Upload
loliloust
View
218
Download
0
Embed Size (px)
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
1/26
Aglietta in England : Bob Jessops contribution to theregulation approachseptembre 1994Bonefeld, Werner
1. Introduction
The main contribution to the Regulation Approach (RA) in the UK has come from B. Jessop [1].
His contribution bas focused on the reformulation of state theory. This reformulation aims at a
conceptualisation of an intermediate concept of state: the fordist or post-fordist states as
distinctively different modes of capitalist regulation. The reformulation of state theory bas been
criticized by various authors [2]. The reformulation was criticized for its disarticulation of
structure and struggle. ln this paper, it will be argued that Jessops adaptation of the RA entails
a destruction of the Marxian notion of social relations in favour of a combination of system
theory and conflict theory. Reformulating Marxism in this way involves a theoretical acceptance
of the conceptual and practical horizons of a social given world. This acceptance involves a
causalist and/or teleological determinism.
Jessops reformulation of state theory is aIl too ready to endorse existing reality and its
ideological projections. For Jessop so-called Thatcherism came to signify a broadranging and
distinctive programme aimed at promoting a new accumulation regime and restoring the
authority of the state. By restricting his horizon to this version of existing reality, Jessops
analysis became blinkered. The movement of class struggle was dismissed in favour of
apparently more fitting concepts like Post-Fordism. Within this restricted field of vision, the
analysis of Thatcherism entailed the acceptance of the inevitability of a presumed thatcherite
project. The acceptance of the conceptual and practical horizon of a given reality as ifs own
theory was based upon a reformulation of Marxist theory in terms of regulation theory and
Poulantzarian state theory. This reformulation entailed a fundamental revision of erstwhile
positions, embracing enthusiastically the crass ideology of neoliberalism.
This paper introduces Jessops notion of the dialectic between structure and strategy and
discusses the application of this dialectic to the analysis of Thatcherism. The presentation is
restricted to arguments relevant to the dialectic between structure and strategy. The following
is the order of presentation : A brief introduction of Jessops own understanding of his work is
followed by a short introduction of Jessops notion of accumulation strategy. The dialectic
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb1http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb1http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb1http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb17/27/2019 Aglietta in England
2/26
between structure and strategy will be discussed in the third part. There then follows a section
on Jessops approach to Thatcherism. The theoretical and political implications of Jessops
approach will be examined in the papers final part. The conclusion is written in more general
terms. This is so because it would be wrong to see his contribution as somehow unique. Jessop
works within the framework of a particular school of thought. The differences within this school
become of secondary importance when discussed in general terms.
II. Jessops Understanding of his Work
Jessop understands his own work as a combination of regulation theory with a strategic-
relational account of the state inspired by Poulantzas and a discourse-theoretical approach to
hegemony most influenced by Gramsci and Laclau (Jessop 1988). The distinctive features of his
approach are the emphasis on the dialectic between structure and strategy. This emphasis
appears in the use of concepts such as accumulation regime, forms of state, and historical bloc.
These concepts are complemented by others such as accumulation strategy, state projects and
hegemonic projects (ibid.). The dialectic between structure and strategy is explored in terms of
strategie selectivity of structures and the structurally transforming role of strategies (ibid.).
Jessops emphasis is a typical structuralist response to the problem of integrating class struggle
iota the analysis. Within the framework of the RA, Jessop elaborates Agliettas methodological
assumption that the class struggle produces norms and laws ; that these norms and laws form
the object of a theory of social regulation ; that the class struggle itself is beyond any law
(Aglietta 1979, p. 67).
III. The Notion of Accumulation Strategy
Jessops[3] contribution to the dialectic between structure and strategy attempts to build on,
and to develop, Poulantzass approach in response to its critics. Jessop argues for a
conjunctural (or relational) approach to the relation between the political and the economic,
equating, in its most extreme version, not only struggle with strategy, but, as argued by
Holloway (1988/1991), class struggle with capital strategies. The constitution of social reality, in
Jessop, follows the independent logics of political and ideological domains, forcing the scientific
mind to follow, in descriptive terms, the strategic line of capital in the face of various dilemmas,
risks, uncertainties and complexities, emergent strategies, trial and error techniques etc.
(Jessop et al. 1988, p. 8). As a consequence, complex historical phenomena are best analysed
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb3http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb3http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb3http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb37/27/2019 Aglietta in England
3/26
as a complex resultant of multiple determinations (ibid., p. 53). Jessop claims that the interplay
of objective laws of capitalist development and the hegemonic struggle of different capital
logics provide mechanisms that melt different social systems together, so permitting a
corresponding social cohesion of ideological, political and economic patterns. These patterns are,
as argued by Bonefeld (1987/1991) and Clarke (1983), of a systematic kind, objectively
unfolding and framed in a voluntarist fashion. As indicated by Psychopeds (1991) Jessop derives
different logics of capital from distinct allocation interests which exist independently from class.
The class struggle is separated from its mode of motion and degenerates into a factor of a
historical development which is bath contingent and relative. The term accumulation strategy is
used as a means of articulating the contingent unit y between the economic and the political.
Since there is no substantive unity to the circuit of capital nor any predetermined pattern of
accumulation (Jessop 1983, p. 91), sustained accumulation requires an extra power in order to
impose regulative mechanisms. This power is the state. The pattern of accumulation is
determined by the accumulation regime adopted by the state.
Jessop advocates the Poulantzarian distinction between a theory of the capitalist mode of
production and the theory of the capitalist state region. Such an approach to the capitalist state
denies an internaI relation between the political and the economic on the basis of the labour
theory of value (as in Jessop 1982). Responding to his critics, Jessop sought to make this good
by supplying a link between the economic and the political [4]. The link is the concept of
accumulation strategy (Jessop 1983). However, Jessops approach becomes eclectic since his
specification of different accumulation strategies ranges from Hitlers Grossraum-wirtschaft to
Japans rich country and strong army and to Germanys Modell Deutschland (ibid., p. 94).
