmatic, which offers itself to the Other as some

thing to be interpreted, which needs an analyst as partner. It is really within the modern disaster and before the closing of all the recesses

where we could, all the same, find the analyst, the pre-analyst, the

proto-analyst, the para-analyst - as civilization had always offered

them down to modern times - it is in this great desert that it was

necessary to invent the analyst proper, in order to provide for this

task of interpretation offered by this speech. Hysteric speech brings to light a wanting-to-say distinct from the said; it underlines the gap between the saying and the said.

Let's go further in this direction. Hysteric speech is a speech

always dissatisfied with the said. In this speech, the subject feels in

the dissatisfaction, in the suffering, indeed in the guilt, the impossi bility of speaking the truth about the truth, of speaking the whole

truth. The subject feels this impossibility according to various mo dalities, ranging from the fatality of the lie to the pleasure of role playing. Moreover, it is not at all incompatible, on the one hand, to

be sometimes overjoyed with the role-playing, and then sometimes

to collapse under the fatality of the lie it bears with it. This speech is

Page 10: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

168 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

indeed the one which gives its place to the performer, and which

energizes and gives cause to this performer. What could we say about obsessional speech in comparison

with hysteric speech, starting from these coordinates? It is rather a

speech which dries up interpretation, which silences the performer, and which aims at a certain annulment of this subjective division, and therefore at an adequation of wanting-to-say to what is said. We

might say, in forcing the line, by caricaturing it, that it is a speech whose message is forever silent - there is nothing to be added to

this speech. In any case, the Other has nothing to add. Obsessional

speech is all the same a kind of gag on interpretation. To continue with the gallery of great categories: what could we

say about psychotic speech? Here, it is speech itself which takes

charge of interpretation, at least on the paranoiac side, and which

claims to be the mistress of meaning, to the point, in schizophrenia, of denouncing its social semblance down to its last entrenchments.

As for perverse speech -

perhaps we will make a separate

place for it later - let's say that it makes fun of meaning [sens]. When pure, perverse speech deploys itself, it doesn't allow a lot of room for analytic interpretation.

I'm drawing these little vignettes quickly in order to call to

mind the terrain that we can cover in the analytic experience; that is, the extent of the account that we can give of this terrain, by consid

ering structure-language and its essential phenomenon, meaning, even when this meaning is baptized as desire. The substance of our

analytic clinic moves around in these coordinates, of course with some variations, some internal oppositions. It is this substance which

is displaced when we move from language to lalangue.

II

Lalangue, as I began to illustrate, to touch on, last time, doesn't

appear to be a structure. If structure is what I said at the beginning, I can't manage to say, "Lalangue is a structure." Moreover, the word

that Lacan forges, in joining the article to the substantive, is rightly made in order to indicate that, there, the elements that we believe to

Page 11: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 169

be discernable in language, are not as discernable as we thought. And Leiris dumps loads of such examples on us. In any case, lalangue is very ambiguous. It is not without a relationship to the structure,

but we shrink from saying that lalangue is a structure. Especially because lalangue is not an object carved wholly out of synchrony. It

includes a dimension which is irreducibly diachronic, since it is es

sentially alluvial. It is made of alluvia accumulated out of misunder

standings, from linguistic creations, and by each of us.

Lacan took great care to indicate that the expressions that we

use have a precise origin, that we don't always manage to deter

mine. When we read the Dictionnaire des Prdcieuses,3 we notice

that a certain number of their most fabulous inventions became part of our most common means of expression. One day the Marquise Untel said "The word escapes me" [Le mot me manque]. We found

it charming, marvelous - "That's just like her!" We've repeated it, and today it is our way of speaking. This example that Lacan picks up has its value, discreetly, of messing up just a bit object-language in its synchrony. It is, after all, much funnier to take language with

contributions by the Marquise Untel and by the carter from Place

Maubert. It includes a diachronic dimension, and an "individual"

dimension, with "individual" in quotation marks. This concept that

Lacan forges thus reinserts each person's invention as a contribution to the community which inhabits Ialangue.

