30
Higher Order Thoughts Zoltán Dienes, Conscious and unconscious mental processes, 2006 David Rosenthal

Higher Order Thoughts

  • Upload
    morela

  • View
    39

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Higher Order Thoughts. David Rosenthal. Zolt án Dienes, Conscious and unconscious mental processes, 2006. Creature consciousness Awake, alert vs asleep, unconscious etc “Bill is conscious”. Creature consciousness Awake, alert vs asleep, unconscious etc “Bill is conscious” - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: Higher Order Thoughts

Higher Order Thoughts

Zoltán Dienes, Conscious and unconscious mental processes, 2006

David Rosenthal

Page 2: Higher Order Thoughts

Creature consciousness

Awake, alert vs asleep, unconscious etc

“Bill is conscious”

Page 3: Higher Order Thoughts

Creature consciousness

Awake, alert vs asleep, unconscious etc

“Bill is conscious”

Transitive consciousness

Has an object: “Bill is conscious of the noise” (or “aware of”)

You could be asleep – creature unconscious – and conscious of a noise.

Page 4: Higher Order Thoughts

Creature consciousness

Awake, alert vs asleep, unconscious etc

“Bill is conscious”

Transitive consciousness

Has an object: “Bill is conscious of the noise” (or “aware of”)

You could be asleep – creature unconscious – and conscious of a noise.

(Mental) State consciousness

A property of a mental state: A desire could be conscious or unconscious.

You could be asleep and have conscious mental states in your dreams.

A blindsight patient can be, in a sense, conscious of an object moving up, but the visual state is unconscious.

Page 5: Higher Order Thoughts

HIGHER-ORDER THOUGHT THEORY (Rosenthal, 1986, 2002) (see also Carruthers, 1992, 2000)

 

What makes a mental state a conscious mental state?

Central claim:

A conscious mental state is a mental state of which one is conscious.

i.e. state consciousness = transitive consciousness of the state

Seems hard to deny:

A blindsight patient honestly claims not be of conscious of seeing at all

That’s why it is natural to say their seeing is unconscious seeing

Page 6: Higher Order Thoughts

0) There can be unconscious mental states (thinking etc).

 

1) To be conscious of X, one must either perceive X or think about X. (I can see you being there, or I can close my eyes and think of you being there.)

 

2) To be conscious of being in a mental state, one must think that one is in that mental state

(i.e. have a second order thought: A thought about a thought).

(We can think of mental states; can we perceive them?)

Page 7: Higher Order Thoughts

3) A conscious mental state is a mental state of which one is conscious of being in. (The central claim.)

 

Therefore,

the necessary and sufficient condition for having a conscious mental state is to have a second order thought that you are in that mental state.

 

A thought with the content "there is an apple in front of me" is not a conscious mental state. (It is just a ‘first order thought’)

 

It is in virtue of the thought "I see that there is an apple in front of me" that the first order thought is a conscious thought.

Page 8: Higher Order Thoughts

A thought with the content “it is moving up"

makes you conscious of the object moving up

but not consciously aware of it moving up

(cf blindsight)

Being consciously aware of the object moving up requires you are conscious of the object moving up with a conscious mental state

the thought "I see that it is moving up" makes one consciously aware of the object moving up

(what a blindsight patient lacks)

Page 9: Higher Order Thoughts

“First order mental state”: A mental state about the world

Makes us conscious of the world

The world

Refers to

First order mental state

“The tree is green”

Page 10: Higher Order Thoughts

Second order thought makes us conscious of having the first order thought;

Makes us consciously aware of the tree being green

“The tree is green”

“The tree is green”

The world

Refers to

First-order mental state

“I see the tree is green”

Second-order mental state (higher order thought)

Refers to

Page 11: Higher Order Thoughts

Note, logically, the second order thought itself

“I see that the tree is green”

is not a conscious thought until one becomes conscious of it – by a third order thought

e.g. “I am aware that I am seeing that the tree is green”

It is the third order thought that makes one consciously aware (introspectively aware) that it is *me seeing*.

