445
ART AS EXPERIENCE BY JOHN DEWEY A WTOEVTEW/PERIGEE BOOK

Art as Experience - John Dewey

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Art as Experience - John Dewey

ART AS

EXPERIENCE

BY JOHN

DEWEY

A WTOEVTEW/PERIGEE BOOK

Page 2: Art as Experience - John Dewey

Copyright © 1934, by John Dewey.All rights reserved.

SBN 399-50025-1

Perigee Booksare published by

G. P. Putnam's Sons200 Madison Avenue

New York, New York 10016

First PerigeePrinting, 1980

23rd Impression

Library of Congress CatalogCard Number: 58-59756

MANUFACTURED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA

Page 3: Art as Experience - John Dewey

TO ALBERT C. BARNES

IN GRATITUDE

Page 4: Art as Experience - John Dewey

PREFACE

IN THE winter and spring of 1031,1 was invited to give a seriesof ten lectures at Harvard University. The subject chosen wasthe Philosophy of Art; the lectures are the origin of the presentvolume. The Lectureship was founded in memory of WilliamJames and I esteem it a great honor to have this book associatedeven indirectlywith his distinguished name. It is a pleasure, also,te recall, in connection with the lectures, the unvarying kindnessand hospitality of my colleagues in the department of philosophyat Harvard.

I am somewhat embarrassed in an effort to acknowledgeindebtedness to other writers on the subject. Some aspects of itmay be inferred from authors mentioned or quoted in the text.I have read on the subject for many years, however, more orless widely in English literature, somewhat less in French andstill less in German, and I have absorbed much from sourceswhich I cannot now directly recall. Moreover, my obligations toa number of writers are much greater than might be gatheredfrom allusions to them in the volume itself.

My indebtedness to those who have helped me directlycan be more easily stated. Dr. Joseph Ratner gave me a numberof valuable references. Dr. Meyer Schapiro was good enough toread the twelfth and thirteenth chapters and to make suggestionswhich I have freely adopted. Irwin Edman read a large part ofthe book in manuscript and I owe much to his suggestions andcriticism. Sidney Hook read many of the chapters, and theirpresent form is largely the result of discussions with him; this

Page 5: Art as Experience - John Dewey

statement is especially true of the chapters on criticism and thelast chapter. My greatest indebtedness is to Dr. A. C. Barnes.The chaptershave been goneover one by one with him, and yetwhat I owe to his comments and suggestions on this account isbut a small measure of my debt. I have had the benefit of conversations with him through a period of years, many of whichoccurred in the presence of the unrivaled collection of pictureshe has assembled. The influenceof these conversations, togetherwith that of his books, has been a chief factor in shapingmy ownthinking about the philosophy of esthetics. Whatever is sound inthis volume is due more than I can say to the great educationalwork carried on in the Barnes Foundation. That work is of apioneer quality comparable to the best that has been done inany field during the present generation, that of science not excepted. I should be glad to think of this volume as one phaseofthe widespread influence the Foundation is exercising.

I am indebted to the Barnes Foundation for permission toreproduce a number of illustrations and to Barbara and WillardMorgan for the photographs from which the reproductions weremade.

J. D.

Page 6: Art as Experience - John Dewey

CONTENTS

PREFACE vii

I. THE LIVE CREATURE 3

n. THE LIVE CREATURE AND "ETHERIAL THINGS" 20

III. HAVING AN EXPERIENCE 35

IV. THE ACT OF EXPRESSION 5*

V. THE EXPRESSIVE OBJECT 82

VI. SUBSTANCE AND FORM xo6

Vn. THE NATURAL HISTORY OF FORM 134

VIII. THE ORGANIZATION OF ENERGIES 162

IX. THE COMMON SUBSTANCE OF THE ARTS 187

X. THE VARIED SUBSTANCE OF THE ARTS 214

XI. THE HUMAN CONTRIBUTION 24S

XII. THE CHALLENGE TO PHILOSOPHY 272

XIH. CRITICISM AND PERCEPTION 298

XIV. ART AND CIVILIZATION 3*5

INDEX 35i

Page 7: Art as Experience - John Dewey

ART AS EXPERIENCE

Page 8: Art as Experience - John Dewey

CHAPTER I

THE LIVE CREATURE

BY ONE of the ironic perversities that often attend the courseof affairs,the existenceof the works of art upon which forma

tion of an esthetic theory depends has become an obstruction totheory about them. Forone reason, theseworks are products thatexist externally and physically. In common conception, the workof art is often identified with the building, book, painting, orstatue in its existence apart from human experience. Since theactual workof art iswhatthe product does with andin experience,the resultis not favorable to understanding. In addition, the veryperfection of some of these products, the prestige they possessbecause of a long history of unquestioned admiration, createsconventions that get in the way of fresh insight. When an artproduct once attains classic status, it somehow becomes isolatedfrom the humanconditions under which it wasbroughtinto beingand from the human consequences it engenders in actual life-experience.

When artistic objects are separated from both conditionsof origin and operation in experience, a wall is built around themthat renders almost opaque their general significance, with whichesthetic theory deals. Art is remitted to a separate realm, whereit is cut off from that association with the materials and aims ofevery other form of human effort, undergoing, and achievement.A primary task is thus imposed upon one who undertakes to writeupon the philosophy of the fine arts. This task is to restore continuity between the refined and intensified forms of experiencethat areworks of art and the everyday events, doings, and sufferings that are universally recognized to constitute experience.Mountain peaks do not float unsupported; they do not even justrest upon the earth. They are the earth in one of its manifest operations. It is the business of those who are concerned with thetheory of the earth, geographersand geologists, to make this fact

Page 9: Art as Experience - John Dewey

4 ART AS EXPERIENCE

evident in its various implications., The theorist who would dealphilosophically with fine art has a like task to accomplish.

If one is willing to grant this position, even if only by wayof temporary experiment, he will see that there follows a conclusion at first sight surprising. In order to understand the meaningof artistic products, we have to forget them for a time, to turnaside from them and have recourse to the ordinary forces andconditionsof experience that we do not usually regardas esthetic.We must arrive at the theory of art by means of a detour. Fortheory is concerned with understanding, insight, not without exclamations of admiration, and stimulation of that emotional outburst often called appreciation.It is quite possible to enjoy flowersin their colored form and delicate fragrance without knowing anything about plants theoretically. But if one sets out to understandthe flowering of plants, he is committed to finding out somethingabout the interactions of soil, air, water and sunlight that condition the growth of plants.

By common consent, the Parthenon is a great work ofart. Yet it has esthetic standing only as the work becomes anexperience for a human being. And, if one is to go beyond personal enjoyment into the formation of a theory about that largerepublic of art of which the building is one member, one has tobe willing at some point in his reflections to turn from it to thebustling, arguing, acutely sensitive Athenian citizens, with civicsense identified with a civic religion, of whose experience thetemple was an expression, and who built it not as a work of artbut as a civic commemoration. The turning to them is as humanbeings who had needs that were a demand for the building andthat were carried to fulfillment in it; it is not an examinationsuch as might be carried on by a sociologist in search for materialrelevant to his purpose. The one who sets out to theorize aboutthe esthetic experience embodied in the Parthenon must realizein thought what the people into whose lives it entered had incommon, as creators and as those who were satisfied with it, withpeople in our own homes and on our own streets.

In order to understand the esthetic in its ultimate andapproved forms, one must begin with it in the raw; in the eventsand scenes that hold the attentive eye and ear of man, arousing his interest and affording him enjoyment as he looks and

Page 10: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE 5

listens: the sights that hold the crowd—the fire-engine rushingby; the machines excavating enormous holes in the earth; thehuman-fly climbing the steeple-side; the men perchedhigh in airon girders, throwing and catching red-hot bolts. The sources ofart in human experience will be learned by him who sees howthe tense grace of the ball-player infects the onlooking crowd;who notes the delight of the housewife in tending her plants, andthe intent interest of her goodman in tending the patch of greenin front of the house; the zest of the spectatorin poking the woodburning on the hearth and in watching the darting flames andcrumbling coals. These people, if questioned as to the reason fortheir actions, would doubtless return reasonable answers. Theman who poked the sticks of burning wood would say he did itto make the fire burn better; but he is nonethe less fascinated bythe colorfuldramaof changeenactedbefore his eyes and imaginatively partakes in it. He does not remain a cold spectator.WhatColeridge said of the reader of poetry is true in its way of all whoare happily absorbed in their activities of mind and body: "Thereader should be carried forward, not merely or chiefly by themechanical impulse of curiosity, not by a restless desire to arriveat the final solution, but by the pleasurable activity of the journeyitself."

The intelligent mechanic engaged in his job, interested indoing well and finding satisfaction in his handiwork, caring forhis materials and tools with genuine affection, is artistically engaged. The difference between such a worker and the inept andcarelessbungler is as great in the shop as it is in the studio. Oftentimes the product may not appeal to the esthetic sense of thosewho use the product. The fault, however, is oftentimes not somuch with the worker as with the conditions of the market forwhich his product is designed.Were conditions and opportunitiesdifferent, things as significant to the eye as those produced byearlier craftsmen would be made.

