27
Maharam Algebras Boban Veliˇ ckovi´ c Equipe de Logique, Universit´ e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France Abstract Maharam algebras are complete Boolean algebras carrying a positive continuous submeasure. They were introduced and studied by Maharam in [24] in relation to Von Neumann’s problem on the characterization of measure algebras. The question whether every Maharam algebra is a measure algebra has been the main open prob- lem in this area for around 60 years. It was finally resolved by Talagrand [31] who provided the first example of a Maharam algebra which is not a measure algebra. In this paper we survey some recent work on Maharam algebras in relation to the two conditions proposed by Von Neumann: weak distributivity and the countable chain condition. It turns out that by strengthening either one of these conditions one obtains a ZFC characterization of Maharam algebras. We also present some results on Maharam algebras as forcing notions showing that they share some of the well known properties of measure algebras. Key words: measure algebra, Maharam algebra, ccc, weakly distributive, P-ideal dichotomy 1991 MSC: Primary 03Exx, Secondary 28Axx 1 Introduction We say that a complete Boolean B algebra is a measure algebra if it admits a strictly positive σ-additive probability measure. It is easy to see that every measure algebra B satisfies the following. 1. B has the countable chain condition (ccc), i.e. if A⊆B is such that a b = 0, for every a, b ∈A such that a = b, then A is at most countable. 2. B is weakly distributive, i.e. if {b n,k } n,k is a double sequence of elements of B then the following weak distributivity law holds: Email address: [email protected] (Boban Veliˇ ckovi´ c). Preprint submitted to Elsevier 22 April 2008

Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

  • Upload
    hathien

  • View
    228

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Maharam Algebras

Boban Velickovic

Equipe de Logique, Universite de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Abstract

Maharam algebras are complete Boolean algebras carrying a positive continuoussubmeasure. They were introduced and studied by Maharam in [24] in relation toVon Neumann’s problem on the characterization of measure algebras. The questionwhether every Maharam algebra is a measure algebra has been the main open prob-lem in this area for around 60 years. It was finally resolved by Talagrand [31] whoprovided the first example of a Maharam algebra which is not a measure algebra.In this paper we survey some recent work on Maharam algebras in relation to thetwo conditions proposed by Von Neumann: weak distributivity and the countablechain condition. It turns out that by strengthening either one of these conditionsone obtains a ZFC characterization of Maharam algebras. We also present someresults on Maharam algebras as forcing notions showing that they share some ofthe well known properties of measure algebras.

Key words: measure algebra, Maharam algebra, ccc, weakly distributive, P-idealdichotomy1991 MSC: Primary 03Exx, Secondary 28Axx

1 Introduction

We say that a complete Boolean B algebra is a measure algebra if it admitsa strictly positive σ-additive probability measure. It is easy to see that everymeasure algebra B satisfies the following.

1. B has the countable chain condition (ccc), i.e. if A ⊆ B is such that a∧b = 0,for every a, b ∈ A such that a 6= b, then A is at most countable.

2. B is weakly distributive, i.e. if {bn,k}n,k is a double sequence of elements ofB then the following weak distributivity law holds:

Email address: [email protected] (Boban Velickovic).

Preprint submitted to Elsevier 22 April 2008

Page 2: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

∧n

∨k

bn,k =∨

f :N→N

∧n

∨i<f(n)

bn,i

In 1937 Von Neumann asked if these two conditions are sufficient to char-acterize measure algebras (see [25]). A more general version of this questionis to find an algebraic characterization of measure algebras. In her work onVon Neumann’s problem Maharam [24] formulated the notion of a continuoussubmeasure and found an algebraic characterization for a complete Booleanalgebra to carry one. Recall that a submeasure on Boolean algebra B is afunction ν : B → [0, 1] such that

(1) ν(0) = 0(2) If x ≤ y then ν(x) ≤ ν(y)(3) ν(x ∨ y) ≤ ν(x) + ν(y)

We say that ν is positive if ν(a) > 0, for every a ∈ B \ {0}. If B is completethe role of σ-additivity is played by the following continuity condition.

(4) ν(xn) → ν(infn xn), whenever {xn}n is a decreasing sequence.

A submeasure ν satisfying (4) is called continuous. If a complete Booleanalgebra B carries a positive continuous submeasure then we call it a Ma-haram algebra. Maharam [24] showed that every Maharam algebra is weaklydistributive and satisfies the ccc. Therefore Von Neumann’s original questiondecomposes into two questions.

Question 1 Is every Maharam algebra a measure algebra?

Question 2 Is every ccc weakly distributive complete Boolean algebra a Ma-haram algebra?

Over the years a significant amount of work has been done on Question 1,which was known to be equivalent to the famous Control Measure Problem,i.e. the question whether every countably additive vector valued measure µdefined on a σ-algebra of sets and taking values in an F -space, i.e. a completelymetrizable topological vector space, admits a control measure, i.e. a countableadditive scalar measure λ having the same null sets as µ. For instance, Kaltonand Roberts [21] showed that a submeasure µ defined on a (not necessarilycomplete) Boolean algebra B is equivalent to a measure if and only if it isuniformly exhaustive. Recall that a submeasure µ on a Boolean algebra B iscalled exhaustive if for every sequence {an}n of disjoint elements of B we havelimn µ(an) = 0. µ is uniformly exhaustive if for every ε > 0 there is an integern such that there is no sequence of n disjoint elements of B of µ-submeasure≥ ε. Clearly, every continuous submeasure on a complete Boolean algebra isexhaustive. If µ is a positive submeasure on a Boolean algebra B one can define

2

Page 3: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

a metric d on B by setting d(a, b) = µ(a∆b). If µ is exhaustive then the metriccompletion B of B equipped with the natural boolean algebraic structure isa complete Boolean algebra and µ has a unique extension µ to a continuoussubmeasure on B. Thus B is a Maharam algebra. It follows that Question 1 isequivalent to the question whether every exhaustive submeasure on a Booleanalgebra B is uniformly exhaustive. Significant advances towards the solutionof Question 1 were made by Roberts [28] and Farah [7]. Finally, in the Fallof 2005 by using some of their ideas Talagrand [31] produced a remarkableexample of an exhaustive submeasure which is not uniformly exhaustive. Asa consequence he obtained the following.

Theorem 1.1 [31] There is a Maharam algebra which is not a measure alge-bra.

Concerning Question 2 already Maharam [24] observed that a Souslin treeprovides a counterexample. It is well known that Souslin trees may or maynot exist depending on additional axioms of set theory (see for instance [22]).Various other examples relatively consistent MA + ¬CH were provided byGlowczynski [15], the author [34] and others.

In the positive direction, in late 2003 it was shown by Balcar, Jech and Pazak[3] and the author [36] that a positive answer to Question 2 is relatively consis-tent with ZFC assuming the consistency of a supercompact cardinal. This wasachieved by deriving it from the P -ideal dichotomy, a combinatorial statementwhich was introduced by Abraham and Todorcevic [1] and later generalizedby Todorcevic [32]. These results build heavily on the work of Quickert [27]and [26] who defined a natural P -ideal associated to a ccc weakly distributivecomplete Boolean algebra and noticed that the P -ideal dichotomy may beuseful in this context. In particular, Quickert showed that under the P -idealdichotomy there is no nonatomic ccc forcing notion with the Sacks propertyand that every ccc weakly distributive complete Boolean algebra satisfies theσ-finite chain condition. In fact, by slightly strengthening the countable chaincondition one can obtain a ZFC characterization of Maharam algebras. Saythat a complete Boolean algebra B is indestructibly ccc if it remains ccc in anygeneric extension of the universe of set theory. By using the fact that any in-stance of the P -ideal dichotomy can by forced by a σ-distributive forcing andsuch forcing preserves weak distributivity it follows that every indestructiblyccc weakly distributive complete Boolean algebra is a Maharam algebra. Aparticular instance of this result for σ-finite chain condition Boolean algebraswas derived by Todorcevic [33]. It should also be mentioned that a version ofthis result for Souslin posets was obtained by Farah and Zapletal [10] fromSolecki’s result [30] about analytic P -ideals. Finally, we mention that it wasshown by Farah and the author [8] that some large cardinal assumptions arenecessary for the consistency of the positive answer to Question 2.

3

Page 4: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Concerning weak distributivity there is a natural two player infinite gameG(B) on a complete Boolean algebra B such that B is weakly distributive ifand only if Player I does not have a winning strategy in G(B). If in additionPlayer II has a winning strategy in this game we call B strategically weaklydistributive. Games of this type were introduced by Gray [16] and studied byJech [19], Dobrinen [6] and others. We will show in this paper that a completeBoolean algebra B is a Maharam algebra if and only if it is ccc and strategicallyweakly distributive. A related but apparently different result was obtained byFremlin [12, Theorem 8F] who considered a slightly different game which ismore difficult for Player II.