Page 12: Higher Order Thoughts

First order mental state

second order mental state

third order mental state

Unconscious mental state

Conscious mental state

Conscious of…

Or aware of…

Consciously aware of…

Introspectivelyaware of …

Page 13: Higher Order Thoughts

Counter arguments to Rosenthal’s theory

1. Does the theory rule out animals and young children being conscious?

Critic:

To think about being in mental states one needs to have concepts referring to mental states (not just referring to states of the world).

Children’s understanding of mental states develops dramatically

e.g. prior to age 3-4 they do not fully understand belief because they fail to understand false belief (Sally Anne task )

They do not understand mental states are representational.

Does that mean they cannot have higher order thoughts? Surely young children can be consciously aware??

Page 14: Higher Order Thoughts

Reply:

One does not need to understand mental states as representational in order to have some concept of a mental state

Adult’s understanding of mental states continues to develop, but we still at every point have some concept of a mental state

Children younger than 3-4 clearly have some concept of a mental state because they talk about mental states. They can use those concepts in their higher order thoughts.

Critic:

OK, but what about children younger than one year and animals? I find it hard to believe my dog does not have conscious mental states. At least, I do not want to rule that possibility out.

Page 15: Higher Order Thoughts

Reply:

One can have concepts without language.

All that is needed for a higher order thought is some concept or representation of a mental state.

Maybe all mammals, for example, have some concept or representation of (some) mental states (Rosenthal).

Page 16: Higher Order Thoughts

Maybe dogs do not have a full concept of ‘see’ nor of ‘I’,

but they may have a representation for ‘I-see-blue’ and a different one for ‘I-see-yellow’ etc.

They do not realise they are all cases of seeing, nor that when I am seeing blue, I am in the same type of state as you seeing blue. (These dog thoughts could be called ‘non-conceptual’.)

But still the dog could think it is in a certain state, hence render that state conscious.

One’s conscious experience would become more articulate and rich as one became better at conceptualising. (cf learning to taste wines.)

Page 17: Higher Order Thoughts

There need be no evolutionary magic moment when human-like conscious awareness suddenly appeared from nothing.

Maybe conscious experience gradually emerged as representations and concepts of mental states emerged in more and more fine grained ways.

We cannot rule out babies and many animals having HOTs!

Contrast:

Carruthers: It is ONLY when one understands mental states as representational that the right sort of higher order thoughts can be formed! Babies and animals are not consciously aware!

Page 18: Higher Order Thoughts

2. But we don’t seem to have HOTs all the time.

Reply:

By HOT theory, second order thoughts will only be conscious if you are conscious of having them (with third order thoughts).

Presumably we have third order thoughts a lot more rarely than second order thoughts.

Thus it follows from HOT theory that we will not be conscious of having second order thoughts most of the time.

Page 19: Higher Order Thoughts

3. Aren’t so many HOTs wasteful? Why would evolution bother?

Reply:

True, we don’t need to consciously see to act on the world. (cf Milner and Goodale – brain damaged people can be very bad at reporting how something looks, but act appropriately.)

So we must have acquired our rich repertoire of mental state concepts for reasons other than simple acting on the world.

Maybe we acquired so many concepts of mental states in order to explain and predict other people’s behaviour in our richly complex primate social structure?

(But why are humans in particular endowed with so rich mental state concepts? Many animals are intricately social.)

Page 20: Higher Order Thoughts

Maybe humans in particular have an extraordinary number of HOTs because of sexual selection (not because it was useful in any other way).

We evolved to be proficient in talking about mental states in order to chat each other up? (Miller, 2000)

An indicator of genetic fitness might be how elaborately one can wax lyrical about mental states in an original way! This takes an extravagant amount of resources, so people who can do it must be genetically fit.

Or maybe we have such rich mental state concepts because the selective pressure was to have rich concepts (for chatting people up). Richly articulated HOTs were just a by-product of this more general ability.

Page 21: Higher Order Thoughts

4.Why doesn’t thinking about a rock make it conscious?