Further, the arbitrariness of choice is intensified by the failure to integrate a list of social
phenomena iota a theoretical concept. The analysis becomes non-binding and, thereby,
relativist. Jessops theorising is part of a tradition which takes for granted the fragmented
character of social existence. The classical example of this tradition is the work of Max Weber,
aIthough Jessop fails to approach the theoretical profundity and reflection which are
characteristic of Webers analysis (Psychopedis 1991, p. 182). Jessops attempt to incorporate
the labour theory of value iota his argument is conspicuous for its eclecticism. An accumulation
strategy is understood as a "subject" which, in Jessops [1983] own words, "must take account"
of the circuit of capital, international conjunctures, the balance of powers and which "must
consider" the relation between the classes, etc. In other words, we have here a reappearance of
the Hegelian idealistic subject so disliked by the structuralists. (Psychopedis 1991, p. 189). A
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb4http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb4http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb4http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb47/27/2019 Aglietta in England
4/26
successful accumulation strategy stands above class relations because it takes into account
different modes of calculation and gives a particular coherence and political direction to the
multiplicity of forces operating in the real world of competing subjects. An accumulation strategy
articulates multiple determinations of the real world into a specific mode of regulation.
However, no unique accumulation strategy is available to the state, but rather a range of
alternative strategies, expressing different classes and fractional interests and alliances. Any
viable accumulation strategy bas to reconcile the pursuit of sectional interests with the sustained
accumulation of capital. The determination of which accumulation strategy will be adopted by
the state requires an analysis of political conflicts through which strategic issues are resolved
(Jessop 1983). Jessops theory of conflict is based on the relative autonomy of the economic,
political and ideological. The state is, following Poulantzas and Aglietta, seen as being formally
determined as a vehicle for social cohesion. The task is thus to show the unfolding of the states
formaI character in specific historical conjunctures. Jessops politicist understanding of capitalist
reproduction is based on the notion that the state stands above a plurality of competitive and
class struggles and provides the functional integration of a regime of accumulation. The real
movement of capitalism is thus construed in terms of an articulation between different social
systems which stand above the social conflict. Jessop offers his dialectic of structure and
strategy as a means of integrating social relations into the analysis.
IV. The Dialectic between Structure and Strategy
a) The Dualism of Structure and Strategy
Jessops approach is predicated on causal mechanisms and multiple determinations. It is
predicated also on the presupposition of an ideal subject against which he officially proclaims.
This subject is created ex nihilo.Jessops contribution to regulation theory emphasises capital as
an bergreifendes Subjekt.
For Jessop, Marxist theorising is not predicated on the real movement of class antagonism and
the constituting movement of class struggle but, rather, on the contention that the real world is
a world of contingently realised natural necessities (Jessop 1988, p. 8). The notion of
contingency is of vital importance for Jessops attempted Marxist reformulation of neo -
liberalism. It allows him to define a structurally complex world of systems and institutions within
which atomized social subjects pursue their interests. Fundamentally, class antagonism is
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
5/26
understood in terms of competing social groups. Each of these groups occupies a particular class
position vis-a-vis structure. The dual perspective of structural determination and class position
(Jessop 1985) fails to recognise structures as implicit in the form of class relations. For Jessop,
structures connote a system of causal mechanisms which provide social spaces for human
activities. While these activities are vital for the reproduction of structures, the structural
framework is seen as existing independently from human relations. Human relations appear
merely as attendant upon structural laws.
The world of structures is said to be complex because of its division into different regions, each
having its own causal power and liabilities. Further, these regions are said to involve hierarchies,
with some regions emergent from others but reacting back on them. Each region is itself
stratified, comprising not only a level of real causal mechanisms and liabilities but also the levels
on which such powers are actualised and/or- can be empirically examined (Jessop 1988).
Jessops reformulation of the base-superstructure metaphor and of descriptive sociology
associated with Poulantzas takes for granted the separation of social relations into distinctive
structural systems. It also seeks to proliferate these structures by dividing basic structures into
stratified subsystems. These subsystems, as will be shown below, are said to have their own
distinct determinations, logics and laws, subduing and undermining resistance to capitalist
reproduction.
How does Jessop conceptualise, or better, reformulate the Marxian idea of the enchanted and
perverted world of capitalism (Marx) ? Jessop does not deny that there is an inner relation
between different social systems. However, and in contradistinction to approaches predicated
on the notion of an antagonistic constitution of social relations, Jessop thematises this unity in
terms of a positivist social theory. The unity between different systems is founded on the notion
of natural necessities. The sui generis operation of social systems is understood as contingently
realising the natural necessities of capitalism. Jessop avoids providing any answers to the
question as to the constitution of these necessities. The necessities are assumed to be naturaI
necessities. The determination of natural remains unexplained. And yet, the notion of natural
necessities is of crucial importance for what Jessop describes as bis realist ontological approach
(see Jessop 1988) [5]. As will be argued below, Jessops realist ontology is predicated on the
notion that the real defies analysis. Before explaining this further, Jessops dialectic between
structure and strategy needs to be clarified in more detail. Jessop has to account for the fact
that the capitalist system moves. This leads him to introduce, on an empirical level. the notion of
many subjects. We are thus confronted with the notions of, on the one band, a sui
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb5http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb5http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb5http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb57/27/2019 Aglietta in England
6/26
generis operation of different regions, and, on the other, of a plurality of empirically observable
subjects. The dualism between structural determination and many subjects destroys the Marxian
notion of a contradictory constitution of social relations since human relations are understood as
external from structural determination. The notion of many subjects is incomprehensible
because it is premised on the concept of natural necessities which exist independently from, and
whose development is not limited to, human existence. The positivist concept of natural
necessities connotes a thing-like structure which determines social relations. As a consequence,
the concept of class dissolves into the pluralist notion of interest-groups, each of which relates to
emergent structural ensembles in its own way. Jessops pluralist reformulation of the Marxist
notion of class is not uncommon in the Marxist tradition. In the days of the DIAMA T-style
Marxism of the Stalin years, social development was seen as being determined by technological
development. The irony of Jessops approach is that his updating of Marxism reintroduces an
understanding of history in terms of an adaptation of social relations to the functional
requirements of the productive forces [6]. While Jessop proclaims against such an interpretation
of his views, his dualism between natural necessity and many subjects is complicit in the
reintroduction of old-style orthodoxy.
b) Causal Mechanisms and Social Conflict
If one were to follow Jessops notion of thesui generis operation of different systems founded on
natural necessities, how would one be able to understand the contingent realisation of
capitalist reproduction ? The first answer to this question is that this realisation cannot be
conceptualised because the notion of contingency prohibits any grasp on the real movement of
capitalist development. However, according to Jessop, the scientific mind can, nevertheless,
reveal tendential causal mechanisms whose outcome depends on specific initial conditions as
well as on the contingent interaction among tendencies and countertendencies (Jessop 1988, p.