So extensive and subtly pervasive are the ideas that setArt upon a remote pedestal, that many a person would be repelledrather than pleased if told that he enjoyed his casual recreations,in part at least, because of their esthetic quality. The arts whichtoday have most vitality for the average person are things hedoes not take to be arts: for instance, the movie, jazzed music,

Page 11: Art as Experience - John Dewey

* ART AS EXPERIENCE

the comic strip, and, too frequently, newspaper accounts of love-nests, murders, and exploits of bandits. For, when what he knowsas art is relegated to the museum and gallery, the unconquerableimpulse towards experiences enjoyable in themselves finds suchoutlet as the daily environment provides. Many a person whoprotests against the museum conception of art, still shares thefallacy from which that conception springs. For the popularnotion comes from a separation of art from the objects and scenesof ordinary experience that many theorists and critics pridethemselves upon holding and even elaborating. The times whenselect and distinguished objects are closely connected with theproducts of usual vocations are the times when appreciation ofthe former is most rife and most keen. When, because of theirremoteness, the objects acknowledged by the cultivated to beworks of fine art seem anemic to the mass of people, esthetichunger is likely to seek the cheap and the vulgar.

The factors that have glorified fine art by setting it upona far-off pedestal did not arise within the realm of art nor istheir influence confined to the arts. For many persons an auraof mingled awe and unreality encompasses the "spiritual" andthe "ideal" while "matter" has become by contrast a term ofdepreciation, something to be explained away or apologized for.The forces at work are those that have removed religion as wellas fine art from the scope of the common or community life. Theforces have historically produced so many of the dislocations anddivisions of modern life and thought that art could not escapetheir influence. We do not have to travel to the ends of the earthnor return many millennia in time to find peoples for whom everything that intensifies the sense of immediate living is an objectof intense admiration. Bodily scarification, waving feathers, gaudyrobes, shining ornaments of gold and silver, of emerald and jade,formed the contents of esthetic arts, and, presumably, without thevulgarity of class exhibitionism that attends their analoguestoday.Domestic utensils, furnishings of tent and house, rugs, mats, jars,pots, bows, spears, were wrought with such delighted care thattoday we hunt them out and give them places of honor in ourart museums. Yet in their own time and place, such things wereenhancements of the processes of everyday life. Instead of beingelevated to a niche apart, they belongedto display of prowess, the

Page 12: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE 7

manifestation of group and clan membership, worship of gods,feasting and fasting, fighting, hunting, and all the rhythmiccrises that punctuate the stream of living.

Dancing and pantomime, the sources of the art of thetheater, flourished as part of religious rites and celebrations.Musical art abounded in the fingering of the stretched string, thebeating of the taut skin, the blowing with reeds. Even in the caves,human habitations were adorned with colored pictures that keptalive to the senses experiences with the animals that were soclosely bound with the lives of humans. Structures that housedtheir gods and the instrumentalities that facilitated commercewith the higher powers were wrought with especial fineness. Butthe arts of the drama, music, painting, and architecture thusexemplified had no peculiar connection with theaters, galleries,museums. They were part of the significant life of an organizedcommunity.

The collective life that was manifested in war, worship,the forum, knew no division between what was characteristic ofthese places and operations, and the arts that brought color,grace, and dignity, into them. Painting and sculpture were organically one with architecture, as that was one with the social purposethat buildings served. Music and song were intimate parts ofthe rites and ceremonies in which the meaning of group life wasconsummated. Drama was a vital reenactment of the legends andhistory of group life. Not even in Athens can such arts be tornloose from this setting in direct experience and yet retain theirsignificant character. Athletic sports, as well as drama, celebratedand enforced traditions of race and group, instructing the people,commemorating glories, and strengthening their civic pride.

Under such conditions, it is not surprising that theAthenian Greeks, when they came to reflect upon art, formedthe idea that it is an act of reproduction, or imitation. There aremany objections to this conception. But the vogue of the theoryis testimony to the close connection of the fine arts with dailylife; the idea would not have occurred to any one had art beenremote from the interests of life. For the doctrine did not signifythat art was a literal copying of objects, but that it reflected theemotions and ideas that are associated with the chief institutionsof social life. Plato felt this connection so strongly that it led him

Page 13: Art as Experience - John Dewey

8 ART AS EXPERIENCE

to his idea of the necessity of censorship of poets, dramatists, andmusicians. Perhaps he exaggerated when he said that a changefrom the Doric to the Lydian mode in music would be the sureprecursor of civic degeneration. But no contemporary would havedoubted that music was an integral part of the ethos and theinstitutions of the community. The idea of "art for art's sake"would not have been even understood.

There must then be historic reasons for the rise of thecompartmental conception of fine art. Our present museums andgalleries to which works of fine art are removed and stored illustrate some of the causes that have operated to segregate artinstead of finding it an attendant of temple, forum, and otherforms of associated life. An instructive history of modern artcould be written in terms of the formation of the distinctivelymodern institutions of museum and exhibition gallery. I maypoint to a few outstanding facts. Most European museums are,among other things, memorials of the rise of nationalism andimperialism. Every capital must have its own museum of painting, sculpture, etc., devoted in part to exhibiting the greatness ofits artistic past, and, in other part, to exhibiting the loot gatheredby its monarchsin conquestof other nations; for instance,the accumulations of the spoils of Napoleon that are in the Louvre. Theytestify to the connection between the modern segregation of artand nationalism and militarism. Doubtless this connection hasserved at times a useful purpose, as in the case of Japan, who,when she was in the process of westernization, saved much of herart treasures by nationalizing the temples that contained them.

The growth of capitalism has been a powerful influence inthe development of the museum as the proper home for works ofart, and in the promotion of the idea that they are apart from thecommon life. The nouveaux riches, who are an important byproduct of the capitalist system, have felt especially bound tosurround themselves with works of fine art which, being rare, arealso costly. Generally speaking, the typical collector is the typicalcapitalist. For evidence of good standing in the realm of higherculture, he amasses paintings, statuary, and artistic bijoux, as hisstocks and bonds certify to his standing in the economic world.

Not merely individuals, but communities and nations, puttheir cultural good taste in evidence by building opera houses,

Page 14: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE 9

galleries, and museums. These show that a community is notwholly absorbed in material wealth, because it is willing to spendits gains in patronage of art. It erects these buildings and collects their contents as it now builds a cathedral. These things reflect and establish superior cultural status, while their segregationfrom the common life reflects the fact that they are not part of anative and spontaneous culture. They are a kind of counterpartof a holier-than-thou attitude, exhibited not toward persons assuch but toward the interests and occupations that absorb mostof the community's time and energy.

Modern industry and commerce have an internationalscope. The contents of galleriesand museums testify to the growthof economic cosmopolitanism. The mobility of trade and of populations, due to the economic system, has weakened or destroyedthe connection between works of art and the genius loci of whichthey were once the natural expression. As works of art have losttheir indigenous status, they have acquired a new one—that ofbeing specimens of fine art and nothing else. Moreover, works ofart are now produced, like other articles, for sale in the market.Economic patronage by wealthy and powerful individuals has atmany times played a part in the encouragement of artistic production. Probably many a savage tribe had its Maecenas. Butnow even that much of intimate social connection is lost in theimpersonality of a world market. Objects that were in the pastvalid and significant because of their place in the life of a community now function in isolation from the conditions of theirorigin. By that fact they are also set apart from common experience, and serve as insignia of taste and certificates of specialculture.

Because of changes in industrial conditions the artist hasbeen pushed to one side from the main streams of active interest.Industry has been mechanized and an artist cannot work me*chanically for mass production. He is less integrated than formerly in the normal flow of social services. A peculiar esthetic"individualism" results. Artists find it incumbent upon them tobetake themselves to their work as an isolated means of "self-expression." In order not to cater to the trend of economic forces,they often feel obliged to exaggerate their separateness to thepoint of eccentricity. Consequently artistic products take on to a

Page 15: Art as Experience - John Dewey

10 ART AS EXPERIENCE

still greater degree the air of something independent and esoteric.Put the action of all such forces together, and the condi

tions that create the gulf which exists generally between producerand consumer in modern society operate to create also a chasmbetween ordinary and esthetic experience. Finally we have, as therecord of this chasm, accepted as if it were normal, the philosophiesof art that locate it in a region inhabited by no other creature,and that emphasize beyond all reason the merely contemplativecharacter of the esthetic. Confusion of values enters in to accentuate the separation. Adventitious matters, like the pleasure ofcollecting, of exhibiting, of ownership and display, simulateesthetic values. Criticism is affected. There is much applausefor the wonders of appreciation and the glories of the transcendent beauty of art indulged in without much regard to capacity for esthetic perception in the concrete.

