6
http://sss.sagepub.com/ Social Studies of Science http://sss.sagepub.com/content/42/3/424 The online version of this article can be found at: DOI: 10.1177/0306312712437237 2012 42: 424 originally published online 2 April 2012 Social Studies of Science Peter Dear Structure Fifty years of Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com can be found at: Social Studies of Science Additional services and information for http://sss.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Email Alerts: http://sss.sagepub.com/subscriptions Subscriptions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Permissions: http://sss.sagepub.com/content/42/3/424.refs.html Citations: What is This? - Apr 2, 2012 OnlineFirst Version of Record - Jun 6, 2012 Version of Record >> at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014 sss.sagepub.com Downloaded from at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014 sss.sagepub.com Downloaded from

Fifty years of Structure

  • Upload
    p

  • View
    213

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Fifty years of Structure

http://sss.sagepub.com/Social Studies of Science

http://sss.sagepub.com/content/42/3/424The online version of this article can be found at:

 DOI: 10.1177/0306312712437237

2012 42: 424 originally published online 2 April 2012Social Studies of SciencePeter Dear

StructureFifty years of   

Published by:

http://www.sagepublications.com

can be found at:Social Studies of ScienceAdditional services and information for    

  http://sss.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

 

http://sss.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:  

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:  

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:  

http://sss.sagepub.com/content/42/3/424.refs.htmlCitations:  

What is This? 

- Apr 2, 2012OnlineFirst Version of Record  

- Jun 6, 2012Version of Record >>

at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014sss.sagepub.comDownloaded from at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014sss.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 2: Fifty years of Structure

Social Studies of Science42(3) 424 –428

© The Author(s) 2012Reprints and permission: sagepub.

co.uk/journalsPermissions.navDOI: 10.1177/0306312712437237

sss.sagepub.com

Fifty years of Structure

Peter DearCornell University, USA

Keywordshistory of science, incommensurability, paradigm, Thomas Kuhn

The 50 years that have passed since the publication of Kuhn’s (1962) Structure of Scientific Revolutions (SSR) seem less oppressive when I consider that I first read the copy that now sits before me (a pink second edition) nearly 35 years ago (Kuhn, 1970). At that time, it was de rigueur to read it in concert with Lakatos and Musgrave’s (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Its quasi-disciplinary home was History and Philosophy of Science, and its disciplinary antithesis was the philosophy of science, a well-established specialty within philosophy. This created some tension, for which Criticism became a canonical locus. Philosophers’ objections focused on the issues of incommensurability and relativism (Shapere, 1964 is characteristic). Kuhn’s disciplinary self-identification at the beginning of SSR, however, was not with philosophy: ‘History, if viewed as a repository for more than anecdote or chronology, could produce a decisive transformation in the image of science by which we are now possessed’ (Kuhn, 1970: 1). Historians of science (of the right sort) are the heroes, as they ‘have begun to ask new sorts of questions and to trace different, and often less than cumulative, developmental lines for the sciences’ (p. 3).

It seems odd, in retrospect, to realize that one of Kuhn’s ‘new’ historians was Alexandre Koyré, most famous for his Études galiléennes (Koyré, 1940). The oddness stems from what Steven Shapin later dubbed ‘post-Koyréan intellectualism’ (Shapin, 1980a: 110): Koyré soon became a watchword for an intellectualist history of scientific ideas that seemed the antithesis of the sociological vistas opened up by SSR. In this sense, however, Kuhn’s own sensibilities were perhaps precisely those of most historians of science in the 1960s and 1970s: ideas with a bit of social contextualization. Science studies, as it emerged in the 1970s and 1980s, made of Kuhn a quite different figure. In the vanguard of science studies, one of the most forthright uses of SSR was Barry Barnes’

Corresponding author:Peter Dear, Department of History, Cornell University, 435 McGraw Hall, Ithaca, NY 14853, USA. Email: [email protected]

437237 SSS42310.1177/0306312712437237DearSocial Studies of Science2012

at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014sss.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 3: Fifty years of Structure

Dear 425

T.S. Kuhn and Social Science (Barnes, 1982). Tellingly, this book was not only largely ignored by historians of science, but also by Kuhn himself: it receives no notice in Kuhn’s well-known 1991 Rothschild Lecture at Harvard (Kuhn, 2000), even as part of that essay’s generalized condemnation of Edinburgh Sociology of Scientific Knowledge (SSK). By that time it was too late; historians of science had been dragged into confron-tation with SSK as a post-Kuhnian historical enterprise thanks to the slightly delayed notoriety of Shapin and Schaffer’s Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Shapin and Schaffer, 2011 [1985]).1

