3

Click here to load reader

Commercial Surrogacy Commodification or Choice

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

commodification of the body

Citation preview

  • UTMJ Volume 84, Number 3, May 2007 177

    Introduction

    The advent of new reproductive technologies hasbrought unprecedented opportunities to infertile indi-viduals wishing to have children. Among these oppor-tunities is commercial surrogacy, whereby a woman is commis-sioned and paid a fee (above and beyond compensation) tocarry the fetus of another individual. After giving birth, thechild is delivered to the commissioning parent(s), who raisethe child as their own and hold all parental rights.1,2

    Commercial surrogacy is further subdivided into partial andfull surrogacy. In partial surrogacy, the surrogate is the geneticmother and provides the egg from which the child develops.Full surrogacy refers to arrangements in which the gametes areprovided by the commissioning parent(s) and the surrogateacts solely as a gestational host.2,3 The practice of commercialsurrogacy does bring with it several ethical concerns, however.Some have criticized the practice, comparing it to the com-modification, the transformation of a non-commodity into acommodity, not only of children, but also of the reproductivecapacities of women.4 Others have likened it to new-wave pros-titution.5 On the other hand, advocates of the practice havedefended it on the grounds that it is no different than spermdonation.6

    This review will analyze the controversy surrounding com-mercial surrogacy under the guidance of several ethical frame-works. It should be noted that commercial surrogacy is not thesame as non-commercial or altruistic surrogacy. In the latter,the surrogate is not paid for her services and is motivatedmainly by a desire to help an infertile couple have a child oftheir own.7

    CaseTo help navigate the ethical analysis of commercial surro-

    gacy, the following is a prototypical clinical case based looselyon the results of a study analyzing the characteristics of 44 sur-rogate pregnancies:8

    Mary, a 25-year-old female, is seeking to become a par-tial commercial surrogate. She is unmarried, with a two-year-old son. She has a high school education and a 10pack-year smoking history, but quit smoking one yearago. Presently, her only source of income is welfare. Herannual household income is approximately $23,000.She has consulted a surrogacy agency and met withFrank and Emma, the commissioning parents. Frankand Emma have an average household income of$400,000. Emma is unable to have children as a result ofa total abdominal hysterectomy with bilateral salpingo-oophorectomy (TAH-BSO) to treat Stage III ovariancancer. They have agreed to pay Mary $10,000 in addi-tion to any medical fees to be inseminated by Franks

    sperm and carry the child to term. Mary hopes that themonetary compensation from the surrogacy will helpimprove her financial situation. It offers an effectivemeans of income given her minimal education.Is it ethical for Mary to carry through with commercialsurrogacy?

    Deontological ArgumentThe commodification argument against surrogacy is deon-

    tological in principle. As outlined by Anderson, a commodity isdefined as a good or service that is governed by market normsthat regulate its production, exchange, and enjoyment.However, market norms may be objectionable if the produc-tion and distribution of a given good or service fail[s] to valueit in the appropriate way.4 Deontology, the ethical theory con-cerned with duties and rights, proposes a similar logic, statingthat it is unethical to treat beings worthy of respect merely asmeans to satisfy ones own interests or ends. Ultimately, com-mercial surrogacy commodifies both the reproductive capacityof the surrogate and the rights of the newborn child. As such,this practice fails to acknowledge these intrinsically valuablehuman beings and thus violates the deontological tenet ofrespect for persons. Van Niekerk & van Zyl further explore thenature of reproductive labour by stating:

    What distinguishes womens reproductive labour fromother forms of labour, [is] that the productis notsomething but someone...[A] persons relationship withmaterial things is instrumentalist; things are means to anend, but not ends in themselves. Peoples relationshipsto other people, and mothers relationships to theirinfants in particular, are manifestly different. Childrenare not means, but [rather] ends in the relationshipswith their mothers[and] mothers regard the relation-ship as a meaningful end in itself, and notas means tosome other end.3

    As such, in the case of Mary, the use of an unborn child asa means to subsequent financial gain, rather than accepting itas an end in itself, is in clear conflict with deontological inter-pretation.