My purpose, however, is not to engage in an economicinterpretation of the history of the arts, much less to argue thateconomic conditions are either invariably or directly relevant toperception and enjoyment, or even to interpretation of individualworks of art. It is to indicate that theories which isolate art andits appreciation by placing them in a realm of their own, disconnected from other modes of experiencing, are not inherent in thesubject-matter but arise because of specifiable extraneous conditions. Embedded as they are in institutions and in habits of life,these conditions operate effectively because they work so unconsciously. Then the theorist assumes they are embedded in thenature of things. Nevertheless, the influence of these conditionsis not confined to theory. As I have already indicated, it deeplyaffects the practice of living, driving away esthetic perceptionsthat are necessaryingredients of happiness, or reducing them tothe level of compensating transient pleasurable excitations.

Even to readers who are adversely inclined to what hasbeen said, the implications of the statements that have beenmade may be useful in defining the nature of the problem: thatof recovering the continuity of esthetic experience with normalprocesses of living. The understanding of art and of its rdle incivilization is not furthered by setting out with eulogies of itnor by occupying ourselves exclusively at the outset with greatworks of art recognized assuch. The comprehension which theory

Page 16: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE II

essays will be arrived at by a detour; by going back to experience of the common or mill run of things to discover the estheticquality such experience possesses. Theory can start with andfrom acknowledged works of art only when the esthetic is alreadycompartmentalized, or only when works of art are set in a nicheapart instead of being celebrations, recognized as such, of thethings of ordinary experience. Even a crude experience, if authentically an experience, is more fit to give a clue to the intrinsicnature of esthetic experience than is an object already set apartfrom any other mode of experience. Following this clue we candiscover how the work of art develops and accentuates what ischaracteristically valuable in things of everyday enjoyment. Theart product will then be seen to issue from the latter, when thefull meaning of ordinary experience is expressed, as dyes comeout of coal tar products when they receive special treatment.

Many theories about art already exist. If there is justifica*tion for proposing yet another philosophy of the esthetic, it mustbe found in a new mode of approach. Combinations and permutations among existing theories can easily be brought forth by thoseso inclined. But, to my mind, the trouble with existing theoriesis that they start from a ready-made compartmentalization, orfrom a conception of art that "spiritualizes" it out of connectionwith the objects of concrete experience. The alternative, however,to such spiritualization is not a degrading and Philistinish materialization of works of fine art, but a conception that disclosesthe way in which these works idealize qualities found in commonexperience.Were works of art placed in a directly human contextin popular esteem, they would have a much wider appeal thanthey can have when pigeon-hole theories of art win generalacceptance.

A conception of fine art that sets out from its connectionwith discovered qualities of ordinary experience will be ableto indicate the factors and forces that favor the normal development of common human activities into matters of artisticvalue. It will also be able to point out those conditions that arrestits normal growth. Writers on esthetic theory often raise thequestion of whether esthetic philosophy can aid in cultivation ofesthetic appreciation. The question is a branch of the generaltheory of criticism, which, it seems to me, fails to accomplish

Page 17: Art as Experience - John Dewey

12 ART AS EXPERIENCE

its full office if it does not indicate what to look for and what tofind in concrete esthetic objects. But, in any case, it is safe tosay that a philosophy of art is sterilized unless it makesus awareof the function of art in relation to other modes of experience,and unless it indicates why this function is so inadequatelyrealized, and unless it suggests the conditions under which theoffice would be successfully performed.

The comparison of the emergence of works of art out ofordinary experiences to the refining of raw materials intovaluableproducts may seem to some unworthy, if not an actual attemptto reduce works of art to the status of articles manufactured forcommercial purposes. The point, however, is that no amount ofecstatic eulogy of finished works can of itself assist the understanding or the generation of suchworks. Flowers canbe enjoyedwithout knowing about the interactions of soil, air, moisture,and seedsof which they are the result. But they cannot be understood without taking just these interactions into account—andtheory is a matter of understanding. Theory is concerned withdiscovering the nature of the production of works of art and oftheir enjoyment in perception. How is it that the everydaymakingof things grows into that form of making which is genuinelyartistic? How is it that our everyday enjoyment of scenes andsituations develops into the peculiar satisfaction that attends theexperience which is emphatically esthetic? These are the questions theory must answer. The answers cannot be found, unlesswe are willing to find the germs and roots in matters of experience that we do not currently regard as esthetic. Having discovered these active seeds, we may follow the course of theirgrowth into the highest forms of finished and refined art.

It is a commonplace that we cannot direct, save accidentally, the growth and flowering of plants, however lovely andenjoyed, without understandingtheir causal conditions. It shouldbe just a commonplace that esthetic understanding—as distinctfrom sheer personal enjoyment—must start with the soil, air, andlight out of which things esthetically admirable arise. And theseconditions are the conditions and factors that make an ordinaryexperience complete. The more we recognize this fact, the morewe shall find ourselves faced with a problem rather than witha final solution. // artistic and esthetic quality is implicit in every

Page 18: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE 13

normal experience, how shall we explain how and why it so generally fails to become explicit? Why is it that to multitudes artseemsto be an importation into experience froma foreign countryand the esthetic to be a synonym for something artificial?

WE cannot answer these questions any more than we can tracethe development of art out of everyday experience, unless wehave a clear and coherent idea of what is meant when we say"normal experience." Fortunately, the road to arriving at suchan idea is open and well marked. The nature of experience isdetermined by the essential conditions of life. While man is otherthan bird and beast, he shares basic vital functions with them andhas to make the same basal adjustments if he is to continue theprocess of living. Having the same vital needs, man derives themeans by which he breathes, moves, looks and listens, the verybrainwith which he coordinates his senses and his movements,from his animal forbears. The organs with which he maintainshimself in being are not of himself alone, but by the grace ofstruggles and achievements of a long line of animal ancestry.

Fortunately a theoryof the place of the esthetic in experience does not have to lose itself in minute details when it startswith experience in its elemental form. Broad outlines suffice. Thefirst great consideration is that life goes on in an environment;not merely in it but because of it, through interaction with it. Nocreature lives merely under its skin; its subcutaneous organs aremeans of connection with what lies beyond its bodily frame, andto which, in order to live, it must adjust itself, by accommodationand defense but also by conquest. At every moment, the livingcreature is exposed to dangers from its surroundings, andat everymoment, it must draw upon something in its surroundings tosatisfy its needs. The career and destiny of a living being arebound up with its interchanges with its environment, not externally but in the most intimate way.

The growl of a dog crouching over his food, his howl intime of loss and loneliness, the wagging of his tail at the returnof his human friend are expressions of the implication of a living in a natural medium which includes man along with the animal he has domesticated. Every need, say hunger for fresh air

Page 19: Art as Experience - John Dewey

14 ART AS EXPERIENCE

or food, is a lack that denotes at least a temporary absence ofadequate adjustment with surroundings. But it is also a demand,a reaching out into the environment to make good the lack and torestore adjustment by building at least a temporary equilibrium.Life itself consists of phases in which the organism falls out ofstep with the march of surrounding things and then recoversunison with it—either through effort or by some happy chance.And, in a growing life, the recovery is never mere return to aprior state, for it is enriched by the state of disparity and resistance through which it has successfully passed. If the gap between organism and environment is too wide, the creature dies.If its activity is not enhanced by the temporary alienation, itmerely subsists. Life grows when a temporary falling out is atransition to a more extensive balance of the energies of the organism with those of the conditions under which it lives.

These biological commonplaces are something more thanthat; they reach to the roots of the esthetic in experience. Theworld is full of things that are indifferent and even hostile to life;the very processes by which life is maintained tend to throw itout of gear with its surroundings. Nevertheless, if life continuesand if in continuing it expands, there is an overcoming of factorsof opposition and conflict; there is a transformation of theminto differentiated aspects of a higher powered and more significant life. The marvel of organic, of vital, adaptation through expansion (instead of by contraction and passive accommodation)actually takes place. Here in germ are balance and harmony attained through rhythm. Equilibrium comes about not mechanicallyand inertly but out of, and because of, tension.

There is in nature, even below the level of life, somethingmore than mere flux and change. Form is arrived at whenever astable, even though moving, equilibrium is reached. Changes interlock and sustain one another. Wherever there is this coherencethere is endurance. Order is not imposed from without but ismade out of the relations of harmonious interactions that energiesbear to one another. Because it is active (not anything static because foreign to what goes on) order itself develops. It comesto include within its balanced movement a greater variety ofchanges.

Order cannot but be admirable in a world constantly

Page 20: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE 15

threatened with disorder—in a world where living creatures cango on living only by taking advantage of whatever order existsabout them, incorporating it into themselves. In a world like ours,every living creature that attains sensibility welcomes order witha response of harmonious feeling whenever it finds a congruousorder about it.

For only when an organism shares in the ordered relations of its environment does it secure the stability essential toliving. And when the participation comes after a phase of disruption and conflict, it bears within itself the germs of a consummation akin to the esthetic.