The essential phenomenon of what Lacan called lalangue is not meaning

- it is necessary to get used to this idea - it is

jouissance. In this displacement, this substitution, it is a whole pan orama which changes, not just a small modification that we make to

meaning, that we slip in here, while the rest doesn't budge. When we meddle with it, the whole edifice collapses, or in any case, tot

ters.

Let's say it another way: the principle of the second triad isn't

wanting-to-say, it is wanting-to-enjoy [ vouloir-jouir] . I've also rigged

up a little something here, I say to myself: "The Marquis Lacan said:

'L'apparole'" that's marvelous. And I adopt this term, 1 pass it on.

The second triad translates the new status of the first, when it is drive - to take up Count Freud's invention - and not signification that is

Page 12: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

170 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

conceived as the principle, the motor of the speaking being, to say it

in so many words. An entire conceptual system is transformed here.

From this displacement, we can see better what was at stake in

this machine of the graph of desire. This machine was - we assured

this by other means last year - an attempt by Lacan to structure

drive on the model of intersubjective communication. It was a stu

pendous attempt, which consisted in making drive a form of mes

sage, a request [une demande] without subject.4 It is a paradoxical message, but one which, all the same, makes drive into a kind of

message. The request is a kind of message, obviously, with an absent or eclipsed subject, or a subject which is no longer present except

through its bar or its lack, but it is still a request. In addition, this

drive is endowed in the graph with a vocabulary all its own, a vo

cabulary that Lacan writes in parallel with the treasure of lalangue. On one side, the treasure of /alangue, on the other, the treasure of

the drive. It is really to indicate that the drive is endowed with its own vocabulary. All the same, there is a message which finds its way from the other side and which is formulated in terms of drive, and

then over here a meaning-effect [effet de sens], extremely specific, but an effect of special, paradoxical, limited meaning.

We notice therefore, from the position that I invite you to take

up, that Lacan began with communication, and that he structured,

modeled, the drive on speech. In fact, he comments at length on

this, on speech and drive.

Page 13: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 171

To model the drive on speech was doubtless to make its place for drive as wanting-to-enjoy, but always under the domination of

wanting-to-say. This is done with extreme subtlety, and not without

foundation.

Here's where I undress the princess. We'll see that it depends on a simple, elementary principle. The princess is the graph. If we

were to take everything off, what will remain is the organization itself, the skeleton of the princess. And, for that matter, if we pulled a

little too hard, like in the story by Alphonse Allais ...

Here we grasp what is at stake when l'apparole appears in

place of the concept of /a parole. L'apparole is not something that

Lacan said often, once, twice at the most. No matter. We must re

elaborate the concept of speech when we come to the extremities

that I have just described.

Speech - calm speech

- always says both one and the other,

even if the other becomes the big 0 Other, it still presupposes ques tion and response. It is always a relation, a dialogue.

Now, l'apparole is a monologue. This theme of monologue haunts the Lacan of the '70s - the reminder that speech is above all

monologue. Here I'm proposing l'apparole as the concept which

responds to what comes to light in the Seminar Encore, when Lacan asks in a rhetorical way "Is Lalangue primarily of use in dialogue?" Nothing is less certain. I said that what responds to this remark, this

interrogation - which, advanced as minimally as that, is of a nature

to make the whole system collapse - is what makes a new concept

of speech necessary, insofar as lalangue is of no use in dialogue. With the concept of l'apparole, the body of reference to com

munication collapses; or at least, at the level where it is a question of

l'apparole, there is no dialogue, there is no communication, there is autism. There is no Other with a big "0." L'apparole isn't grounded in a principle of wanting-to-say to the Other, or starting from the

Other.

In Encore, Lacan touches on the term blablabla. This term is

not in Le Robert, at least not in the edition that I have, but it is listed in the Larousse Dictionary of Slang, which I recommend to you.

Blablabla - an expression really in current use - is glossed as empty

Page 14: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

172 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

prattle and being uninteresting. As for its origin, obviously we don't

know too much about it, it seems to be derived from joking [b/aguer] - a joke is by no means prattle that is without interest, it is what is

interesting in communication - or it might derive from "to blab" in

English, which means "to chatter" [Fr. jaser]. You would find this use

of it in Celine (as publishers aren't reissuing all of Celine's works,

given the significance of his blablabla which isn't always of the best

sort ... I don't have the volume in question, 1937). In any case, for

me blablabla is poured out by Le canard enchaind. I believe that

some years ago this magazine claimed paternity of this expression. We would have to make a scholarly inquiry into blablabla, into its

etymology. If someone is either in possession of this etymology or

would want to make such an inquiry, it would be most welcome.