    Deontologys second tenet requires the need for ethicalprinciples to be universalizable in asking an individual to actonly on that maxim through which [he/she] can at the sametime will that it should become a universal law.9 To investigatethe universalizability of commercial surrogacy, we may consid-er two hypothetical additions to Marys case:

    Consider the scenario where Mary has an annual house-hold income of $100,000. Given her new financial circum-stances, it is highly improbable that she would seek commercialsurrogacy as a means of further financial gain. Returning to

    FeaturesPhilosophy and Medicine

    Commercial Surrogacy: Commodification or Choice?

    Steven Orlov, B.Sc. (1T0), Faculty of Medicine, University of TorontoDavid Orlov, H.B.Sc. (0T9), Faculty of Medicine, University of Toronto

  • UTMJ Volume 84, Number 3, May 2007178

    universalizability, Marys contradictory actions are dependenton her financial situations, and are at odds with the ideal thatone should act by a universal standard, independent of cir-cumstance.

    Consider a situation in which all children are born via com-mercial surrogacy, as would be the case if it were a universal law.This construction is typical of most slippery slope arguments,which contend that the loosening of ethical standards may leadto social chaos.10 In a world of commercial surrogacy, it is feasi-ble to envision a distinct separation of classes in which the poorbear children for the rich. Such a society is remarkably similarto the fictional dystopia presented by Margaret Atwood in hernovel, The Handmaids Tale, in which Handmaids are fertilewomen whose social function is to bear children for the socialelite.11

    Both of the above scenarios suggest that commercial surro-gacy is in conflict with the deontological principle of universal-izability.

    The Role of AutonomyTo refute the ethical merit of commercial surrogacy, one

    must show reason to overrule a voluntary transaction betweencompetent adults. Indeed, several advocates of the practicehave raised the issue that a surrogates decision to carry a childis entirely voluntary, and thus overruling it would be a breachof her autonomy. Epstein explains that the basicpresump-tion should be set therefore in favour of voluntary exchange.12

    However, it should be noted that valid informed consentrequired for any medical procedure under the principle ofautonomyis far more rigorous than mere voluntariness2

    Consent can be given despite underlying covert duress or coer-cion, thus rendering the consent involuntary.13 In a well-devel-oped argument, Wilkinson introduces the concept of omissivecoercion to question the validity of consent in commercial sur-rogacy agreements. The theoretical framework is as follows: Aomissively coerces B to do X if and only if: (1) A has a duty todo Y for B; and (2) A proposes/threatens not to do Y for Bunless B does X.2 Applying this rubric to the practice of com-mercial surrogacy, with a largely egalitarian outlook on distrib-utive justice, a paid surrogate may be the victim of omissivecoercion if:

    The commissioning parents have a duty to help her[on charitable grounds] without demanding surrogacyservices, but propose (threaten) not to act in accor-dance with this duty unless she provides surrogacyservices.Society in generalhas a duty to ensure that she has a

    certain level of welfare, but makes it the case that shecan only reach this level of welfare by selling surrogacyservices.2

    The latter of these premises is founded on the ideal of thewelfarist assumption, wherein society has an obligation toensure that the prospective surrogateobtains a certain levelof welfare [or well-being].2 Reflecting on the case of Mary, theargument that she may be a victim of omissive coercion is asfollows:

    Based on the welfarist assumption, society is obliged to pro-vide Mary with a certain level of well-being (ie. greater than

    $23,000/year). Alternatively, given their financial prosperity($400,000/year), Frank and Emma have a duty to help Maryattain a higher level of welfare through charitable means.Either society or Frank and Emma threaten not to provideMary with the necessary level of welfare unless she acts as acommercial surrogate. Given the existence of such omissivecoercion, Marys consent to perform the commercial surroga-cy is invalid.

    Thus, the absence of valid informed consent in Marys deci-sion to undertake the surrogacy arrangement invalidates theprinciple of respect for autonomy. As such, commercial surro-gacy appears to contradict the assertions set forth by the ethi-cal framework of principalism.