In light of Talagrand’s solution of Maharam’s problem it is natural to ask ifsome known properties of measure algebras are shared by all Maharam alge-bras. In this direction, it was shown by the author in [36] that every nonatomicMaharam algebra adds a splitting real and by Farah and the author in [9] thatthe product of two nonatomic Maharam algebras adds a Cohen real. Both ofthese properties are well known for measure algebras. The problem remains tofind a combinatorial property of measure algebras which distinguishes themamong all Maharam algebras. At the moment it is not even known if theMaharam algebra constructed by Talagrand contains a nonatomic completesubalgebra which is a measure algebra. If the answer to this is negative thiswould give a counterexample to a well known problem of Prikry who askedif it is relatively consistent that every ccc forcing adds a Cohen or a randomreal. For more information about this problem the reader is referred to [35].

The purpose of this paper is to survey some of the main results related tothe characterization of Maharam algebras and their combinatorial properties.It reflects the author’s personal taste and preferences and is not meant to beexhaustive. A more detailed account of Maharam algebras can be found inFremlin survey paper [12]. The paper is organized as follows. In §2 we surveysome counterexamples to Question 2 under various additional set theoreticassumptions. We present the examples of Glowczynski [15], the author [34]and Farah and the author [8]. In §3 we develop some facts about the sequen-tial topology and present several characterizations of Maharam algebras. Weprove a result of Balcar, Jech and Pazak [3] and the author [36] stating thatunder the P -ideal dichotomy every ccc weakly distributive complete Booleanalgebra is a Maharam algebra and then discuss some corollaries of the proof.We present a result of Balcar, Glowczynski and Jech [2] saying that a ccc com-plete Boolean algebra B is a Maharam algebra iff the sequential topology τs onB is Hausdorff. We then use this to give another characterization of Maharamalgebras: a complete Boolean algebra is a Maharam algebra iff it is ccc andstrategically weakly distributive. In §4 we discuss properties of Maharam alge-bras as forcing notions. We present a result of the author from [36] saying thatevery nonatomic Maharam algebra adds a splitting real and a result of Farahand the author [9] saying that the product of any two nonatomic Maharam

4

Page 5: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

algebras adds a Cohen real. Finally, in §5 we discuss some open problems anddirections for future research.

Our notation is mostly standard and can be found in [22] for terms relatingto set theory and in [11] for notions from measure theory.

2 Examples

We start by presenting some examples of ccc weakly distributive completeBoolean algebras obtained under additional set-theoretic assumptions whichare not Maharam algebras.

Example 1 A Souslin tree is an ω1 tree with no uncountable chains or an-tichains. It is well known that Souslin trees may or may not exist. For instance,the combinatorial principle ♦ which holds in the constructible universe L im-plies that there is a Souslin tree. On the other hand, MA + ¬ CH implies thatthere are no Souslin trees (see [22]). The regular open algebra of a Souslin treeis a ccc weakly distributive complete Boolean algebra which is not a Maharamalgebra (see [24]).

Example 2 Sacks forcing S consists of all perfect subtrees of 2<ω orderedunder inclusion. A key property of this forcing is called the Sacks property.

Definition 2.1 A forcing notion P has the Sacks property iff for every P-name τ for an element of ωω and for every condition p ∈ P there is a conditionq ≤ p and a sequence 〈In : n < ω〉 such that In ∈ [ω]2

n, for all n, and

q τ ∈ ΠnIn.

Clearly the Sacks property implies weak distributivity. The forcing notion Sitself is not ccc, but it is possible, under suitable assumptions, to extract accc suborder of S which still has the Sacks property. This was first done byJensen [20] who constructed a ccc suborder of S in order to ’construct’ anonconstructible Π1

2-singleton. He used ♦ and a fusion argument. This con-struction was later extended by the author [34]. For a partial ordering P letCCC(P) denote the following statement.

For every family D of 2ℵ0 dense open subsets of P there is a ccc perfectsuborder Q of P such that D ∩Q is dense in Q, for every D ∈ D.

Here perfect suborder means that the incompatibility relation of Q is the re-striction of the incompatibility relation of P . In [34] the following was shown.

Theorem 2.2 [34] Suppose κ > ℵ1 is regular and κ<κ = κ. Then there is ageneric extension in which Martin’s Axiom holds, 2ℵ0 = κ, and CCC(S) holds.

5

Page 6: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Proposition 2.3 Assume CCC(S). Then there is a ccc perfect suborder of Swhich has the Sacks property.

PROOF: In order to do this we have to define a family of 2ℵ0 dense opensubsets of S. Suppose A = 〈An : n < ω〉 is a sequence of countable antichainsin S. Let DA be the set of all T ∈ S such that either there is n such that Tis incompatible with all members of An or for all n there is Xn ⊆ An with|Xn| ≤ 2n such that T ≤ ∨

Xn. By a standard fusion argument one showsthat each DA is dense and open in S. Let

D = {DA : A a sequence of countable antichains }.

By applying CCC(S) to D we obtain a ccc perfect suborder Q of S in whichthe sets DA are all dense. It follows that Q has the Sacks property. 2

Example 3 We now present a construction of Glowczynski from [15]. In orderto obtain the assumptions of the theorem one needs a measurable cardinal,but the advantage is that the construction is very simple.

Theorem 2.4 [15] Assume Martin’s Axiom holds and there is an uncountablecardinal κ < 2ℵ0 which carries an ℵ1-saturated σ-ideal I. Then P(κ)/I is a cccweakly distributive complete Boolean algebra which is not a Maharam algebra.

Remark. This situation is easy to obtain: start with a measurable cardinalκ and force, using the standard ccc poset, MA + κ < 2ℵ0 . The dual of themeasure on κ in the ground model generates an ℵ1-saturated σ-complete idealI.

Proof: Let B = P(κ)/I. Clearly, B is ccc.

Claim 2.5 B is weakly distributive.

PROOF: Fix a double sequence {an,k}n,k of elements of B. We may assumewithout loss of generality that

∨k an,k = 1, for each n. We can find subsets

An,k of κ, for each n and k, such that an,k = [An,k]I and such that the family{An,k}k is a partition of κ, for each n. For each α < κ, define a functiongα ∈ ωω by:

gα(n) = min{k : α ∈ An,k}.Since we have MAκ there is a function g ∈ ωω such that gα ≤∗ f , for each α.Here ≤∗ denotes domination modulo finite sets. Define functions fl ∈ ωω byfl(k) = max{f(k), l} and let

Bl = {α : gα(n) ≤ fl(n), for all n}.

It follows that κ =⋃

l Bl. Thus, letting bl = [Bl]I , for each l, we have that∨l bl = 1, and on the other hand bl ≤

∧n

∨k<fl(n) an,k. 2

6

Page 7: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Claim 2.6 B is not a Maharam algebra.

PROOF: Suppose towards contradiction that B is a Maharam algebra and fixa continuous submeasure µ on B. By lifting µ to κ we obtain a continuoussubmeasure µ on P(κ) which gives value 0 to singletons and value 1 to thewhole space. Notice that we can replace κ by any set of reals D of size κ. Sincewe have MAκ, any subset of D is a Gδ-set. Therefore if Y is a subset of D ofµ-submeasure 0 then, for every ε > 0, there is an open set G ⊇ Y such thatµ(G) < ε. But now we can repeat the proof of the classical result that underMAκ any set of reals of size κ is Lebesgue null (see [22] ). 2

Example 4 We now present an example from [8] showing that if there is asingular strong limit cardinal κ such that 2κ = κ+ and �κ holds then thereis a complete Boolean algebra B of size κ+ which is weakly distributive andccc but is not a Maharam algebra. In fact, it suffices to build B which is nota measure algebra but such that every complete subalgebra of B of size atmost κ is a measure algebra. The point of this example is that if there is nosuch cardinal κ then there is an inner model with a measurable cardinal λ ofMitchell order o(λ) = λ++ (see [13]). Therefore the consistency of the positiveanswer to Question 2 requires at least these large cardinal assumptions. Theconstruction relies heavily on the one of Gitik and Shelah from [14].

Theorem 2.7 [8] Assume κ is a singular strong limit cardinal of uncountablecofinality such that 2κ = κ+ and �κ holds. Then there is a complete Booleanalgebra B of size κ+ which is ccc and weakly distributive but is not a Maharamalgebra.

Proof: We build a complete Boolean algebra B of size κ+ which is not ameasure algebra, but any complete subalgebra of B of strictly smaller size is ameasure algebra. The fact that small subalgebras are measure algebras clearlyimplies that B is ccc and weakly distributive. On the other hand, it is wellknown (see ([11, p. 584]) that any Maharam algebra which is not a measurealgebra contains a countably generated subalgebra which is not a measurealgebra. Thus B cannot be a Maharam algebra.