We also say - this is noted by the Dictionary of Slang

- "blabla."

Moreover, Lacan willingly used the expression blabla - only two

times. It's more refined. With blablabla, there is certainly more than

bla bla bla, but we get the impression that the one who is speaking is

letting himself get all carried away by the subject matter and that he

is precisely, blablahing. Whereas blabla is the minimum.

I ask myself if we could liken blabla to l'apparole. Not exactly, even if Lacan calls to mind, in Encore, what is satisfied by blablabla.

Blabla is a degraded form of speech, but it is in the register of speech and not of l'apparole. It is finally empty speech, as Lacan baptized it,

speech where it is not the semantic content which prevails, which

carries the weight. This is why the dictionary says it is empty prattle. It is not the semantic marrow which counts, but the blabla - I don't

know what you think of it - continues to assure the essential func

tions of speech, to the point that we ask ourselves if we can make

the distinction. Blabla spreads its wings over everything that is speech. You are thinking rightly that I settle on this question when I lecture.

Blabla secures a communication function perfectly. It secures ex

ceedingly well what Jakobson calls the phatic function, the function of maintaining contact with the other. The emptier blabla is, the more

it demonstrates the orientation toward the Other and gets its claws

into the Other. The less information it contains, the more speech is

phatic.

Page 15: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 173

L'apparole doesn't have any phatic quality. This is why, just now, I even called it autistic, in a somewhat hasty use of the term.

L'apparole is what speech becomes when it is dominated by drive

and when it assures not communication but jouissance. Which an

swers to the formula that Lacan gives in Encore - "There, where It

speaks, It enjoys." [La o' ga parle, ga jouit]. That means, in context, It enjoys by speaking.

Thus, there is something to be situated which is satisfied with

this blabla, and which is satisfied on the level of the unconscious.

it enjoys

it speaks

In Encore, Lacan tried to advance a radical conjunction of the

'It speaks' and the 'It enjoys' [du ga parle et du ga jouit], that is to say, a conjunction of the Lacanian Other and the Freudian or Groddeckian It [ga].5 It is the conjunction of what, in the graph, is distinguished here; that is, how the structure of the ga parle imposes its structure

on the ga jouit. It's really the marriage of the earthen pot and the iron

pot. The earthen pot of the Other is shattered by the iron pot of the It.

Lacan is thus necessarily led to reexamine the axiom of the

unconscious structured like a language, which belongs to the first

triad. Therefore, it worries Lacan immensely to have said the uncon

scious is structured like a language. We have witness of this concern

in the fact that he periodically returns to this point. I said the uncon

scious is structured like a language. He simplifies the question

"Lalangue, l'apparole, there where It speaks It enjoys, that's exactly what I said in saying the unconscious is structured like a language."

Page 16: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

174 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

I cite him, in the chapter on "The other satisfaction," where he con

veys and demonstrates this perfectly novel conjunction. Let's provide the essential commentary

- three commentar

ies.

Firstly, when he says it and repeats it, it is not true. The uncon

scious structured like a language was formulated on the contrary, as

he says - I've often mentioned this formula of the "Function and

Field of Speech and Language," which really is a point of reference - in order to resolve techniques of decoding the unconscious and

the theory of the drives. It was done precisely to set drive, or instinct, aside and to isolate properly the phenomena of meaning [sens]. So, if he repeats this formula so often, in an affirmative manner, it is

precisely because it's not true.