9). Tendencies, such as the tendency of the rate of profit to fall, and countertendencies, such as
the countertendencies to the tendency of the rate of profit to fall, comprise different,
substantially unconnected mechanisms of the abstract structure of capitalism. These
mechanisms operate within the economic domain. Tendencies and countertendencies, although
externally related to each other, stand to each other in a relation of interdependency, thus
reciprocally transforming their sui generis operation. The articulation as between tendencies and
countertendencies establish the laws of motion of capitalism. The unfolding of these laws
provide causal mechanisms. These mechanisms establish the natural necessities of capitalist
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb6http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb6http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb6http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb67/27/2019 Aglietta in England
7/26
reproduction in terms of structural moments which define the framework of social actions.
Structural moments are both constraining and facilitating in regard to the interests of social
subjects. The laws themselves are understood to be underdetermined. The results of capitalist
reproduction do not follow the unfolding of these laws because these laws need to be activated
in specific conjunctural conditions. Thus, while there are causal mechanisms, the actual results
of these mechanisms depend on empirical conditions which, as was reported above, defy
conceptualisation. Jessop denies that there is a single objective logic of capitalist development
which transcends all particularities (Jessop 1988/1991). He deduces from this denial the
separation of abstract theory from real results, that is, from empirical data. He insists that the
development of capitalism is always mediated through historically specific institutional forms,
regulatory institutions and norms of conduct, such as the wage relations, forms of competition,
monetary emission, the state, the international commercial and financial system and the norms
of conduct and modes of calculation which correspond to these institutional forms, etc. (Jessop
1988/1991, p. 151). Jessop fails to show how this list can be integrated conceptually and how it
can be applied to concrete analysis. Further, the mediating elements of historical development
are dependent on human agency at the same time as they stand above, and are thus not limited
to, human agency. The upshot is a system of natural structures which define the structural
framework within which social conflict unfolds. The social conflict is construed in terms of its
functionality, that is, as a means of reinforcing the status quo. Conflict is understood as a
creative means of balancing and hence maintaining a society. It helps to create and modify
norms, and assures the continuance of the system of natural necessities under changed
conditions. Thus, the theory of regulation is, for Jessop, concerned with the modus vivendiof a
complex process of mutual adjustment and accomodation within and among different institutions
in empiricaIly observable conjunctures.
c) Rack to the Closure and Positivism of determinist Sociology
Jessops conjunctural reformulation of the notion of the relative autonomy dwells on the idea of
intermediate concepts[7]. These are seen as being necessary if the gap between generic and
specific analysis is to be bridged. What is taken for granted, here, is a dualistic separation of the
generic from the specific, since, otherwise, there would be no gap to bridge. However, the net
resuIt of this reformulation is not sufficient because it merely reproduces the problems of the
base-superstructure metaphor in sociological terms. This is so because the conjuncturaI
approach has to identify key variables, such as technological development from mass assembly
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb7http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb7http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb7http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb77/27/2019 Aglietta in England
8/26
lines to new technology or shifting articulations of the economy and politics, which make
everything clear. The identification of key variables abuts on to a determinism and by doing so
marginalises class from the analysis. The conjunctural analysis makes a methodological principle
out of the notion of multiple determinations. so permitting a sociological analysis in terms of the
separation of social life into different distinct economic and political features. For example, the
state-system can adopt specifically fascist or authoritarian or bourgeois-liberal or fordist or
post-fordist forms. The idea of form as a species of something more generic has underpinned
both DIAMA T-style conceptions of general laws which have to be applied to specific social
instances and the conjunctional approach which focuses on intermediate concepts to bridge the
gap between the abstract level of general laws and their concrete application. The concrete is
not seen as a mode of existence of social relations but, rather, as a specific articulation of more
general laws of natural necessity. The consequence of this understanding is that the approach
can identify static structures only because human relations appear merely attendent upon
structural laws. Further, the identification of key variables not only reinforces the idea of
structural laws but provides, also, a sociology of interconnected features without being able to
specify the theoretical relationships between the various elements of the supposed concrete
articulation of structures is, for example, the form of Post-Fordism. Theory becomes non-binding
and arbitrary. This is so because the dualist separations of a fetishised world - the separations of
struggle from structure and of one region of society from another are not called into question
but taken for granted, as the principle of social thought. The separation between structure and
struggle entails a deterministic conceptualisation of capital in that capital becomes a structure of
inescapable lines of development, subordinating social practice to predetermined laws.
In response to his critics, Jessop reasserts that his approach includes the class struggle and that
proper attention is given to its movement. And at the same rime, he insists emphatically that
capital is not class struggle (Jessop 1991). How can one understand these conflicting
statements ? For Jessop, the structure-strategy dialectic does not separate struggle form
structure but shows their complex forms of interaction. The dialectics between structure and
struggle is construed in terms of system theorys conflict theory, so making the disarticulation of
structure and struggle the methodological principle of his approach. For Jessop, the real world of
capitalism is subject to change through the sui generis operation of different regions whose
articulation is dependent on, but not limited to, the action of social subjects. Jessops conception
of social development indicates a degree of voluntarism which, however. is limited by the dualist
conception of structure and struggle : that is. it is restricted by the existence of objective laws
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
9/26
and thus by an objectively given range of options. The term strategy is based upon the
recognition of structurally-given conditions. Jessop uses the term strategy as a concept with
which to grasp the subjective notion of decision-taking and the importance of subjective action
within history. Jessops voluntarist approach is a product of his disarticulation between structure
and class struggle. This disarticulation leads to a deterministic understanding of social
development in which obeisance may be paid to class struggle, but what really counts is the
inescapable lines of tendency and logic of direction established by the objective laws of capitalist
development. The activation of these laws depends on human subjects operating within a
structurally defined environment. Jessops failure to understand the contradictory unity of
structure and struggle leads him to separate human agency from structure, and conversely,
structure from human agency. This dualism underlies his voluntarist approach to subjective
action within history : voluntarism and determinism have always been happy enough to sec
structures as constraining action and action as, complementarily, the limit of the effectivity of
social structures. As a consequence, there is, in Jessop, a dichotomy between a determinist
conception of capitalist development and a voluntarist conception of social action. Jessop
attempts to resolve this dichotomy by declaring the real results of capitalist development to be
contingent [8]. The positivism, structuralism and voluntarism of Jessops approach is
characterized by an understanding of class struggle as a means of reproducing the
structures [9].