The rhythm of loss of integration with environment andrecovery of union not only persists in man but becomes consciouswith him; its conditions are material out of which he forms purposes. Emotion is the conscious sign of a break, actual or impending. The discord is the occasion that induces reflection.Desire for restoration of the union converts mere emotion intointerest in objects as conditions of realization of harmony. Withthe realization, material of reflection is incorporated into objectsas their meaning. Since the artist cares in a peculiar way for thephase of experience in which union is achieved, he does not shunmoments of resistance and tension. He rather cultivates them, notfor their own sake but because of their potentialities, bringing toliving consciousness an experience that is unified and total. Incontrast with the person whose purpose is esthetic, the scientificman is interested in problems, in situations wherein tension between the matter of observation and of thought is marked. Ofcourse he cares for their resolution. But he does not rest in it;he passes on to another problem using an attained solution onlyas a stepping stone from which to set on foot further inquiries.

The difference between the esthetic and the intellectual isthus one of the place where emphasis falls in the constant rhythmthat marks the interaction of the live creature with his surroundings. The ultimate matter of both emphases in experience is thesame, as is also their general form. The odd notion that an artistdoes not think and a scientific inquirer does nothing else is theresult of converting a difference of tempo and emphasis into adifference in kind. The thinker has his esthetic moment whenhis ideas cease to be mere ideas and become the corporate mean-

Page 21: Art as Experience - John Dewey

16 ART AS EXPERIENCE

ings of objects. The artist has his problems and thinks as heworks. But his thought is moreimmediately embodied in the object. Becauseof the comparative remoteness of his end, the scientific workeroperates with symbols,wordsandmathematical signs.The artist does his thinking in the very qualitative media heworks in, and the terms lie so dose to the object that he is producing that they merge directly into it.

The live animal does not have to project emotions intothe objects experienced. Nature is kind and hateful, bland andmorose, irritating and comforting, longbefore she is mathematically qualified or even a congeries of "secondary" qualities likecolorsand their shapes. Even suchwordsas long and short, solidand hollow, still carry to all,but thosewhoare intellectually specialized, a moral and emotional connotation. The dictionary willinform any one who consults it that the early use of words likesweet and bitter was not to denote qualities of sense as such butto discriminate things as favorable and hostile. How could it beotherwise? Directexperience comes fromnatureandman interacting with eachother. In this interaction, humanenergygathers, isreleased, dammed up, frustrated and victorious. There are rhythmic beats of want and fulfillment, pulses of doing and beingwithheld from doing.

All interactions that effect stability and order in the whirling flux of changeare rhythms. There is ebb and flow, systole anddiastole! ordered change. The latter moves within bounds. Tooverpass the limits that are set is destruction and death, out ofwhich, however, new rhythms are built up. The proportionateinterceptionof changes establishes an order that is spatially, notmerely temporally patterned: like the waves of the sea, the ripples of sand wherewaves have flowed back and forth, the fleecyand the black-bottomed cloud. Contrast of lack and fullness, ofstruggle and achievement, of adjustment after consummated irregularity, form the drama in which action, feeling, and meaningare one. The outcome is balance and counterbalance. These arenot static nor mechanical. They express power that is intensebecause measured through overcoming resistance. Environing objects avail and countervail.

There are two sorts of possible worlds in which estheticexperience would not occur. In a world of mere flux, change

Page 22: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE 17

would not be cumulative; it would not move toward a close.Stability and rest would have no being. Equally is it true, however, that a world that is finished, ended, would have no traitsof suspenseand crisis, and wouldoffer no opportunity for resolution. Where everything is already complete, there is no fulfillment. We envisagewith pleasure Nirvana and a uniform heavenlybliss only because they are projected upon the background of ourpresent world of stress and conflict. Because the actual world,that in which we live, is a combination of movement and culmination, of breaks and re-unions, the experience of a livingcreature is capableof esthetic quality. The live being recurrentlyloses and reestablishes equilibrium with his surroundings. Themoment of passage from disturbance into harmony is that ofintensest life. In a finished world, sleep and waking could not bedistinguished. In one wholly perturbed, conditions could not evenbe struggled with. In a world made after the pattern of ours,moments of fulfillment punctuate experience with rhythmicallyenjoyed intervals.

Inner harmony is attained only when, by some means,terms are made with the environment. When it occurs on anyother than an "objective" basis, it is illusory—in extreme casesto the point of insanity. Fortunately for variety in experience,terms aremade in many ways—waysultimately decidedby selective interest. Pleasures may come about through chance contactand stimulation; such pleasures are not to be despised in a worldfull of pain. But happiness and delight are a different sort ofthing. They come to be through a fulfillment that reaches to thedepths of our being—one that is an adjustment of our wholebeingwith the conditions of existence. In the process of living,attainment of a period of equilibrium is at the same time theinitiationof a new relation to the environment, one that bringswith it potencyof new adjustments to be made through struggle.The time of consummation is also one of beginning anew. Anyattempt to perpetuate beyond its term the enjoyment attendingthe time of fulfillment and harmony constitutes withdrawal fromthe world. Hence it marks the lowering and loss of vitality. But,through the phases of perturbation and conflict, there abides thedeep-seated memory of an underlying harmony, the sense ofwhich haunts life like the sense of being founded on a rock.

Page 23: Art as Experience - John Dewey

18 ART AS EXPERIENCE

Most mortals are conscious that a split often occurs between their present living and their past and future. Then thepast hangs upon them as a burden; it invades the present with asense of regret, of opportunities not used, and of consequenceswe wish undone. It rests upon the present as an oppression, instead of being a storehouse of resources by which to move confidently forward. But the live creature adopts its past; it canmake friends with even its stupidities, using them as warningsthat increase present wariness. Instead of trying to live uponwhatever may have been achieved in the past, it uses past successes to inform the present. Every living experience owes itsrichness to what Santayana well calls "hushed reverberations." *

To the being fully alive, the future is not ominous but apromise; it surrounds the present as a halo. It consists of possibilities that are felt as a possession of what is now and here.In life that is truly life, everything overlaps and merges.But all too often we exist in apprehensions of what the futuremay bring, and are divided within ourselves. Even when notoveranxious,we do not enjoy the present becausewe subordinateit to that which is absent. Because of the frequency of this abandonment of the present to the past and future, the happy periodsof an experiencethat is now completebecauseit absorbs into itselfmemories of the past and anticipationsof the future, come to constitute an esthetic ideal. Only when the past ceases to troubleand anticipations of the futurearenot perturbing is a beingwhollyunited with his environment and therefore fully alive. Art celebrates with peculiar intensity the moments in which the pastreenforces the present and in which the future is a quickeningof what now is.

To grasp the sourcesof esthetic experience it is, therefore,necessary to have recourse to animal life below the human scale.

* "These familiar flowers, these well-remembered bird notes, this skywith its fitful brightness, these furrowed and grassy fields, each with a sort ofpersonality given to it by the capricious hedge, such things as these are themother tongue of our imagination, the language that is laden with all thesubtle inextricable associations the fleeting hours of our childhood left behindthem. Our delight in the sunshine on the deep-bladedgrass today might be nomore than the faint perception of wearied souls, if it were not for the sunshine and grass of far-off years, which still live in us and transform our perception into love." GeorgeEliot in "The Mill on the Floss."

Page 24: Art as Experience - John Dewey

THE LIVE CREATURE 19

The activities of the fox, the dog, and the thrush may at leaststand as reminders and symbols of that unity of experience whichwe so fractionize when work is labor, and thought withdraws usfrom the world. The live animal is fully present, all there, in allof its actions: in its wary glances, its sharp sniffings, its abruptcocking of ears. All senses are equally on the qui vive. As youwatch, you see motion merging into sense and sense into motion—constituting that animal grace so hard for man to rival. Whatthe live creature retains from the past and what it expects fromthe future operate as directions in the present. The dog is neverpedantic nor academic; for these things ariseonly when the pastis severed in consciousness from the present and is set up as amodel to copy or a storehouse upon which to draw. The pastabsorbed into the present carries on; it presses forward.

There is much in the life of the savage that is sodden. But,when the savage is most alive, he is most observant of the worldabout him and most taut with energy. As he watches what stirsabout him, he, too, is stirred. His observation is both action inpreparation and foresight of the future. He is as active throughhis whole being when he looks and listens as when he stalks hisquarry or stealthilyretreats from a foe. His senses are sentinelsof immediate thought and outposts of action, and not, as they sooften are with us, mere pathways along which material is gathered to be stored away for a delayed and remote possibility.

It is mere ignorance that leads then to the suppositionthat connection of art and esthetic perception with experiencesignifies a lowering of their significance and dignity. Experiencein the degree in which it is experience is heightened vitality.Instead of signifying being shut up within one's own pri/ate feelings and sensations, it signifies active and alert commerce withthe world; at its height it signifies complete interpenetration ofself and the world of objects and events. Instead of signifyingsurrender to caprice and disorder, it affordsour sole demonstration of a stability that is not stagnation but is rhythmic and developing. Because experience is the fulfillment of an organismin its strugglesand achievements in a world of things, it is art ingerm. Even in its rudimentary forms, it contains the promiseof that delightful perception which is esthetic experience.