To begin the construction, note that using the assumptions of the theorem wecan obtain a nonreflecting stationary set S ⊆ κ+ consisting of limit ordinalsof cofinality ω such that ♦(S) holds and such that there is a �κ-sequence(Cα : α < κ+& lim(α)) such that Cα ∩ S = ∅, for all limit α (see [8] fordetails).

For a set I let AI be the Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of {0, 1}I . If I ⊆ Jthere is a natural projection πJ

I : {0, 1}J → {0, 1}I and we can consider AI

as a subalgebra of AJ by identifying a set A ∈ AI with (πJI )−1(A). We shall

consider finitely additive probability measures on various AI . Note that if µ issuch a measure then it naturally extends to a σ-additive measure µ on the σ-

7

Page 8: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

algebra BI of Baire subsets of {0, 1}I (see [11]). We let Iµ denote the σ-ideal ofµ-null sets. Given two finitely additive measures µ and ν on a Boolean algebraA we say µ and ν are equivalent and write µ ∼ ν if for every sequence (an)n

of elements of A we have limµ(an) = 0 iff lim ν(an) = 0. In case A = AI thismeans that the measures µ and ν have the same null sets. Finally, if I ⊆ Jand µ is a finitely additive measure on AJ let µ � AI be the induced measureon AI .

Fix a nonreflecting stationary set S ⊆ κ+ consisting of ordinals of cofinalityω, a ♦(S)-sequence (Dα : α ∈ S) and a �κ-sequence (Cα : α < κ+& lim(α))such that Cα ∩ S = ∅, for all limit α.

We construct by induction a sequence µα, for α < κ+, such that µα is a finiteprobability measure on Aα and the following conditions hold:

(1) If α < β then µα ∼ µβ � Aα.(2) If α = β + 1 for some β, then µα is the product of µβ and the uniform

probability measure on {0, 1} at the β-th coordinate.(3) If α /∈ S is a limit ordinal or α ∈ S and Dα is bounded in α, then µα is

the product measure of µα0 and the µαξ+1� A[αξ,αξ+1), where {αξ : ξ < δ}

is the increasing enumeration of Cα.(4) If α ∈ S and Dα is unbounded in α fix a sequence {αn}n cofinal in α

consisting of elements of Dα. Now let νn be the measure on A[αn,αn+1)

which is the product of µαn+1 � A(αn,αn+1) and, at coordinate αn, theprobability measure ρn on {0, 1} which gives measure 1/2n+1 to {0} and1− 1/2n+1 to {1}. Finally, let µα be the product measure of µα0 and theνn, for n < ω.

It is easy to show by induction that condition (1) holds. The main point isshowing that once the construction is completed we have the following.

Claim 2.8 There is no finitely additive probability measure µ on Aκ+ suchthat for all α < κ+, µ � Aα ∼ µα.

PROOF: Assume otherwise and fix such a µ. For every α let Eα be the set ofall f ∈ {0, 1}κ+

such that f(α) = 1. Then Eα ∈ Aκ+ , but we also consider itas an element of AI , for all I such that α ∈ I. Formally, we are identifying Eα

and πκ+

I (Eα).

Claim 2.9 For every ε > 0 there is δ > 0 such that for every A ∈ Aα ifµ(A) > ε then µ(A \ Eα) > δ.

PROOF: Recall that µα+1 is the product of µα and the uniform probabilitymeasure on {0, 1} at the α coordinate. Therefore if A ∈ Aα then

µα+1(A \ Eα) =1

2µα(A).

8

Page 9: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Since µ � Aα+1 ∼ µα+1 the claim follows. 2

Now for a given α < κ+ define the function fα ∈ ωω by letting fα(n) be theleast m such that for every A ∈ Aα if µ(A) ≥ 1/n then µ(A \Eα) ≥ 1/m. ByClaim 2.9 this function is well defined. Since κ+ > 2ℵ0 there is an unboundedsubset X of κ+ and a function f ∈ ωω such that fα = f , for all α ∈ X.

Claim 2.10 Suppose {αn}n is a strictly increasing sequence of elements ofX. Then

limn→∞

µ(⋂i<n

Eαi) = 0.

PROOF: Assume otherwise and fix an integer k such that for µ(⋂

i<nEαi) >

1/k, for all n. Let l = f(k). Since fαn = f , for every n, and the sequence{αn}n is strictly increasing, it follows that for every n

µ(⋂

i<n+1

Eαi) < µ(

⋂i<n

Eαi)− 1/l,

which is a contradiction. 2

Now since (Dα : α ∈ S) is a ♦(S)-sequence there is α ∈ S such that Dα =X ∩ α and this set is unbounded in α. It follow that at stage α we were usingcase (4) of our construction. Let {αn}n be the chosen sequence of elements ofDα. By the definition of µα the sets Eα are stochastically independant andµα(Eαn) = 1 − 1/2n+1. But then limn µα(

⋂i<nEαi

) ≥ ∏n(1 − 1/2n+1) > 0.

Therefore µ � Aα � µα, a contradiction. 2

Now, extend each µα to a σ-additive measure µα on the σ-algebra Bα of Bairesubsets of {0, 1}α. Let Iµα be the σ-ideal of µα-null sets. It follows by ourconstruction that if α < β then Iµα = Iµβ

� Bα in the obvious sense. Nowlet I =

⋃α<κ+ Iµα and C = Bκ+/I. It follows that C is a complete Boolean

algebra of size κ+ which is not a measure algebra but any complete subalgebraof C of size at most κ is a measure algebra. Finally to see that B is not aMaharam algebra note that any Maharam algebra which is not a measurealgebra contains a countably generated subalgebra which is not a measurealgebra (see [11, p. 584]). 2

3 Characterizations of Maharam algebras

The goal of this section is to present several characterizations of Maharamalgebras both in ZFC and under additional set theoretic assumptions. We willshow that it is relatively consistent with ZFC that the two conditions isolatedby Von Neumann, weak distributivity and the countable chain condition, are

9

Page 10: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

sufficient to characterize Maharam algebras. We then show that by strengthen-ing either one of these two conditions one can obtain a ZFC characterization.We start by reviewing some facts about the sequential topology defined byMaharam [24].

Definition 3.1 Let B be a σ-complete Boolean algebra. We say that an in-finite sequence {xn}n of elements of a B converges strongly to x (in symbolsxn → x) iff

lim supnxn = lim inf

nxn = x

It is fairly easy to verify.

(1) If xn = x, for all n, then xn → x(2) If xn → x, then any subsequence of {xn}n also converges strongly to x.(3) A monotone sequence is strongly convergent(4) xn → 0 iff lim supn xn = 0(5) If xn → x then −xn → −x(6) infn xn ∨ infn yn = infn,m xn ∨ ym

Given a subset A of B let us define A as the set of all x in B such that thereis a sequence {xn}n of elements of A such that xn → x. We now have:

(1) {0} = {0}(2) A ⊆ A(3) A ∪B = A ∪B

Note that in general ¯A may be different from A. In order to get a topologywe would have to iterate this operation ω1 times. However, Maharam ([24,Theorem 2]) showed that this is not necessary if B satisfies the followingcondition.

(I) Given any double sequence {xn,k}n,k which, for each fixed n decreasesmonotonically to 0 as k →∞, there exists a function f : N× N → N suchthat: ∧

i

∨n

xn,f(i,n) = 0

Moreover, it is easy to see that if B is weakly distributive and has the countablechain condition then it satisfies (I). In this case let τs be the induced topology.Note that the boolean operations are not in general continuous as binaryfunctions, but they are separately continuous, i.e. if we fix x then the functiony 7→ x ∨ y is continuous in y. Similarly for ∧ and ∆.

Now, if B is a measure algebra with a measure µ this topology is in fact metriz-able and the metric d is given by d(x, y) = µ(x∆y), where ∆ is the symmetricdifference. In this case (B,∆) is a topological group with the sequential topol-

10

Page 11: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

ogy. Maharam showed that B carries a continuous positive submeasure, i.e. is aMaharam algebra, iff (B, τs) be metrizable. Moreover, she found an algebraiccondition equivalent to the metrizability of B. Maharam’s characterizationwas improved by Balcar, Glowczynski and Jech [2] who showed that B is aMaharam algebra assuming only that the sequential topology τs is Hausdorff.

We will start by restating Maharam’s result in modern terminology. Recallthat an ideal I of subsets of a set X is called a P -ideal if for every sequence{An : n < ω} of elements of I there is A ∈ I such that An ⊆∗ A, for all n.Here ⊆∗ denotes inclusion modulo finite sets. We say that a set Y is orthogonalto a family A provided the intersection of Y with any element of A is finite.In this case we write Y⊥A and let A⊥ denote the collection of all subsetsY of X which are orthogonal to A. Note that A⊥ is always an ideal. Finallywe say that an ideal I on a set X is countably generated over FIN if there isa countable family {An}n of elements of I such that for any A ∈ I there isn such that A ⊆∗ An. Let B be a ccc weakly distributive complete Booleanalgebra. Following Quickert [27] let us define the following ideal I of countablesubsets of B:

X ∈ I if there is a maximal antichain A of elements of B such that everymember of A is compatible with at most finitely many elements of X.