Jessop maintains that the transition from one form, such as Fordism, to another form, such as
Post-Fordism, depends on class struggle. He emphasises, however, there there is no objective
developmental logic of capital that inevitably and painlessly ensures passage from one regime to
another (Jessop 1983). The class struggle seems thus to be separated from its mode of
existence and becomes merely one factor amongst others in the contingent and relative
historical development [10]. This is so because the real is understood to be indeterminable
since the real is the outcome of an infinite number of empirical factors, so making capitalist
development contingent and relative. This, however, means that the real world of social conflict
cannot be conceptualised because of its contingent character and its infinite plurality of
determinations. As a consequence, capitalist exploitation of labour in the real world of
empirically observable facts defies analysis. While the analysis is said to focus on the concrete,
the latters movement cannot be conceptualized. This contradiction that is, the contradiction
between determinism and voluntarism - is resolved by Jessop in an irrational and romantic
fashion. The concrete is seen as being determined by capital as a transhistorical subject. Before
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb8http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb8http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb8http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb87/27/2019 Aglietta in England
10/26
dwelling on this romantic and irrational conception of capital in more detail, attention is focused
on Jessops destruction of the Marxian notion of class antagonism.
d) Pluralism, Determinism and Sociologism
Jessop understands the Marxian notion of capitalist social relations as a means of articulating
different systems and, on a lower level of abstraction, of articulating different laws of motion.
The distinction between different systems and laws is already problematic since it destroys the
notion of the inner relationship between different phenomena. The inner nature is abstractly
conceived in terms of the obscure concept of natural necessities. The concrete is construed in
terms of a combination of causal mechanisms and natural necessities. Conceptually
mechanisms and natural necessities are not connected with each other. The concrete is the
result of contingent developments based upon a pluralist diversity of social conflicts which are
merely constrained and/or facilitated by the structural selectivity inscribed in structures. The
conditions of the realisation of a mode of articulation remain indeterminate and contingent. As a
consequence, the articulation of different regions cannot be conceptualised because its
realization is a chance discovery(Fundsache). The empiricism of Jessops approach goes hand-
in-hand with its formalism.
Jessops approach is characterized by the attempt to derive social conflict from pre -formed
categories, so subordinating history to structural laws. The historical constitution of these laws is
presupposed in terms of a logical construct.
It is clear that Jessops approach entails a systematic attempt to destroy the conceptual links
which permit an analysis of the mode of existence of class antagonism. The laws of capitalist
accumulation are not conceived of as a mode of existence of class antagonism but, rather, as a
structural framework which determines the empirically observable class conflict in the real world.
However, class conflict is seen as playing an important part in the reproduction of capitalist
development insofar as the activation of the causal mechanisms of capitalist reproduction
requires active human agents.
Jessop argues that capitalist domination is realised through an emergent and impersonal and
quasi-natural network of social connections. This network is reproduced by human agents and,
according to Jessop, could never be understood without referring to their actions. He insists,
however, that it would be wrong to conceive of class struggle as the starting point because class
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
11/26
struggle is one of the mechanisms in and through which capital accumulation is analysed. The
understanding of the class struggle as a mechanism of capitalist reproduction calls for objective
sociological criteria with which to establish the class relevance of social antagonism (Jessop
1991). The class character of social subjects is defined in terms of their relation to the value
form. For Jessop, the key to deciphering the structural framework of class antagonism is the
concept of surplus value (ibid., p. 148). It is the dominance of the value form in a system of
generalized commodity production which is seen as determining the conceptual identity of
classes, the nature of class relations, the forms of class struggle and the totalizing dynamic of
class struggle and competition within the capitalist mode of production (ibid.).
For Jessop, the value forrn is better understood as a meta-form (ibid.). This notion is founded on
Jessops genus - species distinction. The value meta-form describes the structural framework
within which different forms of value, such as productive, financial, commercial capital, compete
with each other. They compete with each other within the circuit of capital whose structure is
abstractly defined by the value meta-form. Within the circuit of capital we find, according to
Jessop, different logics of capital. These logics connote different accumulation strategies of
competing capital fractions. The value meta-form does not fully determine the course of
accumulation but only the institutional logic and directional dynamic of capitalism, in itself
indeterminate. The value form thus in Jessops view needs to be determined at more concrete
levels of analysis, those of the competitive relation between different capital logics and class
struggle. The value form needs to be overdetermined by an economic class struggle in which
the balance of class forces is moulded by many factors beyond the value form itself (Jessop
1983, p. 90).
The value form is understood not as a process in and through which social relations appear in
the form of relations between things, but as a thing-like structure which determines social
relations. This inversion underlies the empiricism of Jessops approach, according to which it is
contingent institutional forms and political conflicts which determine the development of value
relations and the course of accumulation (Clarke 1991, p. 49 fn 24). The value meta-form
defines the coherence of the capitalist mode of production, a coherence which is achieved, in
practice, through the contingent forces of social conflict in the real world.
The value meta-form is seen merely as constraining, externally, the room for manoeuvre of
different capital logics. The conception of the value form as a value metaform is tautological.
This is so because the determination of the value meta-form in the real world of contesting
social forces presupposes the practical existence of the value meta-form, and vice
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
12/26
versa. However, according to Jessop, the value meta-form is seen as external to its own
determination. This destruction of the Marxian notion of the inner nature of capital is
complemented by the empiricisrn of Jessops approach. For Jessop what realy counts is the
observable pluralism of the contest over income resources. The category of labour is conceived
of in terms of the wage relation which is founded on nothing but itself. Capitalist exploitative
relations are understood in terms of a pluralist distribution struggle over income between the
working class and different capital logics. However, the understanding of social conflict in terms
of empirically observable facts ofdistributive struggles destroys an understanding ofcapital as
an exploitative social relation. Jessops empiricism is complemented by his technicist reading
ofthe law ofvalue. This law is understood as governing the allocation oflabour-time among
different productive activities. The law ofvalue is understood as standing above the class
struggle.
Jessop destroys an understanding ofthe capital-labour relation as an exploitative relation
because he construes class antagonism as external tothe trajectory dynamic ofcapitalism.