Page 25: Art as Experience - John Dewey

CHAPTER II

THE LIVE CREATURE AND"ETHERIAL THINGS"*

WHY IS the attempt to connect the higher and ideal thingsof experience with basic vital roots so often regarded as

betrayal of their nature and denial of their value? Why is thererepulsion when the high achievements of fine art are broughtinto connection with common life, the life that we share with allliving creatures? Why is life thought of as an affair of lowappetite, or at its best a thing of gross sensation, and ready tosink from its best to the level of lust and harsh cruelty? A complete answer to the question would involve the writing of a historyof morals that would set forth the conditions that have broughtabout contempt for the body, fear of the senses, and the opposition of flesh to spirit.

One aspect of this history is so relevant to our problemthat it must receive at least passing notice. The institutional lifeof mankind is marked by disorganization. This disorder is oftendisguised by the fact that it takes the form of static division intoclasses, and this static separation is accepted as the very essenceof order as long as it is so fixed and so accepted as not to generate open conflict. Life is compartmentalized and the institutionalized compartments are classified as high and as low; theirvalues as profane and spiritual, as material and ideal. Interestsare related to one another externally and mechanically, througha system of checks and balances. Since religion, morals, politics,business has each its own compartment, within which it is fittingeach should remain, art, too, must have its peculiar and privaterealm. Compartmentalization of occupations and interests bringsabout separation of that mode of activity commonly called "prac-

*The Sun, the Moon, the Earth and its contents, are material to formgreater things, that is, etherial things—greater things than the Creator himself made.—John Keats.

20

Page 26: Art as Experience - John Dewey

"ETHERIAL THINGS" 21

tice" from insight, of imagination from executive doing, of significantpurpose from work, of emotion from thought and doing.Each of these has, too, its own place in which it must abide.Those who write the anatomy of experience then suppose thatthese divisions inhere in the very constitution of human nature.

Of much of our experience as it is actually lived underpresent economic and legal institutional conditions, it is only tootrue that these separations hold. Only occasionally in the livesof many are the senses fraught with the sentiment that comesfrom deep realization of intrinsic meanings. We undergo sensations as mechanical stimuli or as irritated stimulations, withouthaving a sense of the reality that is in them and behind them: inmuch of our experience our different senses do not unite to tell acommon and enlarged story. We see without feeling; we hear,but only a second-hand report, second hand because not reen-forced by vision. We touch, but the contact remains tangentialbecause it does not fuse with qualities of senses that go belowthe surface. We use the senses to arouse passion but not to fulfillthe interest of insight, not because that interest is not potentiallypresent in the exercise of sense but because we yield to conditions of living that force sense to remain an excitation on thesurface. Prestige goes to those, who use their minds without participation of the body and who act vicariously through control ofthe bodies and labor of others.

Under such conditions, sense and flesh get a bad name.The moralist, however, has a truer sense of the intimate connections of sense with the rest of our being than has the professionalpsychologist and philosopher, although his sense of these connections takes a direction that reverses the potential facts of ourliving in relation to the environment. Psychologist and philosopher have in recent times been so obsessed with the problem ofknowledge that they have treated "sensations" as mere elementsof knowledge. The moralist knows that sense is allied with emotion, impulse and appetition. So he denounces the lust of the eyeas part of the surrenderof spirit to flesh. He identifies the sensuous with the sensual and the sensual with the lewd. His moraltheory is askew, but at least he is aware that the eye is not animperfect telescope designed for intellectual reception of materialto bring about knowledge of distant objects.

Page 27: Art as Experience - John Dewey

22 ART AS EXPERIENCE

"Sense" covers a wide range of contents: the sensory, thesensational, the sensitive, the sensible, and the sentimental, alongwith the sensuous. It includes almost everything from bare physical and emotional shock to sense itself—that is, the meaning ofthings present in immediate experience. Each term refers to somereal phase and aspect of the life of an organic creature as lifeoccurs through sense organs. But sense, as meaning so directlyembodied in experience as to be its own illuminated meaning,is the only signification that expresses the function of senseorganswhen they are carriedto full realization. The sensesare the organsthrough which the live creature participates directly in the ongoings of the world about him. In thb participation the variedwonder and splendor of this world are made actual for him in thequalitieshe experiences. This material cannot be opposed to action, formotorapparatus and"will" itself arethe meansby whichthis participation is carried onanddirected. It cannot be opposedto "intellect," for mind is the means by which participation isrendered fruitful through sense; by which meanings and valuesare extracted, retained, and put to further service in the inter*courseof the live creature with his surroundings.

Experience is the result, the sign, and the reward of thatinteraction of organism and environment which, when it is carried to the full, is a transformation of interaction into participation and communication. Since sense-organs with their connectedmotor apparatus are the means of this participation, any andevery derogation of them, whether practical or theoretical, is atonce effect and cause of a narrowed and dulled life-experience.Oppositionsof mind and body, soul and matter, spirit and fleshall have their origin, fundamentally, in fear of what life maybring forth. They are marks of contraction and withdrawal. Fullrecognition, therefore, of the continuity of the organs,needs andbasic impulses of the human creature with his animal forbears,implies no necessary reduction of man to the level of the brutes.On the contrary, it makes possible the drawing of a ground-planof human experience upon which is erected the superstructure ofman's marvelous and distinguishing experience. What is distinctive in man makes it possible for him to sink below the level ofthe beasts. It alsomakes it possible for him to carry to new andunprecedented heights that unity of sense and impulse, of brain

Page 28: Art as Experience - John Dewey

"ETHERIAL THINGS" 23

and eye and ear, that is exemplified in animal life, saturating itwith the conscious meanings derived from communication anddeliberate expression.

Man excels in complexity and minuteness of differentiations. This very fact constitutes the necessity for many morecomprehensive and exact relationships among the constituents ofhis being. Important as are the distinctions and relations thusmade possible, the story does not end here. There are more opportunities for resistance and tension, more drafts upon experimentation and invention, and therefore more novelty in action,greater range and depth of insight and increase of poignancy infeeling. As an organism increases in complexity, the rhythms ofstruggle and consummation in its relation to its environment arevaried and prolonged, and they come to include within themselves an endless variety of sub-rhythms. The designs of livingare widened and enriched. Fulfillment is more massive and moresubtly shaded.

Space thus becomes something more than a void in whichto roam about, dotted here and there with dangerous thingsand things that satisfy the appetite. It becomes a comprehensiveand enclosed scene within which are ordered the multiplicity ofdoings and undergoings in which man engages. Time ceases to beeither the endless and uniform flow or the succession of instantaneous points which some philosophers have asserted it to be.It, too, is the organized and organizing medium of the rhythmicebb and flow of expectant impulse, forward and retracted movement, resistance and suspense, with fulfillment and consummation. It is an ordering of growth and maturations—as James said,we learn to skate in summer after having commenced in winter.Time as organization in change is growth, and growth signifiesthat a varied series of change enters upon intervals of pause andrest; of completions that become the initial points of new processes of development. Like the soil, mind is fertilized while it liesfallow, until a new burst of bloom ensues.

When a flash of lightning illumines a dark landscape, thereis a momentary recognition of objects. But the recognition is notitself a mere point in time. It is the focal culmination of long,slow processes of maturation. It is the manifestation of the continuity of an ordered temporal experience in a sudden discrete

Page 29: Art as Experience - John Dewey

24 ART AS EXPERIENCE

instant of climax. It is as meaningless in isolation as would bethe drama of Hamlet were it confined to a single line or wordwith no context. But the phrase "the rest is silence" is infinitelypregnantas the conclusion of a dramaenacted through development in time; so may be the momentary perception of a naturalscene. Form, as it is present in the fine arts, is the art of makingclear what is involved in the organization of space and time prefigured in every courseof a developinglife-experience.

Moments and places, despite physical limitation and narrow localization, are charged with accumulations of long-gathering energy. A return to a scene of childhood that was left longyears before floods the spot with a release of pent-up memoriesand hopes. To meet in a strange country one who is a casualacquaintance at home may arouse a satisfaction so acute as tobring a thrill. Mere recognitions occur only when we are occupied with something else than the object or person recognized.It marks either an interruption or else an intent to use what isrecognized as a means for something else. To see, to perceive, ismore than to recognize. It does not identify something presentin terms of a past disconnected from it. The past is carried intothe present so as to expand and deepen the content of the latter.There is illustrated the translation of bare continuity of externaltime into the vital order and organization of experience. Identification nods and passes on. Or it defines a passing moment inisolation, it marks a dead spot in experience that is merely filledin. The extent to which the process of living in any day or hour isreduced to labeling situations, events, and objects as "so-and-so"in mere succession marks the cessation of a life that is a consciousexperience. Continuities realized in an individual, discrete, formare the essence of the latter.