Note that X ∈ I iff for every enumeration {xn}n of X limn xn = 0 in thesequential topology. Now we can restate Maharam’s result.

Theorem 3.2 [24] A ccc weakly distributive complete Boolean algebra B car-ries a continuous submeasure if and only if the dual I⊥ of the Quickert idealof B is countably generated over FIN. 2

Fix a Boolean algebra and let I be its Quickert ideal. Note that a set A is inI⊥ iff the closure A of A in the sequential topology does not contain 0. Thefollowing two facts are from [26].

Lemma 3.3 [26] If B is weakly distributive and ccc then I is a P -ideal.

Proof: SupposeXn ∈ I, for all n. Fix for each n a maximal antichain An suchthat each element of An is compatible with at most finitely many members ofXn. By the ccc of B An is countable for all n. Now, using the weak distributivityof B we can find a maximal antichain A which weakly refines each An, i.e. suchthat for each a ∈ A and each n there are at most finitely many members of An

compatible with a. Note that each element of A is compatible with at mostfinitely many members of Xn, for each n. Now, fix an enumeration {an}n ofA and let X be the union of the sets Xn \ {x ∈ Xn : x ∧ ∨n

i=0 ai 6= 0}. ThenX ∈ I as witnessed by the antichain A and Xn ⊆∗ X, for all n. 2

11

Page 12: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Lemma 3.4 [26] If B is ccc then there is no uncountable X such that [X]≤ω ⊆I.

Proof: Suppose X is an uncountable subset of B. Since B satisfies the cccthere is b ∈ B such that every nonzero a ≤ b is compatible with uncountablymany members of X. Then again, using the ccc of B there is a countableA ⊆ X such that every nonzero a ≤ b is compatible with infinitely manyelements of A. 2

We are now in the position to present the following strengthening of Ma-haram’s theorem which was proved by Balcar, Jech and Pazak [3] and theauthor [36] .

Theorem 3.5 [3][36] Let B be a weakly distributive ccc complete Boolean al-gebra and let I be the Quickert ideal of B. Assume B \ {0} can be covered bycountably many sets orthogonal to I. Then B is a Maharam algebra.

Proof: Now, by our assumption we can write B \ {0} =⋃

nXn, where Xn

is orthogonal to I, for all n. By replacing Xn by its upward closure we mayassume that if a ∈ Xn and a ≤ b then b ∈ Xn. Second, we can replaceXn by its topological closure. Note that the topological closure of Xn is stillupward closed. Finally, by replacing Xn by

⋃i≤nXi, we may assume that

X0 ⊆ X1 ⊆ X2 ⊆ . . .. Let Un = B \ Xn. Let U be the collection of all opensets which are downward closed and contain 0. Then, each Un belongs to U ,U0 ⊇ U1 ⊇ U2 ⊇ . . . and

⋂{Un : n < ω} = {0}.

Our first goal is to improve this sequence in order to have the additionalproperty that Un+1 ∨ Un+1 ⊆ Un, for every n, where U ∨ V = {u ∨ v : u ∈U and v ∈ V }. For this, it is clearly sufficient to show that for every U ∈ Uthere is V ∈ U such that V ∨ V ⊆ U .

For a subset V of B let V (x) = {a ∈ V : x ∨ a ∈ V }. Using the separatecontinuity of ∨ we see that if V is open then so is V (x), for every x. If Vis also downward closed then so is V (x) and finally if x ∈ V then V (x) isnonempty since it contains 0. So, if V ∈ U and x ∈ V then V (x) ∈ U .

Lemma 3.6 For every V ∈ U there is W ∈ U such that W ∨W ⊆ V .

Proof: Assume otherwise and fix a V ∈ U for which this fails. Let V0 = V ∩U0.Then, by our assumption, there are x0 and y0 in V0 such that x0∨ y0 /∈ V . LetV1 = V0(x0) ∩ V0(y0) ∩ U1. Then V1 ∈ U and therefore there are x1 and y1 inV1 such that x1 ∨ y1 /∈ V . Let V2 = V1(x1) ∩ V1(y1) ∩ U2. Then again, V2 ∈ U .We pick x2 and y2 in V2 such that x2 ∨ y2 /∈ V . We proceed by recursion.Given Vn ∈ U we can pick xn and yn in Vn such that xn ∨ yn /∈ V . We thenlet Vn+1 = Vn(xn) ∩ Vn(yn) ∩ Un+1. Notice that for every n and k we havexn ∨ xn+1 ∨ xn+2 . . . ∨ xn+k ∈ Un.

12

Page 13: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Claim 3.7 {xn : n < ω} and {yn : n < ω} belong to I.

Proof: Since the statement is symmetric let us assume, towards contradic-tion, that {xn : n < ω} is not in I. Fix a nonzero b in B such that every nonzeroa ≤ b is compatible with infinitely many xn. Since B is weakly distributive wecan pick a strictly increasing function f in ωω such that

c =∧n

f(n+1)∨i=f(n)+1

xi 6= 0.

Let zn =∨f(n)

i=f(n)+1 xi. Then, by our construction, we have that zn ∈ Uf(n)

and on the other hand c ≤ zn, for all n. Since the Un are downward closed itfollows that c ∈ ⋂{Ul : l < ω} = {0}, a contradiction. 2

Now, since both {xn : n < ω} and {yn : n < ω} are in I it follows that {xn ∨yn : n < ω} is in I, as well. This means that the sequence {xn ∨ yn}n stronglyconverges to 0 and V was supposed to be a neighborhood of 0. Therefore, foralmost all n, xn ∨ yn ∈ V , a contradiction. 2

Now, using Lemma 3.6 we can improve the original decreasing sequence U0 ⊇U1 ⊇ . . . to have in addition that Un+1 ∨ Un+1 ⊆ Un, for all n. At this pointwe could use Maharam’s theorem, but it is equally easy to define a continuoussubmeasure directly. First, let us define a function ϕ : B → [0, 1] by:

ϕ(a) = inf{2−n : a ∈ Un}

Now we define a submeasure µ : B → [0, 1] as follow

µ(b) = inf({l∑

i=1

ϕ(ai) : b ≤l∨

i=1

ai} ∪ {1})

Lemma 3.8 µ is a positive continuous submeasure on B.

Proof: It is clear that if a ≤ b then µ(a) ≤ µ(b) and that µ(a ∨ b) ≤µ(a) + µ(b), for every a, b ∈ B. We need to show that µ is positive on everynonzero element of B and that it is continuous. The following fact is immediate.

Fact 1 Suppose n1 < n2 < . . . < nk and ai ∈ Uni+1, for i = 1, . . . k. Then∨ki=1 ai ∈ Un1. 2

From this it follows that if a /∈ Un then µ(a) ≥ 2−n, therefore µ is positive.Finally, to see that µ is continuous notice that by Lemma 1 of [24] it sufficesto prove that if {an : n < ω} ∈ I then limn µ(an) = 0. To show this fix aninteger k. Since {an : n < ω} ∈ I and Uk is large, there is n such that al ∈ Uk

for all l ≥ n. This means that

µ(al) ≤ ϕ(al) ≤ 2−k

13

Page 14: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

for all l ≥ n. Since k was abritrary it follows that limn(an) = 0, as desired.This finishes the proof of Lemma 3.8 and Theorem 3.5. 2

For a given uncountable cardinal κ we consider the following statement.

(∗)κ : Let X be a set of size at most κ and let I be a P -ideal of countablesubsets of X. Then one of the following two alternatives holds:(a) there is an uncountable subset Y of X such that [Y ]≤ω ⊆ I, or(b) we can write X =

⋃nXn, where Xn is orthogonal to I for each n.

The P -ideal dichotomy is the statement that (∗)κ holds for all cardinals κ.This principle follows from the Proper Forcing Axiom and was first studiedby Abraham and Todorcevic [1] who proved that (∗)2ℵ0 is relatively consistentwith CH. Later, Todorcevic [32] extended this result by showing that the fullversion of the P -ideal dichotomy is relatively consistent with GCH assumingthe existence of a supercompact cardinal. In particular, what is shown in [32]is the following.

Lemma 3.9 Let I be a P -ideal of countable subsets of a set X. Assume thatX is not covered by countably many sets orthogonal to I. Then there is properσ-distributive forcing notion P which adds an uncountable subset Y of X suchthat [Y ]≤ω ⊆ I.

Say that a partial ordering P is indestructibly ccc if P remains ccc in anygeneric extension of the universe of set theory. For example, forcing notionswhich are σ-linked, satisfy the σ-finite chain condition 1 and Souslin forcings 2

are all indestructibly ccc. On the other hand, a Souslin tree T is not indestruc-tibly ccc since forcing with T itself destroys the ccc-ness of T . Now, usingTheorem 3.5, Lemma 3.4 and Lemma 3.9 we immediately have the following.