Both capital and labour are conceived as human bearers ofstructural laws which stand above
the social conflict. By putting his argument in this way, Jessop treats capital and labour as both
victims ofstructural laws and as creative powers transforming structural forms within the
framework ofnatural necessity. However, this is not tosay that the notion ofthe real power
ofcompetitive struggle and class conflict is conceived ofin terms merely ofan equilibrium
between the social contestants. The combination ofstructural laws and sites ofcontest
reintroduces capital as a transhistorical subject whose dynamic logic is theoretically
presupposed and whose realisation is empirically observable. Within the relation ofcapital and
labour, the class struggle is subordinated tothe basic forms and dynamics ofcapital as the
dominant force (bergreifende Subjekt) (Jessop 1991. p. 165). What this, however, means is
that the social conflict is understood merely in terms ofa theory ofcapital regulation. As Jessop
puts it, the multification ofinstitutional forms and regulative mechanisms ... actually create
significant barriers to a general attack on the capital relation by fragmenting and disorganizing
opposition and resistance and/or channelling it along particular paths where it threatens legs
harm to the core institutions ofcapitalism (Jessop 1988, p. 43). In sum, class conflict is merely
an essential moment in the expanded reproduction ofcapital. The class conflict does not as such
create the totality of nor does it give rise to [capitalisms] dynamic trajectory (Jessop 1991, p.
154). This is because the conceptual identity ofclasses is given by the capital relation itself
rather than being constrained by classes which shape the capital relation (ibid.). The capital
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
13/26
relation stands above class relations. For Jessop, it would be more accurate to conclude that
class antagonism arises because ofthe inherent quality ofthe capital-labour relation than that
this relation is antagonistic because ofthe contingent occurence ofclass struggle and/or
competition (Jessop 1991, pp. 1501). Jessop thus insists that capital is not an antagonistic
social relation and that the antagonism ofclasses arises only in the real world ofmultiple
determination. The Marxist notion ofclass antagonism is thus destroyed in favour ofa
sociological conception ofempirically observable modalities ofsocial conflict. What sense can be
made ofJessops concept capital-labour relation? The capital relation defines the natural
necessity ofcapitalism in terms ofabstract structures, causal mechanisms and capital as an
ideal subject. While proclaiming against the notion ofclass subjectivity, Jessop reintroduces
capital as an ideal subject. The understanding ofcapital as an bergreifendes Subjektmeans,
fundamentally, that the articulation ofcausal mechanisms in the real world ofmultiple
determinations is achieved by the subjectivity ofcapital. While the world is conceived as a world
ofcontingently realized natural necessities (Jessop 1988), the notion ofcontingency relates
only tothe ability ofcapital to achieve a sustained reproduction on the basis ofa successful
accumulation strategy. Jessops structuralist and posivist approach finds it difficuIt to explain
how social conflict and structures interrelate. His equation ofclass struggle with capitalist
strategies is a characteristic response tothis problem.
e) Many Subjects and the Return of Idealism
For Jessop, the real world comprises a complex synthesis of multiple determinations. The
synthesis is seen as being achieved through a process without a subject (Jessop
1985,1988/1991). However, for Jessop, this does not mean that there are no active subjects. On
the contrary, the actualization ofthe natural necessity ofcapitalism is achieved through a
plurality ofcontesting forces : any natural necessity ofcapitalism must be reproduced through
social practices which are always (and inevitably) definite social practices, articulated more or
less closely as moments in specific modes of regulation (Jessop 1988. p. 34). Jessop seeks to
resolve the contradiction between the notion of a process without a subject and the subjectivity
of capital (capitalisthe subject: Jessop 1991, p. 150)) by differentiating capital, as mentioned
above, into a series of logics which are defined in terms of different allocation interests.
Different social subjects pursue different interests, the realisation of which depends on the
facilitating framework of structural moments. Each of these logics is in competition with each
other, so permitting a pluralist struggle between different capital interests. There is no logic of
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
14/26
capital but a series of logics with a family resemblance, corresponding to different modes of
regulation and accumulation regimes (ibid.). The family resemblance mentioned by Jessop
connotes the notion of capital as an bergreifendes Subjekt. Alternative accumulation
strategies connote the activities of different capital subjects seeking to establish a specific
regime of accumulation within the limits of the value form. The term accumulation strategy
indicates a degree of voluntarism which, however, is limited by the dualist conception of
structure and struggle : that is, it is restricted by the existence of objective laws (or : abstract
tendencies) and thus by an objectively given range of options. The term strategy is based upon
the recognition of structurally-given conditions. The dual perspective of structural determination
and class position (Jessop 1985, p. 344) connotes the power of social subjects to modify the
abstract tendencies of capitalism in and through a stable articulation between the invariant
elements of capitalism and the variant elements emergent in different specific forms such as
Fordism and/or Post-Fordism (see Jessop 1988, p. 34). The thing-like structure of the value form
plays the role of an external economic structure which passively defines the limits within which
pluralist social subjects and historical contingency can determine the course of accumulation.
f) Conflict Theory and Empiricism
How does an accumulation strategy succeed ? The term accumulation strategy is founded on
the notion that the social body is incoherent. The segmented parts of this body have no unit y
until they are coordinated into a strategy by a somehow hidden agency of condensation. This
agency cannot be theorized because the result of the dualist movement between structural
determination and class position is said to be contingent. The only indicator as to the character
of this agency is contained in Jessops pluralist conception of social conflict based on the relative
autonomy of the economic, political and ideological domains. For Jessop, the realization of
capitalist development is dependent on the action of different social subjects whose class
positions comprise distinct modes of calculation, patterns of strategic conduct and forms of
struggle. This means that the transition to, for example, Post-Fordism is a resuIt of interactions
on many different terrains and among many different forces. The relative success or failure of a
strategy is seen as depending on unrecognized structural conditions of action [11].
In order to gain purchase on the systemic conditions of action, Jessop distinguishes between
broadly four structural levels. These levels are, first, the empirically observable regularities in
social relations ; second, the basic forms of social relations which together comprise a social
formation ; third, the network of institutions and organisations comprising a social order ; and.
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb11http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb11http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb11http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb117/27/2019 Aglietta in England
15/26
lastly, the structural constraints and conjuncturaI opportunities provided by structural
development for social actors (Jessop 1988, p. 38). According to Jessop, the first level, i.e. the
empirically observable regularities in social relations, does not offer much purchase on the
systemic conditions of action. This is so because it does not provide direct evidence concerning
the basic structures as they resuIt from changing combinations of real mechanisms and
contingent circumstances. The second level, i.e. the basic forms of social relations is too abstract
to give much purchase on strategic conduct. The third level, i.e. the network of institutions,
gives purchase on strategic conduct but it needs to be specified further so as to bring out its
strategic relevance. It is the fourth level which is crucial. Structures need to be examined
relationally, that is, in terms of their structural constraints and conjuncturaI opportunities which
emerge from the strategic orientation of social forces (ibid.).