The most obvious ‘application’ of SSR in historical studies, one flagged by Kuhn himself in the ‘Postscript’ to the second edition of SSR (Kuhn, 1970: 176), might be thought to be the identification and investigation of scientific communities. These are, after all, the social embodiments of a ‘paradigm’ in either of Kuhn’s clarified senses of ‘disciplinary matrix’ or ‘exemplar’ (getting down to cases confuses that mapping, of course). But surprisingly little work of this kind has actually been done by historians of science, and certainly not in an explicitly Kuhnian idiom. Instead, accounts of the sorts of things that Kuhn evidently saw as paradigm-communities in the broader sense – professional communities trained from the same textbooks – continued to be rather taken for granted by historians, even when they acknowledged their in-principle significance; if one 19th-century physicist had been trained in a different regime than that of another with whom he interacted, those different formations would typically be recognized through systematic differences in doctrine rather than by sociologically enunciated markers (bibliometrically, for example). Those many historians deserve to be let off the hook, though; Kuhn had provided them with little guidance. Even his distinction between the two kinds of paradigm provided little real sense of how big or small a paradigm com-munity might be, or when the disciplinary matrix might have shrunk to little more than a few internalized exemplars. In 1979 Kuhn showed his cards by leaving Princeton to become a philosopher at MIT. I think that historians of science had long, by then, tended to conceive of Kuhn’s significance in the terms that the philosophers (and Kuhn himself) had established as central: incommensurability and relativism. He was never really a guide to historical research except by association.

There are always exceptions, of course. Shapin’s (1980b) review in Isis of Gerald Geison’s Michael Foster and the Cambridge School of Physiology (Geison, 1978) skew-ered its author for never having mentioned Kuhn, despite the book’s focus on a research group, its structure and its commitments. (‘That’s because you’ve absorbed me so thor-oughly’, Kuhn was said by Geison to have commented wryly.2) Geison’s subsequent interest in related issues focused on ‘research schools’ rather than ‘paradigm communi-ties’ (Geison, 1981; Geison and Holmes, 1993), and had little to say about Kuhn’s work itself. Studies that focused on what might otherwise be described as the intellectual con-tent of a Kuhnian paradigm necessarily differed little from Koyréan historiography, one of Kuhn’s principal models.

Evidence from absence for SSR’s role in the history of science at this time may be represented by the decline of biography as a leading historiographical mode. ‘To under-stand why science develops as it does, one need not unravel the details of biography and personality that lead each individual to a particular choice, though that topic has vast fascination’, Kuhn carefully wrote in his Postscript (Kuhn, 1970: 200). It certainly seems

at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014sss.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 4: Fifty years of Structure

426 Social Studies of Science 42(3)

that in the 1970s and 1980s the stock of scholarly biography in the history of science had declined severely. Although books continued to appear that focused on aspects of indi-vidual figures, prefaces routinely took care to note that ‘this is not meant to be a biography’(see Geison, 1978: xiii). By contrast, the past 20 years have seen a resurgence in the respectability of biographical treatments in the history of science (among the very best examples of new historiographical departures being Porter [2004]). Nowadays, even scientific objects have biographies (Daston, 2000).

And what of SSR’s celebration of ‘the insulation of the scientific community from society’ (p. 164)? Kuhn saw this as a good thing, giving scientific enterprises their character and enabling their peculiar success. The implication that there is no society inside science, as well as the curious Cold War, Polanyi-esque ideal of isolated, privi-leged groups being shoveled massive funding from behind a curtain, surely created potential conflict between Kuhn and the concerns of emergent science studies (see, inter alia, Dear and Jasanoff, 2010). Only Kuhn, in his assaults on SSK, seems to have cared very much about this discord; most citations of his work in science studies long ignored it (cf. Fuller, 2000). What became dubbed, in the 1970s, the ‘social history of science’, especially associated at the time with the Department of History and Sociology of Science at the University of Pennsylvania, had very little interest in the detailed content of scientific knowledge, and in effect set itself at odds with Kuhn’s own central concerns (for example, Kohler, 1982).

In short, it is easy to downplay the importance of SSR for the history of science. The rarity of references to SSR in the historiography of science (as compared nowadays with those to Leviathan and the Air-Pump) make that apparent insignificance all the more plausible. Certainly, any historian who sits down to reread SSR will be struck by its almost archaic historiographical sensibilities: it really is based on Koyréan intellectual history, tricked out with a clever and beguiling structural model of science. The latter is clearly based on a dominant US Cold-War era ideology of science as a free and demo-cratic social institution, and elaborated with elements drawn from cognitive psychology and the later Wittgenstein. It is a product of the 1950s, and became enormously popular as part of the counter-cultural 1960s: Tolkien for physics students (see also Kaiser, 2011).

It remains alive today for a variety of reasons: in science studies, it holds a mythic status (witness this special section of the journal) as the intervention that brought down the dominance of logical empiricism in the philosophy of science and Mertonian func-tionalism in the sociology of science, thereby clearing the way for the revolution of the 1980s, with SSK, Donna Haraway, and Bruno Latour. More actively, however, SSR, and Kuhn’s work in general, has gained a surprising legitimacy in professional philosophy of science: books and articles on Kuhn by philosophers have appeared unremittingly during the past 20 years, and show no signs of dwindling: Kuhn is a part of the philosopher of science’s canon (dating between Hoyningen-Huene [1993] and Wray [2011]).