Corollary 3.10 Every indestructibly ccc weakly distributive complete Booleanalgebra is a Maharam algebra. 2

The particular instance of this corollary for Boolean algebras satisfying theσ-finite chain condition was derived directly by Todorcevic [33]. Finally, byassuming the full P -ideal dichotomy we have the following.

Corollary 3.11 Assume the P -ideal dichotomy. Then every weakly distribu-tive ccc complete Boolean algebra is a Maharam algebra. 2

In [29] Shelah showed that every ccc Souslin forcing which is nowhere weaklydistributive adds a Cohen real. On the other hand, it is well known (see [18])

1 A partial ordering P satisfies the σ-finite chain condition if it can be written asP =

⋃n An such that every antichain in An is finite, for all n.

2 A forcing notion (P,≤) is called Souslin if P is an analytic set of reals and boththe ordering ≤ and the incompatibility relation ⊥ are analytic subsets of P2.

14

Page 15: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

that the ccc of Souslin forcing notions is indestructible. Thus we have thefollowing result which was also obtained by Farah and Zapletal [10] by usingSolecki’s result [30] about analytic P -ideals.

Corollary 3.12 Let S be a nonatomic Souslin ccc forcing notion. Then eitherthere is p ∈ S such that forcing with S below p adds a Cohen real or else theregular open algebra RO(S) is a Maharam algebra. 2

We now turn back to the sequential topology τs on a complete Boolean algebraB and present a result of B. Balcar, W. Glowczynski, and T. Jech [2] sayingthat B is a Maharam algebra iff τs is Hausdorff. In order to prove this wewill need a lemma which is similar to Lemma 3.6. Let as before U denote thefamily of open sets which are nonempty and downward closed. The differencebetween Lemma 3.13 and Lemma 3.6 is that now we do not assume that thereis a decreasing family {Un}n of sets which are in U and such that

⋂n Un = {0}.

In fact, Lemma 3.6 is not true without this additional assumption.

Lemma 3.13 [2] Assume B is ccc and weakly distributive. Then for everyU ∈ U there is a V ∈ U such that V ∨ V ∨ V ⊆ U ∨ U .

Proof: Assume otherwise and fix a U ∈ U for which this fails. For any V ⊆ Band x ∈ B let as before V (x) denote the set of all y ∈ B such that x ∨ y ∈ V .So we have that if V ∈ U and x ∈ V then V (x) ∈ U .

We define recursively a sequence {Vn}n of sets in U and three sequences {xn}n,{yn}n and {zn}n as follows. Let V0 = U . Then, by our assumption, there are x0,y0 and z0 in V0 such that x0∨y0∨z0 /∈ U ∨U . Let V1 = V0(x0)∩V0(y0)∩V0(z0).Then V1 ∈ U and therefore there are x1, y1 and z1 in V1 such that x1∨y1∨z1 /∈U∨U . Let V2 = V1(x1)∩V1(y1)∩V1(z1). We proceed by recursion. Given Vn ∈ Uwe can pick xn, yn and zn in Vn such that xn ∨ yn ∨ zn /∈ U ∨ U . We thenlet Vn+1 = Vn(xn) ∩ Vn(yn) ∩ Vn(zn). Once we complete the construction letx = lim supn xn, y = lim supn yn and z = lim supn zn. Notice that x ∨ y ∨ z ≥lim supn(xn ∨ yn ∨ zn) and since xn ∨ yn ∨ zn /∈ U ∨ U , for all n, and U ∨ U isdownward closed and topologically open it follows that x ∨ y ∨ z /∈ U ∨ U .

On the other hand, notice that by our construction for every l < m < n wehave

l−1∨i=0

xi ∨m−1∨i=l

yi ∨n−1∨i=m

zi ∈ U.

Now, first find l such that a = x − ∨l−1i=1 xi ∈ U , then let U1 = U(a) and find

m > l such that b = y − ∨m−1i=l yi ∈ U1, and finally let U2 = U1(b) and find

n > m such that c = z−∨n−1m zi ∈ U2. So we have that a∨b∨c ∈ U . Therefore

we have that

x ∨ y ∨ z ≤ (l−1∨i=0

xi ∨m−1∨i=l

yi ∨n−1∨i=m

zi) ∨ (a ∨ b ∨ c) ∈ U ∨ U.

15

Page 16: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Since U ∨ U is downward closed it follows that x ∨ y ∨ z ∈ U ∨ U , a contra-diction. 2

Theorem 3.14 [2] Suppose B is a ccc complete Boolean algebra for which thesequential topology is Hausdorff. Then B is a Maharam algebra.

Proof: We first prove that B is weakly distributive. So, fix a sequence {An}n

of maximal antichains in B. Enumerate each An as {an,k}k. Now, given anonzero x ∈ B we need to find y ≤ x which is compatible with at most finitelymany elements of An, for each n. Fix disjoint τs-open sets U and V such that0 ∈ U and c ∈ V . Now, define a decreasing sequence {xn}n of elements of V asfollows. Let x0 = x. Given xn consider the sequence {xn∧

∨ki=0 an,i}k. Since An

is a maximal antichain this sequence converges to xn and since V is open andxn ∈ V there is kn such that xn∧

∨kni=0 an,i ∈ V . Let xn+1 = xn∧

∨kni=0 an,i. Note

that the sequence {xn}n is decreasing, so it converges to y =∧

n xn. Since thexn do not belong to U and U is open it follows that y /∈ U . So in particulary is not zero and it is clearly compatible with at most finitely many membersof An, for each n.

Let, as before, U denote the family of all topologically open downward closednonempty subsets of B. We claim that for every nonzero a ∈ B there is asequence {Un}n of members of U such that a − ∨ ⋂

n Un 6= 0. To see this fixa 6= 0. Since τs is Hausdorff we can find U ∈ U such that a /∈ U ∨ U . UsingLemma 3.13 we can pick a decreasing sequence {Un}n of members of U suchthat U0 = U , and Un+1 ∨ Un+1 ∨ Un+1 ⊆ Un ∨ Un, for every n. It follows that

Un+k ∨ Un+k ∨ . . . ∨ Un+k︸ ︷︷ ︸k+2−times

⊆ Un ∨ Un

We claim that the sequence {Un}n works. Suppose towards contradiction thata ≤ ∨ ⋂

n Un. Since B is ccc we can find a sequence {bn}n of elements of⋂

n Un

such that a ≤ ∨n bn. Since U1 is a downward closed neighborhood of 0 there

is an n such that a − ∨ni=0 bi ∈ U1. Since bi ∈ Un, for each i, we have that∨n

i=0 bi ∈ U1 ∨ U1. Therefore, a ∈ U1 ∨ U1 ∨ U1 ⊆ U ∨ U , a contradiction.

Now, we can choose a maximal antichain A and, for each a ∈ A, a decreas-ing sequence {Ua

n}n of members of U such that a is incompatible with everyelement of

⋂n U

an . Since B is ccc the antichain A is countable and it follows

that {Uan : n ∈ ω and a ∈ A} is a countable family of members of U whose

intersection is {0}. Therefore by Theorem 3.5 B is a Maharam algebra. 2

As an application of this result, we now show that by keeping the ccc andstrengthening weak distributivity we can obtain another characterization ofMaharam algebras. For this we will need the concept of a weak distributivitygame G(B) on a complete Boolean algebra B which is played as follows.

16

Page 17: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

I a0, A0 A1 A2 ...

II a1 a2 a3 ...

Player I starts by playing a nonzero a0 ∈ B and a maximal antichain A0 in B.Then Player II chooses a nonzero element a1 ≤ a0 which is contained in theunion of finitely many elements of A0. Player I then plays another maximalantichain A1 and Player II plays a nonzero a2 ≤ a1 contained in the union offinitely many elements of A1. The game proceeds in this fashion ω moves. Inthe end we say that Player I wins iff

∧n an = 0; otherwise Player II wins. A

winning strategy τ for one of the players is a rule which tells him what to playat any given position such that if he follows τ he wins the game. The followingfact is well known and easy to prove (see e.g. [19]).

Proposition 3.15 Suppose B is a complete ccc Boolean algebra. Then B isweakly distributive iff Player I does not have a winning strategy in G(B). 2

Clearly, at most one player can have a winning strategy in this game. Notethat if B is a Maharam algebra then Player II has an easy winning strategy.Namely, fix a strictly positive continuous submeasure µ on B. Suppose I playsa0, A0 in the first move. Let α = µ(a0). II just makes sure to play elements an

such that µ(an) > α/2. At stage n suppose we have an such that µ(an) > α/2and I plays a maximal antichain An. Let {xk}k be an enumeration of An.Since µ is continuous there is k such that µ(a0 ∧

∨ki=0 xi) > α/2. Player II

then plays an+1 = an ∧∨k

i=0 xi. In the end, since µ is continuous we havethat µ(

∧n an) ≥ α/2, so Player II wins this run of the game. Now, let us

say that a complete Boolean algebra B is strategically weakly distributive ifPlayer II has a winning strategy in G(B). We now show that by strengtheningweak distributivity to strategic weak distributivity in Question 2 we obtain apositive result in ZFC.