The mutual conditioning of strategies and variant structures implies that regulation theory has to
analyse the correspondence between the strategic selectivity inscribed in a given mode of
regulation, including the modes of calculation of strategic conduct adopted by social forces to
sustain and/or to transform a given mode of regulation. The notion of structural selectivity
connotes the objectively given range of options available for acting social subjects seeking to
impose some sort of institutional coherence and direction upon a confusing myriad of competing
interests. This is a pluralist conception of social conflict based upon structurally defined
conjunctural moments. These moments involve such elements which can be altered by a given
agent (or set of agents) following their strategic line. Structural ensembles and conjunctural
moments are seen as complex and changeable. The boundaries and activities of structural
ensembles are defined as unstable and the world of strategies is seen as pluralistic and
conjunctural (Jessop 1988). In order to get a hold on the contingent realization of capitalist
development, Jessop advises us to analyse the complex relationship between structural
selectivity inscribed in structures and the structural transformations produced through strategic
interactions of human agents.
How can one understand the emergence of definite social practices which articulate the
structural selectivity in strategic terms ? According to Jessop, the same structural clement can
operate as a structural constraint for some agent(s) at the same rime as it presents itself to
other agent(s) as a "conjunctural opportunity" (Jessop 1988. p. 38). For Jessop, this means that
a scientist has to concentrate on the need of capital in order to be able to assess the strategic
relevance of atomized social agents or groups of agents. However, the need of capital bas to be
assessed strategically in relation to complex conjonctures rather than formally in terms of an
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
16/26
abstract, purely economic, circuit of capital (Jessop 1988/1991, p. 155). How can one define the
need of capital in conjunctural terms ? Since the concrete cannot be theorized (see above), the
need of capital can only be assessed in terms ofa pre-formed and functionalist conception of
the natural necessities of the capitalist system. As already discussed, Jessop sees different social
structures as merelyconstraining and facilitating. This notion is bound up with an endorsement
of the natural necessity of capitalism in terms of structural laws. These laws stand above the
class struggle and entail the existence of capital as anbergreifendes Subjekt. Jessops attempt
to gain purchase on the structure-transforming actions of social subjects reintroduces the notion
of capital as an bergreifendes Subjekt. This notion destroys the concept of pluralist social
subjects which was introduced in order to avoid an approach predicated on the notion of a
transhistorical subject. For Jessop, structures are explicit reference points for strategic
calculations and comprise partly recognised and partially unacknowledged sets of structural
constraints and conjunctural opportunities. In order to understand the realisation of capital
reproduction in the real world, Jessop urges us to focus on the need of capital, a need which is
already presupposed abstractly. As a consequence, Jessops notion of the action of social
subjects is not only predicated on a sort of individualistic reformulation of the Marxian notion of
class struggle but also, and as a mater of entirely distinct theorising, on a sort of idealist
reformulation of capital as a transhistorical subject. All social subjects are seen as mere
participants in the global capitalist subject. Social conflicts are thus seen as facilitating forces
which reproduce the capitalist system in the real world of opportunity. Social conflict is thus
construed as a creative force. The structurally transforming action of social subjects is creative
in that it articulates structural opportunities in practical terms, so realizing the dynamic direction
and institutional logic of capital in the real world.
g) Theory : An End in itself
However, even if one were to accept Jessops reformulation of Marxism, it remains still unclear
how the incoherent body of pluralist struggles can be transformed into a definite strategy. In
order to understand how capitalism is reproduced we must examine the structural selectivity
inscribed in structures (Jessop 1988/1991. p. 159). How can one understand structural
selectivity? Jessop tackles this problem by stressing that it would be wrong to reduce a
structural category to, and/or derive it from, a strategic category, and to derive a single strategy
from a given structure (Jessop 1988, p. 41). This is so because structural categories belong to
the realm of the system which is disconnected from the concrete realm of social practices and
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
17/26
because there are always competing strategies. Further, the relationship between different
structural elements have only a relative unity. Lastly, the outcome of the dialectic between
structure and strategy is always contingent. Still, what constitutes selectivity ? It seems there is
no answer to this question and to the question of how the reciprocal transformation of structures
and strategies is realised in the real world of capitalism. This, however, means that theory loses
its truth criteria. Jessop insists that structural constraints and conjunctural opportunities emerge
from the strategic orientation of social forces (Jessop 1988, p. 38). In turn, however, this means
that structural selectivity is defined by and remains at the mercy of- the contingently emerging
transformation of social reality. This, further, implies that the notion of structural selectivity
defies conceptualization and that it can be observed only empirically. As in Critical Realism (see
Gunn 1991a,b), Jessops argument comprises a vicious circularity of presuppositions. He
presupposes structural selectivity as conditioning the action of social subjects and then he
presupposes that structural constraints emerge from the strategic conduct of social subjects.
Each is supposed to make sense of the other. In other words, the real world lies outside theorys
grasp. Jessops realist ontologyturns against itself as much as, therefore, it offers no concept
of the real. The upshot of Jessops attempt to reformulate Marxism is a nominalist and
normative theory. Jessops (1986a, 1990) flirtation with Luhmann is logically conclusive as it
faciliates the destruction of Marxist theory in favour of a descriptive sociology concerned with
system maintenance.
If one were to follow Jessop, all theory would be able to achieve is to say that the real world is
changing within a framework of structurally defined parameters whose concrete implications
defy conceptualisation. According to Jessop we know that there are different subjects who se
activities are more or less coordinated, whose activities meet more or less resistance from other
forces, and whose strategies are pursued within a structural context which is both constraining
and facilitating (Jessop 1988, p. 43). We know also that there are signifiant barriers to a general
attack on the capital relation (ibid.), that there is a real scope for class struggle and that the
success of the nth strategy depends on its complementarity to all other relevant strategies
within the overall structural ensemble (ibid. pp. 42,43). This body of knowledge, however, is
insubstantial because of the complex web of cont ingencies. Any conceptualisation of the real is
doomed to failure because the real world is a world of discovery and of contingently emergent
realities. Regulation is, consequently, defined as a study of the complex process of mutual
adjustment and accomodation within and among different institutions (Jessop 1988/1991, p.