Secondly, who can say to Lacan: That's not true? People who

don't like him. That's not the case with me. This is a reinterpretation of the initial formula, a creative auto-reinterpretation. Indeed, Lacan

- there we only see fireworks - with an extraordinary art, manages to demonstrate to you that it can just as easily mean what it didn't

mean in 1953. And it is worth the trouble of following the argument in detail, because it is fed precisely by designs which are especially

delicate and interesting. After all, it's easy to say, "I was wrong." All these questions are

not at the level of a mistake. It's easy to say "I am forgetting what I

said, I'm starting something else." It is, all the same, much more

difficult not to leave anything behind, to take it up again, to dress the

princess in new finery after having undressed her, and to show that

now, for example, she's a republican. That is what Lacan does, and, on the way, it's much more interesting.

Thirdly, when he says "that's what I'm saying," it suffices to

add a temporal marker "That's what I'm saying now, when I say the

unconscious is structured like a language." Lacan's interrogation goes to the point of putting in question

this "unconscious structured like a language," and, by these means, he recasts the work. We notice that it doesn't go back in exactly, that

sometimes you have to force it a bit. In any case, this interrogation

signals that the very foundations are in question.

Page 17: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 175

What he presents as the jouissance of speech, the Other satis

faction, the one which is supported by language - this jouissance

of speech is distinct from whatever the pure jouissance of the non

speaking body might be. But the very expression of the jouissance of speech could slip

by without our seeing the value of giving it expression. Some ortho

dox analysts - as they call themselves - were ready to put this

jouissance into the register of the oral drive. This is not the proper value that Lacan gives to this expression of the jouissance of speech.

We must give a radical value to this expression, i.e., that

jouissance speaks. Speech is animated by a wanting-to-enjoy. Not

only in the request [demande]. We could say that this appeal aims at

a need, a satisfaction, in truth a jouissance, and therefore this want

ing-to-enjoy is already present in the notion of demande, but a want

ing-to-enjoy which goes by way of and is dominated by a

wanting-to-say. In order to put the formula of the jouissance of speech into its

proper place, we must inscribe it in relation to the formula of "I, the

truth, I speak" [Moi, la vdritd, je parle]. That's a formula which be

longs to the context of the first triad of terms. In the first triad - the formations of the unconscious, the analysis by Freud of the first slip of the tongue

- this is what Lacan summarizes in saying "I, the

truth, I speak." The truth speaks, and it speaks "I."

When he evokes the jouissance of speech, it is the symmetri cal and opposite formula of the former. The unconscious structured

like a language implies that the truth speaks, whereas, in the context

of lalangue and of I'apparole, it is jouissance who speaks. Moreover, this formula leads to an inversion of the value of

empty and of full speech, as Lacan had introduced it at the begin

ning of his teaching. Empty speech is hollow speech, and full speech is speech full of meaning

- like Mary full of grace. Perhaps we can, in this context, find very perplexing what I

put on a line above: "interpretation" with a question mark.

When it is a question of the context of speech, when it is the truth that speaks, in the slip of the tongue, in the failed act, interpre tation has a ready-made place. The goal of interpretation is to make

Page 18: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

176 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

an effect of truth emerge, which no matter which way we modalise

it, contradicts the effect of prior meaning, of truth, which ensued

from what truth was saying in the patient's speech. But what can we

properly make of interpretation when it is a question of I'apparole? when it is jouissance who speaks? To interpret the truth, certainly. To

interpret jouissance!

III

Where do the two "p"s in I'apparole come from? They come - I indicated it last time - from the word "apparatus" [appareil]. Lacan already goes forward in this direction in Encore, when he

calls to mind the apparatuses of jouissance through which reality is

approached. Moreover, he essentially reduces this plural to language as the apparatus of jouissance, though obviously we would just as

easily consider the phantasm as an apparatus of jouissance. Nor

mally, we don't consider that reality is reached through the contriv ances of jouissance. We consider that reality is reached by the

apparatuses of perception, by the apparatuses of representation, by the apparatuses of consciousness. Here, it is in relation to It [ca] that

Lacan formulates that by means of the apparatus of jouissance real

ity is arrived at. It is apprehended by everything which is of use to

enjoyment. We could stop a moment with the word apparatus, instrument,

contraption. But there are other values to apparatus. The apparatus is a final finish [appret], something ready for use. Le Robert says it is

what is at hand [sous la main]. That evokes Heidegger's present-at hand, which is the utensil, what is in proximity.6 The apparatus is

what has been arranged, laid out, prepared in advance.