Theorem 3.16 Suppose B is a ccc strategically weakly distributive completeBoolean algebra. Then B is a Maharam algebra.

Proof: By Theorem 3.14 it suffices to show that the sequential topologyτs on B is Hausdorff. We first show that there are two disjoint τs-open setswhich separate 1 and 0. Let us fix a winning strategy σ for Player II in G(B).We say that a position p = (a0, A0, a1, A1, . . . , An) is consistent with σ ifak = σ(a0, A0, a1, A1, . . . , Ak−1), for each k ≥ 1.

Claim 3.17 There is a position p in G(B) consistent with σ such that forevery two positions q and r of odd length consistent with σ and extending pwe have σ(q) ∧ σ(r) 6= 0.

17

Page 18: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Proof: Otherwise we could build a tree {ps : s ∈ 2<ω} of positions of oddlength consistent with σ and such that σ(ps 0) ∧ σ(ps 1) = 0, for every s ∈{0, 1}<ω. If α ∈ {0, 1}ω then pα =

⋃n pα�n is an infinite run of the game in

which Player II follows σ and therefore wins. Let {aα,n}n be the sequenceof moves played by Player II in pα. It follows that aα =

∧n aα,n 6= 0. Since

σ(ps 0)∧σ(ps 1) = 0, for each s, it follows that {aα : α ∈ {0, 1}ω} is a antichainof size 2ℵ0 in B which contradicts the ccc of B. 2

Now fix a position as in Claim 3.17. We may assume it is Player I’s turn toplay. Let U be the set of all a ∈ B such that there exists a maximal antichainA in B such that σ(pA) ≤ a and let V be the set {−a : a ∈ U}. Clearly,1 ∈ V and 0 ∈ U . Note that by our assumption on p U and V are disjoint. Weclaim that they are both open. To see this for U suppose {xn}n is a sequenceconverging to 0. We can fix a maximal antichain A such that every element ofA is compatible with at most finitely many of the xn. Let a = σ(pA). Thena ∈ V and −a ∈ U . Since U is closed downward it follows that all but finitelymany of the xn belong to U . Thus, a tail of every sequence converging to 0is contained in U and so 0 belongs to the interior of U . A similar argumentshows that V contains a tail of any sequence converging to 1, i.e. 1 is in theinterior of V . Given any nonzero a ∈ B Player I can start the game by playinga0 = a, so a similar argument gives two disjoint open sets separating a and 0.This implies that τs is Hausdorff and thus by Theorem 3.14 B is a Maharamalgebra. 2

Remark In [12] Fremlin considered the following related game G∗(B) playedon a complete Boolean algebra B.

I A0 A1 A2 ...

II a1 a2 a3 ...

In the n-th round of the game Player I plays a maximal antichain An in Band Player II responds by playing an ∈ B which is contained in the union offinitely many members of An. The game proceeds in this fashion ω moves. Inthe end we say that Player II wins iff (an)n converges to 1 in the sequentialtopology. Fremlin shows that a complete Boolean algebra B is a Maharamalgebra iff Player II has a winning strategy in G∗(B). Clearly, if Player II hasa winning strategy in G∗(B) then B is ccc. Thus, Fremlin’s result follows fromTheorem 3.16. In addition Theorem 3.16 implies that Problems 11J and 11Kfrom [12] have negative answers.

18

Page 19: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

4 Maharam algebras as forcing notions

In this section we considered Maharam algebras as forcing notions and askif they have some of the common properties of measure algebras. We firstpresent a result from [36] saying that every nonatomic Maharam algebra addsa splitting real and then a result from [9] saying that the product of any twononatomic Maharam algebras adds a Cohen real.

Let B be a complete Boolean algebra. Recall that B adds a splitting real ifthere is a B name τ for a set of integers such that the maximal condition 1Bforces that τ is neither contained nor disjoint from an infinite set of integersfrom the ground model. It is well known that any nonatomic measure algebraadds a splitting real. The following result shows that Maharam algebras havethe same property.

Theorem 4.1 [36] Let B be a nonatomic Maharam algebra. Then B adds asplitting real.

We will need the following lemma.

Lemma 4.2 Let B be a ccc complete Boolean algebra and let I be the Quickertideal of B. Suppose B does not add a splitting real below any condition. Thenevery infinite subset X of B has an infinite subset Y such that either

∧Y 6= 0

or Y ∈ I.

Proof: Fix an enumeration X = {bn : n < ω} and let τ be the name foran element of 2ω defined by ||τ(n) = 1|| = bn. Since τ is forced not to be asplitting real there is an infinite I0 ⊆ N and a nonzero c0 such that c0 ”τ � I0is constant.” We recursively build an antichain {cξ : ξ < δ} and a decreasingmod finite sequence I0 ⊇∗ . . . ⊇∗ Iξ ⊇∗ . . . such that cξ B ”τ � Iξ is almostconstant”, for all ξ. At a countable limit stage λ we first diagonalize to findan infinite J such that J ⊆∗ Iξ, for all ξ < λ. If {cξ : ξ < λ} is not already amaximal antichain, by using the fact that τ � J is forced not to be a splittingreal, we find cλ incompatible with all the cξ, for ξ < λ, and an infinite Iλ ⊂ Jsuch that cλ B ”τ � J is constant”. Since B is ccc the construction muststop after countably many steps. At this stage we get an infinite I such that ”τ � I is almost constant”. Let Y = {bn : n ∈ I}. If there is c ∈ B \ {0}and an integer n such that c B τ � (I \ n) ≡ 1, then it follows that c ≤ ∧

Y .Otherwise B ”Y ∩ G is finite ”. 2

PROOF of Theorem 4.1: Let µ be a continuous submeasure on B. If µ isuniformly exhaustive, by a theorem of Kalton and Roberts [21] (for a precisestatement see Theorem 4.5 below) B is a measure algebra and therefore itadjoins a random real. Assume now B is not uniformly exhaustive and fixan ε > 0 which witnesses this. We can now fix, for each n, a family An =

19

Page 20: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

{an,1 . . . , an,n} of pairwise disjoint sets of µ-submeasure ≥ ε. Note that byLemma 4.2 and the continuity of µ if X is an infinite set of members of Beach of µ-submeasure ≥ ε then there is an infinite subset Y of X such that∧Y 6= 0. Fix a family {fξ : ξ < ω1} of functions in

∏n{1, . . . , n} such that for

ξ 6= η there is l such that fξ(k) 6= fη(k), for all k ≥ l. We build a tower ofinfinite subsets of N, I0 ⊇∗ I1 ⊇∗ . . . ⊇∗ Iξ ⊇∗ . . ., for ξ < ω1, such that

bξ =∧{an,fξ(n) : n ∈ Iξ} 6= 0,

for each ξ. At a stage α we do the following. If α is a limit ordinal we first findan infinite set J such that J ⊆∗ Iξ, for all ξ < α; if α = β+1 let J = Iβ. Now,look at the family {an,fα(n) : n ∈ J}. By Lemma 4.2 we can find an infiniteIα ⊆∗ J such that bα =

∧{an,fα(n) : n ∈ Iα} 6= 0. Notice that if ξ 6= η then bξand bη are incompatible. Therefore {bξ : ξ < ω1} is an uncountable antichainin B, a contradiction. 2

For the following corollary we only need a version of the P -ideal dichotomy forideals on 2ℵ0 whose relative consistency with CH was proved by Abraham andTodorcevic [1] without any large cardinal assumptions. This follows from thefact that every nonatomic complete ccc Boolean algebra contains a nonatomiccomplete subalgebra of size at most 2ℵ0 .

Corollary 4.3 [36]Assume ZFC is consistent. Then so is ZFC + CH + ”everynonatomic weakly distributive ccc forcing adds a splitting real”. 2

The next result we present is motivated by the well known fact that theproduct of any two nonatomic measure algebras adds a Cohen real (see forinstance [4]). It was shown by Farah and the author [9] that the same is truefor Maharam algebras instead of measure algebras. Before we begin let usrecall that a submeasure ν on a Boolean algebra is pathological if it does notdominate a positive nonzero finitely additive measure. The following is wellknown (see, for instance, [10, Lemma 2.5]).

Proposition 4.4 Let ν be a continuous submeasure on a complete Booleanalgebra B. Then there is b ∈ B such that ν � Bb is pathological and ν � Bb{ isequivalent to a measure, where Ba denotes the restriction of B to a.