Art is thus prefigured in the very processes of living. Abird builds its nest and a beaver its dam when internal organicpressures cooperate with external materials so that the formetare fulfilled and the latter are transformed in a satisfying cul«mination. We may hesitate to apply the word "art," since wedoubt the presence of directive intent. But all deliberation, allconscious intent, grows out of things once performed organicallythrough the interplay of natural energies. Were it not so, artwould be built on quaking sands, nay, on unstable air. The dis*

Page 30: Art as Experience - John Dewey

"ETHERIAL THINGS" 25

tinguishing contribution of man is consciousness of the relationsfound in nature. Through consciousness, he converts the relationsof cause and effect that are found in nature into relations ofmeans and consequence. Rather, consciousness itself is the inception of such a transformation. What was mere shock becomes aninvitation; resistance becomes something to be used in changingexisting arrangements of matter; smooth facilities become agencies for executing an idea. In these operations, an organic stimulation becomes the bearer of meanings, and motor responses arechanged into instruments of expression and communication; nolonger are they mere means of locomotion and direct reaction.Meanwhile, the organic substratum remains as the quickeningand deep foundation. Apart from relations of cause and effect innature, conception and invention could not be. Apart from therelation of processes of rhythmic conflict and fulfillment in animallife, experience would be without design and pattern. Apart fromorgans inherited from animal ancestry, idea and purpose wouldbe without a mechanism of realization. The primeval arts of nature and animal life are so much the material, and, in gross outline, so much the model for the intentional achievements of man,that the theologically minded have imputed conscious intent tothe structure of nature—as man, sharing many activities withthe ape, is wont to think of the latter as imitating his own performances. {

The existence of art is the concrete proof of what has justbeen stated abstractly. It is proof that man uses the materials and energies of nature with intent to expand his ownlife, and that he does so in accord with the structure of his organism—brain, sense-organs, and muscular system. Art is theliving and concrete proof that man is capable of restoring consciously, and thus on the plane of meaning, the union of sense,need, impulse and action characteristic of the live creature. Theintervention of consciousness adds regulation, power of selection,and redisposition. Thus it varies the arts in ways without end.But its intervention also leads in time to the idea of art as a conscious idea—the greatest intellectual achievement in the historyof humanity.

The variety and perfection of the arts in Greece ledthinkers to frame a generalized conception of art and to project

Page 31: Art as Experience - John Dewey

26 ART AS EXPERIENCE

the ideal of an art of organization of human activities as such—the art of politics and morals as conceived by Socrates and Plato.The ideas of design, plan, order, pattern, purpose emerged in distinction from and relation to the materials employed in their realization. The conception of man as the being that uses art becameat once the ground of the distinction of man from the rest ofnature and of the bond that ties him to nature. When the conception of art as the distinguishing trait of man was made explicit,there was assurance that, short of complete relapse of humanitybelow even savagery, the possibility of invention of new artswould remain, along with use of old arts, as the guiding ideal ofmankind. Although recognition of the fact still halts, because oftraditions established before the power of art was adequatelyrecognized,science itself is but a central art auxiliary to the generation and utilization of other arts.4'

It is customary, and from some points of view necessary,to make a distinction between fine art and useful or technologicalart. But the point of view from which it is necessary is one thatis extrinsic to the work of art itself. The customary distinction isbased simply on acceptance of certain existing social conditions.I suppose the fetiches of the negro sculptor were taken to beuseful in the highest degree to his tribal group, more so even thanspears and clothing. But now they are fine art, serving in thetwentieth century to inspire renovations in arts that had grownconventional. But they are fine art only because the anonymousartist lived and experienced so fully during the process of production. An angler may eat his catch without thereby losing theesthetic satisfaction he experienced in casting and playing. It isthis degree of completeness of living in the experience of makingand of perceiving that makes the difference between what is fineor esthetic in art and what is not. Whether the thing made is putto use, as are bowls, rugs, garments, weapons, is, intrinsicallyspeaking, a matter of indifference. That many, perhaps most, ofChe articles and utensils made at present for use are not genuinely

*I have developed this point in "Experience and Nature," in ChapterNine, on Experience, Nature andArt. As faras the presentpoint is concerned,the conclusion is contained in the statement that "art, the mode of activitythat is charged with meanings capable of immediately enjoyed possession, isthe complete culmination of nature, and that science is properly a handmaiden that conducts natural events to this happy issue." (P. 358.)

Page 32: Art as Experience - John Dewey

"ETHERIAL THINGS" 27

esthetic happens, unfortunately, to be true. But it is true forreasons that are foreign to the relation of the "beautiful" and"useful" as such. Wherever conditions are such as to preventthe act of production from being an experience in which thewhole creature is alive and in which he possesses his livingthrough enjoyment, the product will lack something of beingesthetic. No matter how useful it is for special and limited ends,it will not be useful in the ultimate degree—that of contributingdirectly and liberally to an expanding and enriched life. Thestory of the severance and final sharp opposition of the useful andthe fine is the history of that industrial development throughwhich so much of production has become a form of postponedliving and so much of consumption a superimposed enjoyment ofthe fruits of the labor of others.

USUALLY there is a hostile reaction to a conception of art thatconnects it with the activities of a live creature in its environment. The hostility to association of fine art with normal processes of living is a pathetic, even a tragic, commentary on life asit is ordinarily lived. Only because that life is usually so stunted,aborted, slack, or heavy laden, is the idea entertained that there issome inherent antagonism between the process of normal livingand creation and enjoyment of works of esthetic art. After all,even though "spiritual" and "material" are separated and set inopposition to one another, there must be conditions through whichthe ideal is capable of embodiment and realization—and this isall, fundamentally, that "matter" signifies. The very currencywhich the opposition has acquired testifies, therefore, to a widespread operation of forces that convert what might be meansof executing liberal ideas into oppressive burdens and that causeideals to be loose aspirations in an uncertain and ungroundedatmosphere.

While art itself is the best proof of the existence of a realized and therefore realizable, union of material and ideal, thereare general arguments that support'the thesis in hand. Wherevercontinuity is possible, the burden of proof rests upon those whoassert opposition and dualism. Nature is the mother and the

Page 33: Art as Experience - John Dewey

28 ART AS EXPERIENCE

habitat of man, even if sometimes a stepmother and an unfriendlyhome. The fact that civilization endures and culture continues—and sometimes advances—is evidence that human hopes and purposes find a basis and support in nature. As the developing growthof an individual from embryo to maturity is the result of interaction of organism with surroundings, so culture is the productnot of efforts of men put forth in a void or just upon themselves,but of prolonged and cumulative interaction with environment.The depth of the responses stirred by works of art shows theircontinuity with the operations of this enduring experience. Theworks and the responses they evoke are continuouswith the veryprocesses of living as these are carried to unexpectedhappy fulfillment.

As to absorption of the esthetic in nature, I cite a caseduplicated in some measure in thousands of persons, but notable because expressed by an artist of the first order, W. H.Hudson. "I feel when I am out of sight of living, growing grass,and out of the sound of birds' voices and all rural sounds, that Iam not properly alive." He goes on to say, "... when I hearpeople say that they have not found the world and life so agreeable and interesting as to be in love with it, or that they lookwith equanimity to its end, I am apt to think that they havenever been properly alive, nor seen with clear vision the worldthey think so meanly of or anything in it—not even a blade ofgrass." The mystic aspect of acute esthetic surrender, that renders it so akin as an experience to what religionists term ecstaticcommunion, is recalled by Hudson from his boyhood life. He isspeaking of the effect the sight of acacia trees had upon him."The loose feathery foliage on moonlight nights had a peculiarhoary aspect that made this tree seemmore intensely alive thanothers, more conscious of me and of my presence.... Similar toa feeling a personwould have if visited by a supernatural beingif he was perfectly convinced that it was there in his presence,albeit silent and. unseen, intently regarding him and diviningevery thought in his mind." Emerson is often regarded as anaustere thinker. But it was Emerson as an adult who said, quitein the spirit of the passage quoted from Hudson: "Crossing abare common, in snow puddles, at twilight, under a clouded sky,without having in my thought any occurrence of special good

Page 34: Art as Experience - John Dewey

••ETHERIAL THINGS'* 29

fortune, I have enjoyed a perfect exhilaration. I am glad to thebrink of fear."

I do not see any way of accounting for the multiplicity ofexperiences of this kind (something of the same quality beingfound in every spontaneous and uncoerced esthetic response),except on the basis that there are stirred into activity resonancesof dispositions acquired in primitive relationships of the livingbeing to its surroundings, and irrecoverable in distinct or intellectual consciousness. Experiences of the sort mentioned take usto a further consideration that testifies to natural continuity.There is no limit to the capacity of immediate sensuous experience to absorb into itself meanings and values that in and ofthemselves—that is in the abstract—would be designated "ideal"and "spiritual." The animistic strain of religious experience, embodied in Hudson's memory of his childhood days, is an instanceon one level of experience. And the poetical, in whatever medium,is always a close kin of the animistic. And if we turn to an artthat in many ways is at the other pole, architecture, we learnhow ideas, wrought out at first perhapsin highly technical thoughtlike that of mathematics, are capable of direct incorporation insensuous form. The sensible surface of things is never merelya surface. One can discriminate rock from flimsy tissue-paper bythe surface alone, so completely have the resistances of touch andthe solidities due to stresses of the entire muscular system beenembodied in vision. The process does not stop with incarnationof other sensory qualities that give depth of meaning to surface.Nothing that a man has ever reached by the highest flight ofthought or penetrated by any probing insight is inherently suchthat it may not become the heart and core of sense.