This word "apparatus" - it pleases me a lot - one face leans

toward appearance [le semblant] and one face leans toward utility. On one hand, the apparatus is the external display of finishes

or dressings; it is therefore related to everything that is beautiful ap pearance, allure, the impression produced by the totality of what is laid out there. Thus, there is always magnificence of pomp, of osten

tation in the apparatus.

Page 19: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 177

It gets more tricky when we call to mind a simple apparatus. For us, after Racine, the words of Nero describing the amorous pas sion for Junia which overcomes him still ring in our ears. These two

verses are like the condensation of the enunciation of a phantasm "Belle, sans ornement, dans le simple appareil/D'une beaute qu'on vient d'arracher au sommeil."7 'Apparatus' is never better evoked

than in this verse where all pomp and ostentation is abandoned. To

the contrary, it is the very apparatus of surprise and of nudity. Here's

one of the faces of apparatus. Here we really have the phantasm as

an apparatus of jouissance. On the other hand, there is its useful face, since an apparatus is

an assemblage, a fitting, an arrangement, which permits the accom

plishment of a function. This arrangement forms a totality; its ele

ments are combined in order to serve.

So, there is the side of appearance, with all its nuances, and

then there is the side that is utilitarian, functional.

An apparatus is whatever serves to do something, and is not

simple. It is not a tool. A certain complexity is necessary to form the

apparatus.

I am ready to give - I'm not hesitating

- all its value to this

notation of Lacan's, "Language: apparatus of jouissance." I would even be ready to construct the concept of apparatus as a concept

opposed to that of structure.

Language is a structure, but in defining language as "apparatus of jouissance," perhaps we are going towards replacing (at the suit

able level) the concept of structure with the concept of apparatus.

Apparatus is an assemblage, but an assemblage which can be more heterogeneous than structure, and above all which is power

fully finalized. A structure is deciphered, it is constructed, but it is

somewhat within the contemplative element. You have to add things like the action of the structure for it to start to function. Whereas

apparatus is connected straightaway to a finality, here to a finality of

jouissance, which outclasses the so-called finality of "knowledge of reality." Thus, I would like to consider that the concept of structure

belongs properly to the context defined by the first triad, and per

haps I would have its matching piece on the other side with appara tus.

Page 20: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

178 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

When Lacan uses the word I'apparole, he presents it as a mon

ster word, whose ambiguity he asks us to receive favorably. The ex

pression "monster word" cannot fail to recall that of Leiris, the one I

mentioned last time, about oral monsters which are born of lan

guage. Lacan uses "I'apparole" in a written work regarding the graph of desire - as if by chance - of which he says

- "L'apparole which

is made out of the Other is represented in the apparatus." The whole

question is to find out if I'apparole is really compatible with the

Other.

Thus, I was situating the place of interpretation in this new

context as a difficulty, where there is no place for dialogue, for

intersubjective communication, even modified by the introduction

of the big Other. The problem is the "no dialogue," pas-de-dialogue, the PDD.

On that point, there is an indication from Lacan - I'm giving it

you - which could do for today. Calling to mind the PDD, the pas

de-dialogue, and seeing quite well that an absolute position on the

pas-de-dialogue does interpretation in, Lacan points out "The pas

de-dialogue has its limit in interpretation, through which the real is

secured."

As I said, here we are following Lacan into a zone which is not

very clearly marked out and where the circuits cross. I racked my brains over this sentence, saying to myself that at a given moment, this sentence could be of use to me as a compass in this quite tricky zone, where we sometimes let ourselves be led with a bit of reti

cence once we notice that we are in the midst of absolutely taking down the entire house that we've constructed.

It is interesting to tackle things like that. First, it's practical. If

there's no dialogue, there's no interpretation. If we want to make room for interpretation, we have to push a bit on the pas-de-dia

logue. Don't take up all the room! Stated differently: we have to put a limit on some part of the pas-de-dialogue, to not be confined to

saying that it's over, since in any event something like interpretation is still going on.