We will also need the following important result of Kalton and Roberts from[21] (see also [23] and [12]).

Theorem 4.5 [21] Let ν be a pathological submeasure on a Boolean algebraB. Assume that ν(1B) = 1 and let α < 1/3. Then for every integer n there isa sequence (ai)

ni=1 of pairwise disjoint elements of B such that ν(ai) ≥ α, for

all i.

Let CO(2N) denote the algebra of all clopen subsets of 2N. For A ⊆ (2N)2 let

20

Page 21: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Ax = {y : (x, y) ∈ A} and Ay = {x : (x, y) ∈ A}. The following theoremfrom [9] shows that for the product of two submeasure at one of which ispathological Fubini’s theorem fails in the worst possible way. Special cases ofthis result appear in [5] and [10, Lemma 2.5].

Theorem 4.6 [9] Let ϕ and ψ be exhaustive nonatomic submeasures on CO(2N).Assume that ψ is pathological and let ε > 0. Then there is a clopen subset Wof 2N × 2N such that

(1) ψ(W {x ) ≤ ε, for every x ∈ 2N,

(2) ϕ(W y) ≤ ε, for every y ∈ 2N.

PROOF: First note that if ν is an exhaustive nonatomic submeasure onCO(2N) then for every δ > 0 there is an integer n and a partition (Ai)

ni=1

of 2N into disjoint clopen sets such that ν(Ai) ≤ ε, for all i. We fix exhaustivesubmeasures ϕ and ψ as in the statement of the theorem.

Claim 4.7 For every ε > 0 there is a clopen set U ⊆ 2N × 2N such that

(1) ψ(Ux) ≥ ψ(2N)/4, for every x ∈ 2N,(2) ϕ(Uy) ≤ ε, for every y ∈ 2N.

PROOF: Fix a partition (Ai)ni=1 of 2N into disjoint clopen sets such that

ϕ(Ai) ≤ ε, for all i. Now, since ψ is pathological we can apply Theorem 4.5 tofind a partition (Bi)

ni=1 of 2N into clopen sets such that ψ(Bi) ≥ ψ(2N)/4, for

all i. Let U =⋃n

i=1Ai ×Bi. Then U is as desired. 2

Claim 4.8 Let W be a clopen subset of 2N × 2N and ε > 0. Then there is aclopen U such that U ∩W = ∅ and

(1) ψ(Ux) ≥ ψ((Wx){)/4, for every x ∈ 2N,

(2) ϕ(Uy) ≤ ε, for every y ∈ 2N.

PROOF: Since W is clopen we can fix an integer n and a subset S of 2n × 2n

such that (x, y) ∈ W iff (x � n, y � n) ∈ S. For each s ∈ 2<N let [s] denote theset {x ∈ 2N : s ⊆ x}. For s ∈ 2n let Ws denote Wx, for any (equivalently all)x ∈ [s]. Let Zs be the complement of Ws and apply Claim 1 to get a clopensubset of [s]× Zs such that

(1) ψ((Us)x) ≥ ψ(Zs)/4, for every x ∈ [s],(2) ϕ((Us)

y) ≤ ε/2n, for every y ∈ Zs.

Let U =⋃{Us : s ∈ 2n}. Then U is as desired. 2

To finish the proof of the theorem, using Claims 1 and 2 we construct asequence (Un)n of clopen subsets of 2N × 2N such that, letting Wn =

⋃{Ui :i < n}, for every n we have

21

Page 22: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

(1) ψ((Un)x) ≥ ψ((Wn)x){)/4, for every x ∈ 2N,

(2) ϕ((Un)y) ≤ ε/2n+1, for every y ∈ 2N.

We claim that there is n such that ψ((Wn){x) ≤ ε, for all x ∈ 2N. To see that

assume otherwise and let Cn be the set of all x such that ψ((Wn){x) > ε. Note

that Cn is clopen and by our assumption it is nonempty, for all n. MoreoverCn+1 ⊆ Cn for all n. Choose x in

⋂nCn. It follows that the sequence ((Un)x)n

is pairwise disjoint and ψ((Un)x) ≥ ε/4. This contradicts the fact that ψ isexhaustive. 2

We are now ready to prove the following.

Theorem 4.9 [9] Let B and C be two nonatomic Maharam algebras. ThenB × C adds a Cohen real.

Proof: First, we may assume without loss of generality that B and C are bothcountably generated. By the Loomis-Sikorski theorem we may also assumethat there are continuous submeasures ϕ and ψ on the σ-algebra Bor of Borelsubsets of 2N such that B = Bor/Null(ϕ) and C = Bor/Null(ψ). Since Band C are nonatomic, we may also assume that ϕ and ψ are positive on anynonempty clopen subset of 2N. If both B and C are measure algebras, thenB × C adds a Cohen real (see e.g., [4, Theorem 3.2.11]). Therefore we mayassume that one of B and C is not a measure algebra. By Proposition 4.4 forevery continuous submeasure θ on Bor we can find a Borel set A such thatthe restriction of θ to the algebra of Borel subsets of A is equivalent to ameasure while the restriction of θ to the algebra of Borel subsets of 2N \ A ispathological. This means that without loss of generality we may assume thatone of ϕ or ψ is a pathological submeasure. For concreteness, let us say thatψ is pathological. Our plan is to use Theorem 4.6. For ε > 0, let us say thata clopen subset U of 2N × 2N is ε-good if

(1) ψ(U{x) ≤ ε, for every x ∈ 2N,

(2) ϕ(Uy) ≤ ε, for every y ∈ 2N.

Thus, by Theorem 4.6 for every ε > 0 there is a clopen set U which is ε-good.Suppose now U is ε-good, for some ε > 0. Note that for every Borel sets Band C such that ϕ(B) > ε and ψ(C) > ε we have B × C intersects both Uand U{. Given ρ, ε and δ such that 0 < δ < ρ let us say that U is (ρ, δ)-goodif for every Borel sets B and C with ϕ(B) > ρ and ψ(C) > ρ and i ∈ {0, 1}there are Borel sets Bi ⊆ B and Ci ⊆ C such that ϕ(Bi) > δ, ψ(Ci) > δ andsuch that Bi × Ci ⊆ U i, where U0 = U and U1 = U{.

Claim 4.10 Suppose U is clopen and ε-good. Then for every ρ > ε there isδ > 0 such that U is (ρ, δ)-good.

PROOF: Since U is clopen there is n such that U depends on the first n

22

Page 23: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

coordinates, i.e., there is a subset S of 2n × 2n such that (x, y) ∈ U iff (x �n, y � n) ∈ S. Let δ = ρ−ε

2n . We will show that U is (ρ, δ)-good. Suppose Band C are Borel sets such that ϕ(B) > ρ and ψ(C) > ρ. Let T be the setof all u ∈ 2n such that ϕ(B ∩ [u]) > ρ−ε

2n . Let B′ = {x ∈ B : x � n ∈ T}.Similarly let R be the set of all v ∈ 2n such that ψ(C ∩ [v]) > ρ−ε

2n and letC ′ = {y ∈ C : y � n ∈ R}. Then ϕ(B′) > ε and ψ(C ′) > ε. Since U is ε-goodwe have B′×C ′∩U 6= ∅. Fix (x, y) ∈ B′×C ′∩U . Let u = x � n and v = y � n.It follows that (u, v) ∈ S, i.e. [u]× [v] ⊆ U . Set B0 = B∩ [u] and C0 = C ∩ [v].Then B0 and C0 are as desired. The construction of B1 and C1 is symmetricand is done in the same way. 2

We now construct a B × C-name for a Cohen real. We are going to build adecreasing sequence of positive reals (εn)n converging to 0 and a sequence(Un)n of clopen subsets of 2N × 2N such that Un is (2εn, 2εn+1)-good. To startlet ε0 = 1/2 and let U0 be any clopen subset of 2N × 2N which is 1/2-good.Given εn and Un which is εn-good we first use Claim 3 to find εn+1 such thatUn is (2εn, 2εn+1)-good and then use Theorem 4.6 a to find a clopen subsetUn+1 of 2N × 2N which is εn+1-good. By decreasing εn+1 if necessary we mayassume that it is less than 1/2n+1. This completes the construction of the εnand Un. Now, since each Un is clopen we can find an integer mn and a subsetSn of 2mn × 2mn such that x ∈ Un iff x � mn ∈ Sn.

Suppose now G × H is the canonical name for the B × C-generic filter. Letτ denote a name for the set of all n such that there is (u, v) ∈ Sn such that[u]× [v] ∈ G× H.

Claim 4.11 The maximal condition in B × C forces that τ is Cohen genericover the ground model.