152). The research project of regulation theory degenerates iota a merely empirical study of
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
18/26
institutional intersections ; and a research project lacking a conceptual framework is a
contradiction in terms.
h) The Retum of the State
On the assomption that the only purchase on the real world is some sort of empiricist
descriptive sociology, how is it possible to comprehend, despite the complex jungle of multiple
social forces, a definite accumulation strategy ? Jessop insists that there are a number of
alternative accumulation strategies expressing different fractional interests and alliances. There
is thus a need for an external power to impose regulative mechanisms upon the plurality of
contesting capital logics. This power is the state. Jessop brings the state back in as the
totalizing regulative institution. For Jessop (1983), the pattern of accumulation is uItmately
determined by the accumulation strategy adopted by the state. However, there is no unique
accumulation strategy available to the state but, rather, a range of alternative strategies. Does
the state therefore simply take an arbitrary decision ? To understand which accumulation
strategy is adopted by the state requires an analysis of political conflicts through which strategic
issues are resolved (see Jessop 1983). The political conflicts between different accumulation
strategies is discussed in terms of different hegemonic projects (Jessop 1983,1985). Jessop
claims that the interplay between structural development and hegemonic strategies provide
mechanisms that melt different social systems together, so permitting a corresponding social
cohesion of ideological, political and economic patterns.
V. Multiple Determinations and Thatcherism
Jessop understood Thatcherism as a hegomonic project which breaks with the past by
developing towards Post-Fordism (see Jessop 1986b). Thatcherism was seen as an interplay of
trial-and-error policies which concide with relative autonomous forces of the market (ibid., p.
8). Jessops approach replays the determinist-voluntarist dichotomy so typical of structuralist
approaches. Social reality is, in Jessop, constituted by the independent logics of political and
ideological domains, forcing the scientific mind to follow, in descriptive terms, the strategic line
of capital in the face of various dilemmas, risks, uncertainties and complexities, emergent
strategies, trial and error techniques etc. (Jessop et al. 1988, p. 8). The articulation between
different complex determinations was achieved by Thatcherism. As a consequence "Thatcherism"
was reified as a subject which stands above class relations. This is, given the insistence that
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
19/26
complex historical phenomena are best analysed as a complex resultant of multiple
determinations (ibid., p. 53), a surprising move. Thatcherism was said to have known
instinctively that there could be no way back to the old Keynesian welfare state (Jessop 1986b,
p. 8). How did Thatcherism "know" ?
Jessop (et al. 1988) emphasized the development and specifity of the emergent strategic line
pursued by Thatcher (p. 8). His work focused on actual strategies and policies and their ad hoc
emergent character (p. 8). Since Thatcherism was a strategic line (p. 9) and since there is no
single causal mechanism determining social development (p. 53), political events need to be
seen as a complex product of many different causes and circumstances (p. 29). In order to
understand what happens, an adequate account which searches for deeper significances of
historical development must establish the mediations between underlying and more immediate
causes (p. 29). What needs to be done ? Since the theory is deemed to be correct, Jessop
asserted that there are many Thatcherisms (p. 9). This deeper knowledge derived both from a
priori theoretical arguments and from our post hoc reflections on changes in the strategic line
adopted by Thatcherism (p. 9). The notion of Thatcherism was thus based on the idea that the
real cannot be determined since there are many causes and an infinite number of factors.
However, Jessop destroys the interesting notion of many Thatcherisms by declaring that
Thatcherism has adopted a strategic line. If there were many Thatcherisms, how, then, could
one depict Thatcherisms strategic line ? A strategic line evolved from the strategic vision of
Thatcherism (p. 11). This vision had given direction and coherence to policies in the face of
structural dilemmas, political failures, emerging contradictions and resistance. The notion of a
multiplicity of diverse factors was further undermined by Jessops economic determinism. He
argued that Thatcherisms vision was determined economically. This is so because one needs to
have an understanding of the decisive economic nucleus of hegemony in order to sec the
structural source of power (p. 16). Did Thatcherism "know" because it expressed the functionally
presupposed need of capital ?
Jessop supplies a theoretical maze. On the one band, there is no single cause, whilst, on the
other, the economic is determining. On the one band, Jessop isolates different phenomena from
the social whole, and, on the other, he seeks to reconnect phenomena in an external way. On
the one hand, Jessop proposes the separation of social existence into different structural
regions, and, on the other, he seeks to articulate the specific interconnections ofthese regions.
On the one band, Jessop claims that there are underlying laws ofmotion, and, on the other, he
introduces subjective mechanisms for these laws actualization. Jessop urges that the real is
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
20/26
indeterminable since it is mediated by an infinite number of factors. At the same time, he
introduces a subject (Thatcherism) which leads the UK towards Post-Fordism. Jessops
assessment of the need of capital is not only based upon a theoretical maze but also on a
tautological description ofsocial reality. First of all the outward appearance of reality is taken for
granted (multiple causes), and then it is in the light of this outward appearance of reality that
social development is assessed. By attempting to grasp the development of the British state in
this way, his analysis of Thatcherism proliferates structures which are not only static and
fetishized but who se theoretical status remains unclear.
Given this, what sense can be attached to the notion of a left alternative to the (thatcherist)
transition to Post-Fordism ? In general terms, an alternative strategy must take into account the
constraining and facilitating selectivity of structures. Different calculating subjects are differently
located in relation to structural constraint and opportunity and they calculate their strategies
over different time horizons and/or spatial boundaries (Jessop 1988, p. 42). A left alternative
must learn from Thatcherism because it must take into account current changes and adapt its
strategy to them (Jessop 1988/1991, p. 163). Further, the viability of alternative strategies
depends on their strategic conduct over a more or legs extensive social terrain, embracing
various fields of action. Any viable alternative strategy has to enter into different types of
alliances with other social forces (Jessop 1988, p. 42). The upshot is a left hegemonic project,
installating an accumulation regime based on party spirit (ibid., p. 50). The party is the place in
which social forces acquire consciousness, thereby transcending individualism and the corporate
interests of specific groups. It is through the parties that classes become the state [12]. He
affirms the view of Haeusler/Hirsch (1987), according to which the party system plays a key
role in mediating between the state and individuals and institutions in society (Jessop 1988, pp.
50-1). However, the aggregation of man y pluralistic, antagonistic interests in society and
pressures of electoral competition involves that the parties of government both facilitate and
legitimate relatively coherent state actions concerned with societal reproduction (ibid. p. 51).