    Utilitarian ViewThe case in support of commercial surrogacy has often

    been defended on utilitarian grounds. Under the greatest hap-piness principle, which is synonymous with the principle of util-ity, ethical decision making should be based on attaining thegreatest happiness of the greatest number.14 Accordingly, it isapparent how a successful commercial surrogacy agreementoffers benefits, i.e. happiness, to those involved. The followingare some potential benefits in the case of Mary: (1) Mary willbenefit financially by receiving $10,000 to help improve herquality of life; (2) Frank and Emma will benefit physically, psy-chologically, and emotionally, having overcome the obstaclesof infertility and acquiring a child genetically related to Frank;and (3) the unborn child will benefit by entering a lovinghome and being raised by parents who can provide him/herwith a high standard of life. However, these benefits must beviewed in light of several unconscionable and unquantifiablehuman costs. As presented by Anderson, most surrogatemothers experience grief upon giving up their childrenin 10percent of the cases, seriously enough to require therapy.Such grief is justifiable, considering that her labour is alienat-ed, because she must divert it from the end which the socialpractices of pregnancy rightly promotean emotional bondwith her child.4 Inevitably, the strong emotional connectionsexperienced by some surrogate mothers and the children towhom they give birth have led to numerous legal disputes overthe childrens custody.15 These events have prompted someindividuals, such as Prokopijevic, to suggest that:

    the surrogate mother might be allotted a certain peri-od of time in which she could change her mind andkeep the newly-born child, with corresponding com-pensation being paid to the [commissioning parents],including the expenses arising as a result of hospitalcare and the breaking of the contract.16

    However, such a resolution undermines the legitimacy ofthe pregnancy with respect to the commissioning parent(s).According to Van Niekerk and van Zyl, although the [com-missioning] female partner was not physically pregnant, [boththe surrogate and the commissioning parent(s) were]preg-nant in the social and psychological sense of expecting achild.3 To deny the commissioning parent(s) of their childwould cause the same alienation Prokopijevic was trying toremedy. Lastly, it should be noted that commercial surrogacymay have long-term implications for the children born from

    Features

    Philosophy and Medicine

    Commercial Surrogacy: Commodification or Choice?

  • UTMJ Volume 84, Number 3, May 2007 179

    these surrogacy agreements. In particular, Anderson arguesthat, given the nature of their birth, Would it be any wonderif a child born of a surrogacy agreement feared resale by par-ents? or that, children of some surrogate mothers [thoseborn without surrogacy agreements]express a sense of loss atbeing deprived of a sibling.4 Given these socially complex con-sequences, the utilitarian argument in favour of commercialsurrogacy requires a broader analysis of utility prior to deter-mining the correct course of action. In the case of Mary, the fol-lowing are some potential consequences: (1) Mary may, againsther will, be forced to give up the child with whom she sharesan emotional and genetic bond; (2) Frank and Emma mayexperience tremendous grief for the loss of the child shouldMary choose not to honour the surrogacy agreement; and (3)the unborn child may experience distress towards the parentalguardians, be it Mary or Frank and Emma, due to a fear ofbeing resold. Comparing these negative consequences to theaforementioned benefits of commercial surrogacy requiresone to perform the unimaginable task of quantifying emotion-al agony. Given that such quantification cannot be made onany universally agreed-upon grounds, the case for commercialsurrogacy based on utilitarian principles is questionable.

    Law and LegislationHaving considered the ethical implications of commercial

    surrogacy, it is worthwhile to examine the need for any neces-sary legal and legislative interventions. At the present time,Canadian laws concerning commercial surrogacy greatlyreflect the recommendations proposed by the RoyalCommission on the New Reproductive Technologies. As partof their review, the commission issued recommendation 199,which makes surrogacy a criminal offence, [and] directed thefederal government to legislate against it in the strongest pos-sible way:17

    to prohibit advertising for or acting as an intermediary tobring about a preconception (i.e. surrogacy) agreement, andto prohibit receiving payment or any financial or commercialbenefit for acting as an intermediary, under threat of criminalsanction. It should also legislate to prohibit making paymentfor a preconception arrangement, under threat of criminalsanction.18

    The commission further recommended that provincialbodies, particularly the Colleges of Physicians and Surgeons,adopt strict codes of conduct, disciplinary measures andsevere penaltiesagainst members involved in brokering orperforming assisted inseminationto facilitate a preconcep-tion (surrogacy) arrangement.18 However, despite being well-intentioned in protecting against surrogate exploitation andcondemning the unethical practice of commercial surrogacy,the commissions recommendations may have unforeseenimplication; chiefly, the legal prohibition of commercial surro-gacy may undermine the welfare of prospective surrogates.2