PROOF: Let D be a dense set in the Cohen forcing 2<N and let (B,C) bea condition in B × C. Let ρ = min{ϕ(B), ψ(C)}. Find n such that ρ > 2εn.Then find an integer m and t ∈ 2m such that st ∈ D, for every s ∈ 2n.We build decreasing sequences (Bi)

mi=0 and (Ci)

mi=0 of conditions in B and C

respectively. We will have ϕ(Bi) > 2εn+i and ψ(Ci) > 2εn+i, for all i. To startlet B0 = B and C0 = C. Suppose Bi and Ci have been constructed. SinceUn+i is (2εn+i, 2εn+i+1)-good if t(i) = 0 we can choose Bi+1 and Ci+1 such thatϕ(Bi+1) > 2εn+i+1 and ψ(Ci+1) > 2εn+i+1 and such that Bi+1×Ci+1∩Un+i = ∅.If t(i) = 1 we can choose Bi+1 and Ci+1 such that Bi+1×Ci+1 ⊆ Un+i. Finallylet B∗ = Bm and C∗ = Cm. It follows that (B∗, C∗) forces that there is s ∈ 2n

such that τ � (n + m) = st and therefore τ � (n + m) ∈ D. Since B and Cwere arbitrary it follows that τ is forced to be a Cohen real over the groundmodel. 2

This completes the proof of Claim 4 and Theorem 4.9. 2

Using the theorem of Shelah [29] saying that every nonatomic ccc nowhere

23

Page 24: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

weakly distributive Souslin forcing adds a Cohen real, Corollary 3.12 andTheorem 4.9 we now have the following immediate corollary.

Corollary 4.12 If P and Q are nonatomic Souslin ccc forcing notions thenP ×Q adds a Cohen real. 2

5 Open Questions

At the moment the only example of a Maharam algebra which is not a measurealgebra is the one constructed by Talagrand [31] and not much is known aboutits properties.

Question 3 Does the Maharam algebra constructed by Talagrand [31] containa complete nonatomic subalgebra which is a measure algebra?

This is related to the following well known problem of Prikry.

Question 4 Is it relatively consistent with ZFC that every nonatomic cccforcing notion adds either a Cohen or a random real?

The next question asks if it is possible to generalize Talagrand’s constructionto higher cardinals.

Question 5 Given an infinite cardinal κ is there a Maharam algebra of den-sity κ which does not contain a measure subalgebra of density κ?

Question 6 Can forcing with a Maharam algebra add a minimal real, i.e. areal r such that for every real s ∈ V [r] either s ∈ V or V [s] = V [r]?

Note that by the main result of [29] referred to at the end of Section 4 this isreally asking if there is a Souslin ccc forcing which adds a minimal real.

Question 7 Suppose a ccc forcing P does not add splitting reals. Is P neces-sarily weakly distributive?

Finally, we mention a well known problem of Horn and Tarski [17]. Recall thata Boolean algebra B has the σ-finite chain condition if it can be written asB \ {0} =

⋃nXn such that Xn does not contain infinite antichains, for each n.

We say that B has the σ-bounded chain condition if there is such a partitionsuch that for each n there is an integer kn such that Xn does not contain anyantichain of size at least kn. Clearly, every Maharam algebra has the σ-finitechain condition; we can simply take Xn = {a ∈ B : µ(a) ≥ 1/n}, where µ is acontinuous strictly positive submeasure on B.

24

Page 25: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

Question 8 Is there a Boolean algebra which has the σ-finite chain conditionbut not the σ-bounded chain condition? In particular does every Maharamalgebra have the σ-bounded chain condition?

References

[1] U. Abraham and S. Todorcevic. Partition properties of ω1 compatible with CH.Fund. Math., 152(2):165–181, 1997.

[2] B. Balcar, W. Glowczynski, and T. Jech. The sequential topology on completeBoolean algebras. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 155:59–78, 1998.

[3] B. Balcar, T. Jech, and T. Pazak. Complete ccc Boolean algebras, the ordersequential topology, and a problem of von Neumann. Bulletin of the LondonMath. Soc., 37:885–898, 2005.

[4] T. Bartoszynski and H. Judah. Set theory: on the structure of the real line.A.K. Peters, 1995.

[5] J. Christensen. Some results with relation to the control measure problem.In R. Aron and S. Dineen, editors, Vector space measures and applications II,volume 645 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics, pages 27–34. Springer, 1978.

[6] N. Dobrinen. Games and general distributive laws in Boolean algebras. Proc.Amer. Math. Soc., 131(1):309–318 (electronic), 2003.

[7] I. Farah. Examples of ε-exhaustive pathological submeasures. Fund. Math.,181(3):257–272, 2004.

[8] I. Farah and B. Velickovic. Von Neumann’s problem and large cardinals.Bulletin of the London Math. Society, 38(6):907–912, 2006.

[9] I. Farah and B. Velickovic. Maharam algebras and Cohen reals. Proceedings ofthe Amer. Math. Soc., to appear.

[10] I. Farah and J. Zapletal. Between Maharam’s and von Neumann’s problems.Math. Res. Lett., 11(5-6):673–684, 2004.

[11] D. Fremlin. Measure Theory, volume 3. Torres–Fremlin, 2002.

[12] D. Fremlin. Maharam algebras. preprint, University of Essex, available athttp://www.essex.ac.uk/maths/staff/fremlin/preprints.htm, 2004.

[13] M. Gitik and W. J. Mitchell. Indiscernible sequences for extenders, and thesingular cardinal hypothesis. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 82(3):273–316, 1996.

[14] M. Gitik and S. Shelah. More on real-valued measurable cardinals and forcingwith ideals. Israel J. Math., 124:221–242, 2001.

[15] W. Glowczynski. Measures on Boolean algebras. Proceedings Amer. Math. Soc.,11(3):845–849, 1991.

25

Page 26: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

[16] C. Gray. Iterated forcing from the strategic point of view. PhD thesis, Universityof California, Berkeley, 1982.

[17] A. Horn and A. Tarski. Measures in Boolean algebras. Transactions of theAmerican Mathematical Society, 64:467–497, 1948.

[18] J. I. Ihoda and S. Shelah. Souslin forcing. J. Symbolic Logic, 53(4):1188–1207,1988.

[19] T. J. Jech. More game-theoretic properties of Boolean algebras. Ann. PureAppl. Logic, 26(1):11–29, 1984.

[20] R. Jensen. Definable sets of minimal degree. In Y. Bar-Hillel, editor,Mathematical Logic and Foundations of Set Theory, pages 122–128. NorthHolland Publishing. Co., Amsterdam, 1970.

[21] N. Kalton and J. Roberts. Uniformly exhaustive submeasures and nearlyadditive set functions. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society,278:803–816, 1983.

[22] K. Kunen. Set Theory, An Introduction to Independence Proofs. North–Holland,1980.

[23] A. Louveau. Progres recents sur le probleme de Maharam d’apres N.J. Kaltonet J.W. Roberts. In G. C. et al., editor, Seminaire d’initiation a l’analyse,28eme annee, number 20, pages 01–08. 1983/84.

[24] D. Maharam. An algebraic characterization of measure algebras. Ann. of Math.(2), 48:154–167, 1947.

[25] R. D. Mauldin, editor. The Scottish Book. Birkhauser Boston, Mass., 1981.

[26] S. Quickert. CH and the Sacks property. Fund. Math., 171(1):93–100, 2002.

[27] S. Quickert. Forcing and the reals. PhD thesis, University of Bonn, 2002.

[28] J. Roberts. Maharam’s problem. In P. Kranz and I. Labuda, editors, Proceedingsof the Orlitz memorial conference. 1991. unpublished.

[29] S. Shelah. How special are Cohen and random forcings, i.e. Boolean algebrasof the family of subsets of reals modulo meagre or null. Israel J. Math., 88(1-3):159–174, 1994.

[30] S. Solecki. Analytic ideals and their applications. Annals of Pure and AppliedLogic, 99:51–72, 1999.

[31] M. Talagrand. Maharam’s problem. preprint, 31 pages, 2006.

[32] S. Todorcevic. A dichotomy for P-ideals of countable sets. FundamentaMathematicae, 166:251–267, 2000.

[33] S. Todorcevic. A problem of von Neumann and Maharam about algebrassupporting continuous submeasures. Fund. Math., 183(2):169–183, 2004.

26

Page 27: Maharam Algebras - IMJ-PRG équipe LMboban/pdf/Maharam-algebras.pdfMaharam Algebras Boban Veliˇckovi´c Equipe de Logique, Universit´e de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France

[34] B. Velickovic. CCC posets of perfect trees. Compositio Math., 79(3):279–294,1991.

[35] B. Velickovic. The basis problem for CCC posets. In Set theory (Piscataway,NJ, 1999), volume 58 of DIMACS Ser. Discrete Math. Theoret. Comput. Sci.,pages 149–160. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 2002.

[36] B. Velickovic. CCC forcings and splitting reals. Israel Journal of Mathematics,147:209–220, 2005.

27