But if the history of science as a distinct discipline has only a questionable relation-ship to SSR, as an inquiry forming part of a broader science studies it surely owes SSR a great deal (I hold questions of historical causation temporarily in abeyance). The book made certain kinds of approaches in studying science permissible: if Kuhn could get away with something that looked in practice rather like relativism, then so might others. That revolution in the 1980s, involving both SSK and the US style of cultural studies, is

at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014sss.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 5: Fifty years of Structure

Dear 427

hard to imagine without SSR’s being embedded within it; furthermore, Kuhn overtly represented the book as one whose arguments and evidence were those of the historian.

Consequently, Bruno Latour’s (1987) Science in Action appeared originally in English for good reason: the anglophone science studies community, which had responded posi-tively (especially in Britain) to Laboratory Life (Latour and Woolgar, 1979), must by then have seemed the right environment for its epistemically irregular antics. The book appeared almost as if prepackaged to be a blockbuster of SSR dimensions, and historians of science knew to pick it up immediately (my copy is of the first hardcover issue, with its excessive typographical errors). A common response among historians was to inter-pret it as a realist backsliding from the constructivist Laboratory Life, due to the entry of Science in Action’s non-human actants and a justifiable overlooking of their less-than-evident semiotic grounding. Networks, albeit not true Actor Networks, also spurred some notice among historians, but on the whole Latour’s overturning of the epistemol-ogy/ontology distinction, if it was noticed, drummed up little interest.

Neither of these two prominent items in the canon of science studies is easy to evalu-ate for its long-term influence on the practice or findings of the historically oriented scholar – nor should it be, given that ‘influence’ explanations have been suspect among historians at least since Quentin Skinner’s work (Skinner, 1966). Anniversaries are occa-sions for celebration or remembrance. These books are certainly worth remembering; in practice, they’ve been celebrated for a long time.

Notes1. Shapin and Schaffer’s book seems to have received a fair degree of attention among literary

scholars before, around 1990, it began to be widely cited by historians of science. See the authors’ new introduction to the 2011 edition (Shapin and Schaffer, 2011).

2. Personal communication.

ReferencesBarnes B (1982) T.S. Kuhn and Social Science. London: Macmillan.Daston L (ed.) (2000) Biographies of Scientific Objects. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Dear P and Jasanoff S (2010) Dismantling boundaries in science and technology studies. Isis 101:

759–774.Fuller S (2000) Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Times. Chicago: University of

Chicago Press.Geison GL (1978) Michael Foster and the Cambridge School of Physiology: The Scientific

Enterprise in Late Victorian Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Geison GL (1981) Scientific change, emerging specialties, and research schools. History of

Science 19: 20–40.Geison GL and Holmes FL (eds) (1993) Research Schools: Historical Reappraisals. Osiris 8 (new

series). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Hoyningen-Huene P (1993) Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s Philosophy

of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Kaiser D (2011) How the Hippies Saved Physics: Science, Counterculture, and the Quantum

Revival. New York: Norton.

at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014sss.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Page 6: Fifty years of Structure

428 Social Studies of Science 42(3)

Kohler RE (1982) From Medical Chemistry to Biochemistry: The Making of a Biomedical Discipline. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Koyré A (1940) Études galiléennes. Paris: Hermann.Kuhn TS (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Kuhn TS (1970) Postscript –1969. In: Kuhn TS The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 174–210.Kuhn TS (2000) The Trouble with the Historical Philosophy of Science. In: Kuhn TS, The Road

Since Structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 105–120.Lakatos I and Musgrave A (eds) (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.Latour B (1987) Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society.

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Latour B and Woolgar S (1979) Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts.

London: Sage.Porter TM (2004) Karl Pearson: The Scientific Life in a Statistical Age. Princeton: Princeton

University Press.Shapere D (1964) The structure of scientific revolutions. Philosophical Review 73: 383–394.Shapin S (1980a) Social uses of science. In: Rousseau GS and Porter R (eds) The Ferment

of Knowledge: Studies in the Historiography of Eighteenth-Century Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 93–140.

Shapin S (1980b) Untitled review essay of Geison GL Michael Foster and the Cambridge School of Physiology. Isis 71: 146–149.

Shapin S and Schaffer S (2011 [1985]) Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Shapin S and Schaffer S (2011) Up for air: Leviathan and the Air-Pump a generation on. Introduc-tion to the 2011 Edition of Shapin S and Schaffer S Leviathan and the Air-Pump. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, xi–xl.

Skinner Q (1966) The limits of historical explanations. Philosophy 41: 199–215.Wray KB (2011) Kuhn’s Evolutionary Social Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Biographical notePeter Dear is Professor of History and of Science and Technology Studies at Cornell University.

at Harvard Libraries on June 19, 2014sss.sagepub.comDownloaded from