There must be a limit to the autistic monologue of jouissance. And I find it very illuminating to say, "Analytic interpretation estab

Page 21: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 179

lishes the limit." Interpretation, on the contrary, has an infinite po

tentiality. We savor the infinity of interpretation; it's what feeds li

braries. As long as interpretation is interpretation of meaning, just one more signifier will suffice, it doesn't matter which one - we

could choose it with discernment - in order to re-interpret after

wards.

You can feel it in Lacan's commentary. Open the dictionary at

random, and take a word . . . whole numbers. The whole number

and psychoanalysis: on that point we could write whole volumes.

Or, you could follow current events, which allow for perpetual re

interpretation. In other words, when interpretation has to do with

meaning, far from establishing a limit, interpretation creates the un

limited. Here, we are taking things completely to the opposite slope. Not only does this line of argument position analytic interpretation as finite, but it says interpretation "finitizes." Analytic interpretation makes finite.

What I also like in the idea that analytic interpretation estab

lishes limits, is that it situates interpretation as an ending rather than as a renewal, that is to say, the opposite of what a practice of inter

pretation might be. There is also in this sentence the notion that it is not meaning that is secured by interpretation, as it would normally be in the context of the first triad. It is instead the Real that is secured

by interpretation. What can we do with this notion? In what is the Real secured

by interpretation? This notion leads us toward thinking that, in speech as PDD, as pas-de-dialogue, in the monologue of I'apparole, there is no Real, or in any case, on this level, the Real is not secured.

What can this really mean? What is Lacan aiming at with such

things as these? At this point, we are not entirely sure that Lacan is

addressing himself to us. We try to make believe, we try to make it seem as if he is addressing himself to us.

This monologue, if we start free associating - which we can

nonetheless do as a certain exercise of I'apparole, of saying anything whatever - the entire thesis of Lacan, in Encore for example, shows

that saying anything always leads to the pleasure principle, to the

Lustprinzip. That is to say: "There, where It speaks, It enjoys." [L A ou

Page 22: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

180 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

ga parle ga jouit.] It is the commentary of the It [gal. Especially be

cause we put prohibitions, inhibitions, prejudices, etc., in parenthe ses once It really begins to run at this level, there is a satisfaction of

speech. That means everything is going swimmingly. Which is why, when Lacan introduces the notion of the

jouissance of speech, he reflects on "saying," "everything works," etc. It's the same point of view as the one he sets forth in his Televi

sion when he says "The subject is happy." Whatever his misfortunes

may be, at the level of the unconscious he is always happy, that is to

say, drive always functions suitably, unlike desire.

What does this mean? - other than that, at this level, there is

no Impossible. At the level of drive, at the level where the subject is

happy, at the level where, there where It speaks, It enjoys, every

thing is dandy, everything succeeds. In this regime, we can't be as

sured any of Real-as-Impossible. At this level, there is reality as

apprehended by the apparatuses of jouissance, that is to say,

phantasmatic reality. There is phantasmatic "meaning" [signification], there is even an anything-goes interpretation of l'apparole, but no

Real is assured. At the level where the subject is happy, the Real is not secured.

This indicates what the place of analytic interpretation could

be, since it would intervene on the opposite slope of the pleasure principle. We would need to formulate, along the lines of what Lacan

suggests -

only suggests! he would have had the apparatus of the

thing, but we have to reconstitute it - that analytic interpretation introduces the impossible.

In this driven, fatal success - even in the midst of misfortune, it works, the subject is happy

- at the level determined here, ana

lytic interpretation underscores the failure present in the success of

l'apparole. Lacan indicates this failure in Encore: that all this happi ness doesn't allow us to assure the Real of the sexual relationship. I

won't develop this idea, I'm only indicating its place in this context.

There are consequences if we take things from this angle. If

analytic interpretation is that through which the Real is secured, then it is of the order of formalization, if we acknowledge that only math ematical formalization reaches a Real. This is what Lacan explores.

Page 23: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

THE MONOLOGUE OF L'APPAROLE 181

This exploration implies that, like formalization, analytic inter

pretation makes itself into the opposite of meaning. Lacan even evokes

what we could call mis-interpretation, non-sense [contre-sens].