    This idea is based on the assumption that much of the motiva-tion to pursue commercial surrogacy comes as a result of finan-cial hardship. As such, the prohibition of commercial surroga-cy in the absence of alternative mechanisms to help ensure thewelfare of prospective surrogates, may encourage practices thatare more dangerous, exploitative, and morally objectionablethan the practice of commercial surrogacy.2 For this reason,members of government should consider alternative methods

    to improve the welfare of individuals who resort to commercialsurrogacy, prior to strictly forbidding it.

    ConclusionThe ethical implications of commercial surrogacy are ques-

    tionable on several grounds. (1) From a deontological per-spective, the use of an unborn child as a means to some otherend is unethical, as is the absence of universalizability in thepractice of commercial surrogacy. (2) Employing the welfaristassumption, commercial surrogates are omissively coerced intoparticipating in surrogacy agreements, thus rendering theirconsent invalid and their autonomy violated. (3) Furthermore,the negative emotional consequences that may arise from asurrogacy arrangement challenge the prevailing justification ofcommercial surrogacy on utilitarian grounds. However, despitethe unethical nature of commercial surrogacy, considerationshould be given to the existing laws prohibiting it, in order toensure the welfare of prospective surrogates.

    Returning to Marys case within the context of the abovediscussion, she should not proceed with the commercial surro-gacy agreement, for it cannot be sanctioned by ethical theories.

    AcknowledgementsThe authors would like to thank Dr. Kerry W. Bowman fromthe University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics for his crit-ical review of the manuscript.

    References1. Arneson RJ. Commodification and commercial surrogacy. Philos Public Aff.

    1992 Spring;21(2):132-64.2. Wilkinson S. The exploitation argument against commercial surrogacy.

    Bioethics. 2003 Apr;17(2):169-87.3. van Niekerk A, van Zyl L. The ethics of surrogacy: women's reproductive

    labour. J Med Ethics. 1995 Dec;21(6):345-9.4. Anderson ES. Is women's labor a commodity? Philos Public Aff. 1990

    Winter;19(1):71-92.5. Dworkin A. Right-wing women: the politics of domesticated females. London:

    Women's Press; 1983.6. Shalev C. Birth power: the case for surrogacy. New Haven: Yale University

    Press; 1989.7. Baker B. A case for permitting altruistic surrogacy. Hypatia. 1996

    Spring;11(2):34-48.8. Reame NE, Parker PJ. Surrogate pregnancy: clinical features of forty-four

    cases. Am J Obstet Gynecol. 1990 May;162(5):1220-5.9. Singer P. Practical ethics. 2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press; 1993.10. Herzog HA. Book review: The slippery slope to moral chaos: Line drawing

    and animal rights. Ethics & Behavior. 2005;15(2):191-4.11. Atwood ME. The handmaid's tale. Toronto: McClelland & Stewart; 1985.12. Epstein RA. Surrogacy: the case for full contractual enforcement. Va Law Rev.

    1995 Nov;81(8):2305-41.13. Freedman B. A moral theory of informed consent. Hastings Cent Rep. 1975

    Aug;5(4):32-9.14. Bentham J. An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation [micro-

    form]. London: Printed for T. Payne, and son, at the Mews gate; 1789.15. Faulkner E. The case of Baby M. Can J Women Law. 1989;3(1):239-45.16. Prokopijevic M. Surrogate motherhood. J Appl Philos. 1990;7(2):169-81.17. McCormack T. Reproductive technologies: Rights, choice, and coercion. In:

    Brodie J, editor. Women and Canadian Public Policy. Toronto: Harcourt Brace& Company; 1996. p. 199-221.

    18. Canada. Royal Commission on New Reproductive Technologies. Proceed withcare: final report of the Royal Commission on New ReproductiveTechnologies: summary and highlights. Ottawa: The Commission; 1993.

    Features

    Philosophy and Medicine

    Commercial Surrogacy: Commodification or Choice?