According to HOT theory the higher order thought must be to the effect that you yourself are in a certain mental state.

Thinking about rocks does not satisfy the conditions the theory specifies.

NB: A second order thought ‘makes’ a first order state conscious, but not by causing it to ‘light up’/change its intrinsic properties.

A first order mental state’s being conscious just is there being a relevant second order thought.

Page 22: Higher Order Thoughts

5. Are not higher order thoughts just about introspective awareness? What if I am interested in conscious awareness itself, not the more higher level case of introspection?

Reply:

Introspection is being consciously aware of being in a mental state,

not being consciously aware of simply the world.

A second order thought makes one consciously aware of only the world.

Introspection requires a third order thought.

Thus, HOT theory is a theory of conscious awareness itself, not just of introspection.

Page 23: Higher Order Thoughts

6. But HOTs are conceptual and intellectual and conscious states are often fine-grained and qualitative? How can that be?

Many experiences, like visual ones, are qualitative, richly detailed in ways we lack concepts for. We can see a shade of red we have no word for and would in any case find hard to remember long enough to acquire a concept for.

Page 24: Higher Order Thoughts

6. But HOTs are conceptual and intellectual and conscious states are often fine-grained and qualitative? How can that be?

Many experiences, like visual ones, are qualitative, richly detailed in ways we lack concepts for. We can see a shade of red we have no word for and would in any case find hard to remember long enough to acquire a concept for.

Reply:

If you represent yourself as being in a fine grained qualitative state, it will seem like you are!

If you have a concept for a certain shade of red (call it reda), you can represent yourself as seeing a red slightly warmer, slightly more yellow, etc than reda. Thus you can represent yourself as seeing a certain fine grained qualitative property without having a concept for it as such.

Page 25: Higher Order Thoughts

7. But surely HOTs can misrepresent? What happens then?

Reply:

Yes, HOTs are just representations, just thoughts, so they can misrepresent.

They may represent that you are in a state you are not in!

It would consciously seem to you that you are in that state!

We will use this property of HOTs in explaining various psychological phenomena later in the course. This turns out to be a strength not a weakness of the theory.

Page 26: Higher Order Thoughts

8. But what are mental states? Doesn’t the theory beg the question about what mental states are?

Reply:

No one knows what makes mental states mental states. It is not a failing of HOT theory that there still remains much to be explained!

(see Edelman & Tononi (2001) A universe of consciousness. Basic books. Has some interesting ideas)

Page 27: Higher Order Thoughts

Variants of higher order theories:

1. Dispositional vs actual higher order states

Dispositional theory: If a mental state is accompanied by a disposition to have higher order thoughts about it, it is conscious (Carruthers, 1996).

Rosenthal: For a mental state to be conscious, there needs to be an actual existing (‘occurrent’) HOT

Page 28: Higher Order Thoughts

2. HOP vs HOT

Higher order perception theory: We can be conscious of mental states by perceiving that we are in them.

That may help explain how conscious mental states can be richly qualitative.

But do we have an organ for perceiving mental states? Do we need more than concepts in the higher order states to explain the richness of conscious mental experience? In any case, is there more than a terminological difference between the theories?

Perhaps the putative “Theory of Mind module” might be considered as a perceptual organ?

Page 29: Higher Order Thoughts

Contrasting theory:

First order representationalism:

A first order representation can be conscious if it has various properties like stability, distinctiveness, etc (e.g. O’Brien and Opie, 1999).

Violates the intuition of the central claim of higher order thought theory:

A conscious mental state is a mental state of which one is conscious.

If my visual system formed a stable distinctive representation controlling my actions, but I was not aware of seeing, it seems bizzare to say I consciously saw.

Page 30: Higher Order Thoughts

In this course we will look at the following unconscious mental states:

Memory: Can you use memory and not be aware you are doing so?

Perception: Can you perceive without being aware of perceiving?

Knowledge: Can you be using knowledge and not be aware of knowing?

Learning: How can you acquire unconscious knowledge?

Volition: Can you intend to think or behave in a certain way and not be aware of so intending?