The same word, "symbol," is used to designate expressions of abstract thought, as in mathematics, and alsosuch things as a flag, crucifix, that embody deep social valueand the meaning of historic faith and theological creed. Incense,stained glass, the chiming of unseen bells, embroidered robes accompany the approach to what is regarded as divine. The connection of the origin of many arts with primitive rituals becomesmore evident with every excursion of the anthropologist into thepast. Only those who are so far removed from the earlier experiences as to miss their sense will conclude that rites and

Page 35: Art as Experience - John Dewey

30 ART AS EXPERIENCE

ceremonies were merely technical devices for securing rain, sons,crops, success in battle. Of course they had this magical intent,but they were enduringly enacted, we may be sure, in spite of allpractical failures, because they were immediate enhancementsof the experience of living. Myths were something other than in-tellectualistic essays of primitive man in science. Uneasiness before any unfamiliar fact doubtless played its part. But delightin the story, in the growth and rendition of a good yarn, playedits dominant part then as it does in the growth of popular mythologies today. Not only does the direct sense element—and emotion is a mode of sense—tend to absorb all ideational matter but,apart from special discipline enforced by physical apparatus, itsubdues and digests all that is merely intellectual.

The introduction of the supernatural into belief and theall too human easy reversion to the supernatural is much morean affair of the psychology that generates works of art than ofeffort at scientific and philosophic explanation. It intensifies emotional thrill and punctuates the interest that belongs to all breakin familiar routine. Were the hold of the supernatural on humanthought an exclusively—or even mainly—intellectual matter, itwould be comparatively insignificant. Theologies and cosmogonieshave laid hold of imagination because they have been attendedwith solemn processions, incense, embroidered robes, music, theradiance of colored lights, with stories that stir wonder and induce hypnotic admiration. That is, they have come to man througha direct appeal to sense and to sensuous imagination. Most religions have identified their sacraments with the highest reachesof art, and the most authoritative beliefs have been clothed in agarb of pomp and pageantry that gives immediate delight to eyeand ear and that evokes massive emotions of suspense, wonder,and awe. The flights of physicists and astronomers today answerto the esthetic need for satisfaction of the imagination ratherthan to any strict demand of unemotional evidence for rationalinterpretation.

Henry Adams made it clear that the theology of themiddle ages is a construction of the same intent as that whichwrought the cathedrals. In general this middle age, popularlydeemed to express the acme of Christian faith in the westernworld, is a demonstration of the power of sense to absorb the

Page 36: Art as Experience - John Dewey

"ETHERIAL THINGS" 31

most highly spiritualized ideas. Music, painting, sculpture, architecture, drama and romance were handmaidens of religion, asmuch as were science and scholarship. The arts hardly had abeing outside of the church, and the rites and ceremonies of thechurch were arts enacted under conditions that gave them themaximum possible of emotional and imaginative appeal. For I donot know what would give the spectator and auditor of the manifestation of the arts a more poignant surrender than the conviction that they were informed with the necessarymeans of eternalglory and bliss.

The following words of Pater are worth quoting in thisconnection. "The Christianity of the middle ages made its waypartly by its esthetic beauty, a thing so profoundly felt by theLatin hymn writers, who for one moral or spiritual sentiment hada hundred sensuous images. A passion of which the outlets aresealed begets a tension of nerve in which the sensible world comesto one with a reinforced brilliancy and relief—all redness turnedinto blood, all water into tears. Hence a wild convulsed sensuous-ness in all the poetry of the middle ages, in which the things ofnature began to play a strange delirious part. Of the things ofnature, the medieval mind had a deep sense; but its sense of themwas not objective, no real escape to the world without us."

In his autobiographical essay, The Child in the House, hegeneralizes what is implicit in this passage. He says: "In lateryears he came upon philosophieswhich occupiedhim much in theestimate of the proportions of the sensuous and ideal elementsin human knowledge, the relative parts they bear in it; and, inhis intellectual scheme, was led to assign very little to the abstract thought, and much to its sensible vehicle or occasion."The latter "became the necessary concomitant of any perceptionof things, real enough to have any weight or reckoning, in hishouse of thought.... He came more and more to be unable tocare for, or think of soul but as in an actual body, or of any worldbut that wherein are water and trees, and where men and womenlook, so or so, and press actualhands." The elevation of the idealaboveand beyond immediate sensehas operatednot only to makeit pallidand bloodless, but it hasacted,like a conspirator with thesensual mind, to impoverish and degrade all things of directexperience

Page 37: Art as Experience - John Dewey

32 ART AS EXPERIENCE

In the title of this chapter I took the liberty of borrowingfrom Keats the word "etherial" to designate the meanings andvalues that many philosophers and some critics suppose are inaccessible to sense, because of their spiritual, eternal and universal characters—thus exemplifying the common dualism ofnature and spirit. Let me re-quote his words. The artist maylook "upon the Sun, the Moon, the Stars, and the Earth and itscontents as material to form greater things, that is etherial things—greater things than the Creator himself made." In making thisuse of Keats, I had also in mind the fact that he identified theattitude of the artist with that of the live creature; and did so notmerely in the implicit tenor of his poetry but in reflectionexpressed the idea explicitly in words. As he wrote in a letterto his brother: "The greater part of men make their waywith the same instinctiveness, the same unwandering eye fromtheir purposes as the Hawk. The Hawk wants a mate, so does theman—look at them both, they set about and procure one in thesame manner. They both want a nest and they both set about itin the same manner—they get their food in the same manner.The noble animal Man for his amusement smokes his pipe—theHawk balances about in the clouds—this is the only differenceof their leisures. This is that which makes the amusement of Lifeto a speculative mind. I go out among the Fields and catch aglimpse of a Stoat or a fieldmouse hurrying along—to what? Thecreature has a purpose and his eyes are bright with it. I goamongst the buildings of a city and see a Man hurrying along—to what? The Creature has a purpose and his eyes are bright withit...

"Even here though I am pursuing the same instinctivecourse as the veriest human animal I can think of [though] Iam, however young, writing at random straining at particles oflight in the midst of great darkness, without knowing the bearingof any assertion, of any one opinion. Yet may I not in this befree from sin? May there not be superior beings amused withany graceful, though instinctive, attitude my mind may fall intoas I am entertained with the alertness of a Stoat or the anxietyof a Deer? Though a quarrel in the streets is to be hated, theenergiesdisplayed in it are fine; the commonestMan has a gracein his quarrel. Seen by a supernatural Being our reasonings may

Page 38: Art as Experience - John Dewey

••ETHERIAL THINGS" 33

take the same tone—though erroneous, they may be fine. This isthe very thing in whichconsists poetry. There may be reasonings,but when they take an instinctive form, like that of animal formsand movements, they are poetry, they are fine; they have grace."

In another letter he speaks of Shakespeare as a man ofenormous "Negative Capability"; as one who was "capable ofbeing in uncertainties, mysteries, doubts, without any irritablereachingafter fact and reason." He contrasts Shakespeare in thisrespect with his own contemporary Coleridge, who would let apoeticinsight gowhen it was surrounded with obscurity,becausehe could not intellectually justify it; could not, in Keats' language, be satisfied with "/^/-knowledge." I think the same ideais contained in what he says, in a letter to Bailey, that he "neveryet has been able to perceive how anything can be known fortruth by consecutive reasoning.... Can it be that even the greatest Philosopher ever arrived at his Goal without putting asidenumerous objections": asking, in effect, Does not the reasonerhave also to trust to his "intuitions", to what come upon him inhis immediate sensuous and emotional experiences, even againstobjections that reflection presents to him. For he goes on to say"the simple imaginativemind may have its rewards in the repetitions of its own silent workings coming continually on the Spiritwith a fine suddenness"—a remark that contains more of thepsychology of productive thought than many treatises.

In spite of the elliptical character of Keats1 statementstwo points emerge. One of them is his conviction that "reasonings" have an origin like that of the movements of a wild creaturetoward its goal, and they may becomespontaneous, "instinctive,"and when they become instinctive are sensuous and immediate,poetic. The other side of this conviction is his belief that no"reasoning" as reasoning, that is, as excluding imagination andsense, can reach truth. Even "the greatest philosopher" exercisesan animal-like preference to guide his thinking to its conclusions.He selects and puts* aside as his imaginative sentiments move."Reason" at its height cannot attain complete grasp and a self-contained assurance. It must fall back upon imagination—uponthe embodiment of ideas in emotionally charged sense.