Moreover, ambiguity is precisely taking things the other way. If one wished - let's hope

- to give analytic interpretation a

place back in the second triad, it would have to have the value of

formalizing l'apparole. This means that analytic interpretation, as

formalization, accepts, assumes, supports, a certain "It doesn't mean

anything."

Interpretation is a somewhat special mode. All interpretation consists in formulating "It means something else," while here, the

reduction to the "It means nothing" [ga ne veut rien dire] is the hori

zon.8 We could even say that, in analytic interpretation, the extrac

tion of "It wants to enjoy" [ga veutjouir] passes through an "It doesn't

mean anything" [ga ne veut rien dire], and that the unconscious, to

the contrary - this is why we can misrecognize it in this status -

masks this "It wants to enjoy" by the "It wants to say." And therefore, in order to recover the "It wants to enjoy", we must go through the

"It wants to say nothing." That implies still something else, which is not untimely, if it

can be constructed. Following the example of formalization, inter

pretation in the second triad is rather on the side of writing than of

speech. In any case, it must be constructed by vying with the written

work, insofar as formalization presupposes the written work. I am about at the end today. I will continue next week.

31 January 1996

Translated by M. Downing Roberts

[Translator's Note: I would like to thank Juliet Flower MacCannell for her very gener ous and invaluable help with the translation of this paper.]

1 [TN. The neologisms ?'apparole, ?a?angue, and lituraterre are left untranslated

throughout this essay, following the convention used by Jacqueline Rose in her

translation of Lacan's Seminar XX: Encore. For more details about the term

?a?angue, see Rose's discussion in Feminine Sexuality, (New York: W. W. Norton

Page 24: Miller, The Monologue of l'Apparole

182 JACQUES-ALAIN MILLER

& Company, 1985), 46n11. For Lacan's use of the term in Encore, see Le S?minaire

XX: Encore (Paris: ?ditions du Seuil, 1975), 126.] 2 [TN. Here Miller hypenates vouloir-dire, and so I have chosen the somewhat

literal phrase "wanting-to-say" as an English rendering of vouloir-dire, which is

the usual French way of saying "to mean" e.g, "I mean the red one," would be:

Je veux dire le rouge. This choice also brings out the way in which Miller will

juxtapose vouloir-dire with volont?-de-dire and later, vouloir-jouir. Obviously, Miller's use of vouloir-dire also carries the resonance of "meaning" and "to mean," but he often uses the word sens to convey "meaning" in a literal way; while the

"vouloir" o? "vouloir-dire" retains an element of desire, or wanting-to-say.] 3 [TN. See: Somaize, Le Dictionnaire des Pr?cieuses, (Paris: P. Jannet, 1856). See

also Jacques Lacan, Seminar I, Freud's Papers on Technique 1953-1954 (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1991), 286n.]

4 [TN. "request" is used here to render the Lacanian term of art demande, because

the point at issue revolves around a mapping of drive into the coordinate system of intersubjective communication.]

5 [TN. See Jacques Lacan, Le S?minaire XX: Encore (Paris: ?ditions du Seuil, 1975),

95-105.] 6 [TN. Although Miller says l'?tant-sous-la-main, the terms Heidegger uses in Be

ing and Time are vorhanden, or Vorhandenheit, which are rendered in the

Macquarrie-Robinson translation as "present-at-hand" and "presence-at-hand."] 7 [TN. From Racine's ritan ?cus (1670):

Act II, Scene II:

[...]

Narcisse: vous l'aimez?

N?ron: excit? d'un d?sir curieux, Cette nuit je l'ai vue arriver en ces lieux, Triste, levant au ciel ses yeux mouill?s de larmes,

Qui bri Noient au travers des flambeaux et des armes:

Belle, sans ornements, dans le simple appareil D'une beaut? qu'on vient d'arracher au sommeil.

Que veux-tu? Je ne sais si cette n?gligence, Les ombres, les flambeaux, les cris et le silence, Et le farouche aspect de ses fiers ravisseurs

Relevoient de ses yeux les timides douceurs.

(Racine, Oeuvres compl?tes (Paris: Pl?iade, 1950), 405.] 8 [TN. See note 2, above. ?a ne veut rien dire is the usual way of saying, "That

means nothing," or "That's nonsense."]