There has been much dispute as to what Keats meant inhis famous lines:

Page 39: Art as Experience - John Dewey

34 ART AS EXPERIENCE

"Beauty is truth, truth beauty—that is allYeknow on earth, andall ye needto know,"

and what he meant in the cognate prose statement—"What imagination seizes as beautymust be truth." Much of the disputeis carried on in ignorance of the particular tradition in whichKeats wrote and which gave the term "truth" its meaning. Inthis tradition, "truth" never signifies correctness of intellectualstatements about things, or truth as its meaning is now influencedby science. It denotes the wisdom by which men live, especially"the lore of good and evil." And in Keats' mind it was particularly connected with the question of justifying good and trustingto it in spite of the evil and destruction that abound. "Philosophy" is the attempt to answer this question rationally. Keats'belief that evenphilosophers cannot deal with the questionwithout depending on imaginative intuitions receives an independentand positive statement in his identification of "beauty" with"truth"—the particular truth that solves for man the bafflingproblem of destruction and death—which weighed so constantlyon Keats—in the very realm where life strives to assert supremacy. Man lives in a world of surmise, of mystery, of uncertainties. "Reasoning" must fail man—this of course is a doctrinelong taught by those who have held to the necessity of a divinerevelation. Keats did not accept this supplement and substitutefor reason. The insight of imagination must suffice. "This is allye know on earth and all ye need to know." The critical wordsare "on earth"—that is amid a scene in which "irritable reachingafter fact and reason" confuses and distorts instead of bringingus to the light. It was in moments of most intense esthetic perception that Keats found his utmost solace and his deepest convictions. This is the fact recorded at the close of his Ode.Ultimately there are but two philosophies. One of them acceptslife and experience in all its uncertainty, mystery, doubt, andhalf-knowledge and turns that experience upon itself to deepenand intensify its own qualities—to imagination and art. This isthe philosophy of Shakespeare and Keats.

Page 40: Art as Experience - John Dewey

CHAPTER III

HAYING AN EXPERIENCE

EXPERIENCE occurs continuously, because the interaction oflive creature and environing conditions is involved in the very

process of living. Under conditions of resistance and conflict,aspects and elements of the self and the world that are implicated in this interaction qualify experience with emotions andideas so that conscious intent emerges. Oftentimes, however, theexperience had is inchoate. Things are experienced but not insuch a way that they are composed into an experience. There isdistraction and dispersion; what we observe and what we think,what we desire and what we get, are at odds with each other. Weput our hands to the plow and turn back; we start and thenwe stop, not because the experience has reached the end for thesake of which it was initiated but because of extraneous interruptions or of inner lethargy.

In contrast with such experience, we have an experiencewhen the material experienced runs its course to fulfillment. Thenand then only is it integrated within and demarcated in the general stream of experience from other experiences. A piece of workis finished in a way that is satisfactory; a problem receives itssolution; a game is played through; a situation, whether that ofeating a meal, playing a game of chess, carrying on a conversation, writing a book, or taking part in a political campaign, is sorounded out that its close is a consummation and not a cessation.Such an experience is a whole and carries with it its own individualizingquality and self-sufficiency. It is an experience.

Philosophers, evenempirical philosophers, have spoken forthe most part of experience at large. Idiomatic speech, however,refers to experiences each of which is singular, having its ownbeginning and end. For life is no uniform uninterrupted marchor flow. It is a thing of histories, each with its own plot, its owninception and movement toward its close, each having its own

35

Page 41: Art as Experience - John Dewey

36 ART AS EXPERIENCE

particular rhythmic movement; each with its own unrepeatedquality pervading it throughout. A flight of stairs, mechanicalasit is, proceeds by individualized steps, not by undifferentiatedprogression, and an inclined plane is at least marked off fromother things by abrupt discreteness.

Experience in this vital sense is defined by those situationsand episodes that we spontaneously refer to as being "real experiences"; those things of which we say in recalling them, "thatwas an experience." It may have been something of tremendousimportance—a quarrel with one who was once an intimate, acatastrophe finally averted by a hair's breadth. Or it may havebeen something that in comparison was slight—and which perhaps because of its very slightness illustrates all the better whatis to be an experience. There is that meal in a Paris restaurantof which one says "that was an experience." It stands out as anenduring memorial of what food may be. Then there is that stormone went through in crossing the Atlantic—the storm that seemedin its fury, as it was experienced, to sum up in itself all that astorm can be, complete in itself, standing out becausemarked outfrom what went before and what came after.

In such experiences, every successive part flows freely,without seam and without unfilled blanks, into what ensues. Atthe sametime thereis no sacrifice of the self-identity of the parts.A river, as distinct from a pond, flows. But its flow gives a defi-nitenessand interest to its successive portions greater than exist inthe homogenous portions of a pond. In an experience, flow is fromsomething to something. As one part leads into another and asone part carries on what went before, each gains distinctness initself.The enduring whole is diversified by successive phases thatare emphases of its varied colors.

Because of continuous merging, there are no holes, mechanical junctions, and dead centers when wehaveanexperience.There are pauses, places of rest, but they punctuate and definethe quality of movement. They sum up what has been undergone and prevent its dissipation and idle evaporation. Continuedacceleration is breathless and prevents parts from gaining distinction. In a work of art, different acts, episodes, occurrencesmelt and fuse into unity, and yet do not disappear and lose theirown character as they do so—just as in a genial conversation

Page 42: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 43: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 44: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 45: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 46: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 47: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 48: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 49: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 50: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 51: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 52: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 53: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 54: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 55: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 56: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 57: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 58: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 59: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 60: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 61: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 62: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 63: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 64: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 65: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 66: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 67: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 68: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 69: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 70: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 71: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 72: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 73: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 74: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 75: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 76: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 77: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 78: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 79: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 80: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 81: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 82: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 83: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 84: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 85: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 86: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 87: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 88: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 89: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 90: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 91: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 92: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 93: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 94: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 95: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 96: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 97: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 98: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 99: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 100: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 101: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 102: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 103: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 104: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 105: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 106: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 107: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 108: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 109: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 110: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 111: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 112: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 113: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 114: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 115: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 116: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 117: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 118: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 119: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 120: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 121: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 122: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 123: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 124: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 125: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 126: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 127: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 128: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 129: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 130: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 131: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 132: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 133: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 134: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 135: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 136: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 137: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 138: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 139: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 140: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 141: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 142: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 143: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 144: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 145: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 146: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 147: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 148: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 149: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 150: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 151: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 152: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 153: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 154: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 155: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 156: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 157: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 158: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 159: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 160: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 161: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 162: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 163: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 164: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 165: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 166: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 167: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 168: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 169: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 170: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 171: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 172: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 173: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 174: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 175: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 176: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 177: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 178: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 179: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 180: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 181: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 182: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 183: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 184: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 185: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 186: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 187: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 188: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 189: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 190: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 191: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 192: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 193: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 194: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 195: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 196: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 197: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 198: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 199: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 200: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 201: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 202: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 203: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 204: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 205: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 206: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 207: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 208: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 209: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 210: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 211: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 212: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 213: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 214: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 215: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 216: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 217: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 218: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 219: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 220: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 221: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 222: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 223: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 224: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 225: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 226: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 227: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 228: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 229: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 230: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 231: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 232: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 233: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 234: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 235: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 236: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 237: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 238: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 239: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 240: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 241: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 242: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 243: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 244: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 245: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 246: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 247: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 248: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 249: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 250: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 251: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 252: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 253: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 254: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 255: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 256: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 257: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 258: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 259: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 260: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 261: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 262: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 263: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 264: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 265: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 266: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 267: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 268: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 269: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 270: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 271: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 272: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 273: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 274: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 275: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 276: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 277: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 278: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 279: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 280: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 281: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 282: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 283: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 284: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 285: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 286: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 287: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 288: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 289: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 290: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 291: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 292: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 293: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 294: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 295: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 296: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 297: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 298: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 299: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 300: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 301: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 302: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 303: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 304: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 305: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 306: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 307: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 308: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 309: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 310: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 311: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 312: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 313: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 314: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 315: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 316: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 317: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 318: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 319: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 320: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 321: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 322: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 323: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 324: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 325: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 326: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 327: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 328: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 329: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 330: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 331: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 332: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 333: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 334: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 335: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 336: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 337: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 338: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 339: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 340: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 341: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 342: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 343: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 344: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 345: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 346: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 347: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 348: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 349: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 350: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 351: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 352: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 353: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 354: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 355: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 356: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 357: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 358: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 359: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 360: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 361: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 362: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 363: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 364: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 365: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 366: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 367: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 368: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 369: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 370: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 371: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 372: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 373: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 374: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 375: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 376: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 377: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 378: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 379: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 380: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 381: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 382: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 383: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 384: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 385: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 386: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 387: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 388: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 389: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 390: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 391: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 392: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 393: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 394: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 395: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 396: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 397: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 398: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 399: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 400: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 401: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 402: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 403: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 404: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 405: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 406: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 407: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 408: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 409: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 410: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 411: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 412: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 413: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 414: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 415: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 416: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 417: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 418: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 419: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 420: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 421: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 422: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 423: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 424: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 425: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 426: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 427: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 428: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 429: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 430: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 431: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 432: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 433: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 434: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 435: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 436: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 437: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 438: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 439: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 440: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 441: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 442: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 443: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 444: Art as Experience - John Dewey
Page 445: Art as Experience - John Dewey