What needs to be done ? In the absence of a revolutionary party, revolution has to be
postponed sine dei(see Holloway 1991,1992). By implication, Marxist theory has to
accommodate to the conjuncturaI opportunities created by structural selectivity. Marxist theory
has to become a more sophisticated theory of capitalist regulation so as to effect a leftist
refashioning of the real world of capitalism. Unfortunately, given the complexities and
contingencies of the real world and the systemic constraints on action, Jessop and his co-authors
refrain from providing detailed recommendations for the Labour Party or the Left. Their concern
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb12http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb12http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb12http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb127/27/2019 Aglietta in England
21/26
is rather to outline the broad issues that any successful left strategy must confront (Jessop et al.
1987). Altogether this outline is restricted to the parameters of existing reality. The Left has to
confront the existing post-fordist realities in order to articulate a viable hegemonic project and to
ensure its popular appeal so as to reform the institutions of social administration in a fair and
just way. In sum, the political implications of Jessops reformulation of regulation theory are that
Marxism has to refrain from the scholarly work of negation [13] in favour of advising political
groups as to the development of norms, modes of ca1culation and procedures which could gain
popular support Marxism has to supply sociological knowledge concerning the conjunctural
opportunities already inscribed in structural development. Marxism needs to assume the role of
a political adviser. The political implication of Jessops approach is that of an opportunist politics
of the conjuncture, aiming at effecting a leftist activation of natural necessities.
VI. Conclusion
Approaches such as Jessops, which are predicated on the disarticulation of structure and
struggle, involve no internal connection between the political and the economic on the basis of
the constitutive power of labour. The central methodological misunderstanding of such
approaches is the separation of the social whole into different regions each of which is seen as
having its formaI structure, its own laws and logic. Such approaches cannot take account of
fundamental historical developments in and through the constitutive power of labour because
labour plays no role in the internal logic of the different regions. Labour is separated from capital
and is reduced to merely an empirical factor of a historical development which is both contingent
and relative. Instead of investigating the constitution and forms of social materiality, such
approaches raise the formal aspect of social existence (i.e. the fragmented character of society)
to the level of an methodological principle. At the same time, these approaches are forced to
introduce subjective notions, such as accumulation strategy or hegemonic project, so as to
provide a link between perceived modalities of the states concrete existence (e.g. the fordist
state) and its formal structure. These subjective notions are, in turn, constrained by the
systemic rules and "natural necessities" of capitalism.
Jessops approach is a typical response to the methodological misunderstanding of structuralism.
He aims at giving greater weight to historical analysis by combining abstract theory with a
theory of historical developments. The combination of the concrete with an abstract theoretical
structure implies the modelling of social phenomena on to pre-formed concepts which for their
part are placed at the mercy of the historical contingency they seek to render intelligible. In
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb13http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb13http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb13http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nb137/27/2019 Aglietta in England
22/26
other words the concepts stand above historical developments. An analysis which takes the
fragmented character of bourgeois society for granted and which seeks to trace the causal
interconnections of such fragments can not grasp their historical development because it refuses
to risk the methodic assertion of the real in and through abstraction.
An approach such as Jessops, turning as it does upon structural integration, is an approach
which is complicit in the fetishisation of human relations as relations of things. Further, such an
approach runs the risk of conceptual collapse. Thisis so because such an approach can not
justify its concepts. For example, the assumption that the real world is divided into different
regions raises the question of the interdependence, that is, the structural adequacy of different
regions such as the political. Firstly, to what is the political adequate ; secondly, what
determines the adequacy of the political ; thirdly, what is the criterion with which to define
adequacy ? Only three solutions are possible. Firstly, the adequacy of the political is measured in
terms of its output concerning the requirements of the economic. Such a solution opens the way
for an economistic Marxism, the political superstructure arising from it however sophisticated a
fashion the economic base. Such a view concentrates on the economic as the determining
structure, thug making the political merely attendant upon the inescapable lines of economic
development. The second solution is to introduce a new set of concepts with which to justify the
first level of concepts. However, the new set of concepts needs to be justified itself, leading to
the introduction of new concepts and so on. This solution reproduces the problem it claims to
resolve through an infinite regress of metatheories (see Gunn 1989). The third solution is to
abnegate a conceptual understanding in favour of a descriptive sociology of corresponding
features among different subsystems. Such a solution sees the economic and the political as
autonomous systems which generate causal interrelations through asui generis operation of
their internal laws. As a consequence, theory must identify reciprocal elements which exist in
different subsystems (e.g. mass production and demand management and the ideology of social
consensus). No explanation can be given of how a reciprocal matrix of mutually supporting
elements develops. The only possible explanation is to declare such a matrix to be a contingent
articulation among different autonomous systems. This solution interprets historical development
in terms of its more or legs close approximation to a model whose elements are not
conceptualised but, rather, presupposed. The problem of justifying concepts is thereby avoided
only because the historical development is understood to be contingent, thus allowing the
concepts to be contingent and arbitrary themselves. Further the concepts can be readily justified
on the basis of the real: it is what it is. Since, for example, we can observe the hegemonic
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
23/26
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
24/26
Aglietta 1979,A Theory of Capitalist Regulation, Verso : London.
Agnoli 1990, Die Destruktion aIs Bestimmung des Gelehrten in drftiger Zeit, Konkret1/1990.
Bonefeld 1987/1991, Reformulation of State Theory,Capital&Class n 33. reprinted in
Bonefeld/Holloway (eds.) 1991.
Bonefeld 1992, Social Constitution and the Form of the Capitalist State in Bonefeld / Gunn /
Psychopedis 1992a. Bonefeld / Holloway (eds.) 1991. Post-Fordism and Social Form :A Marxist
Dedate on the Post-Fordist State Macmillan : London.
Bonefeld / Gunni (eds.) 1992a, Open Marxism Vol 1 : History and Dialectics, Psychopedis, Pluto
Press : London.
Bonefeld / Gunn (eds.) 1992b, Open Marxism Vol. II : Theory and Practice, Psychopedis, Pluto
Press : London.
Clarke 1983, Comments on Jessop,Kapitalistate 10/11, Berkeley.
Clarke 1988 / 1991. Overaccumulation, Class Struggle and the Regulation
Approach. Capital&Class, n 36, reprinted in Bonefeld / Holloway (ed.) 1991.
Clarke 1990. New utopias for old : Fordist dreams and Post-Fordist
fantasies. Capital&Class, n 42.
Clarke 1991, Introduction to The State Debate, edited by Clarke, Macmillan : London 1991.
Elster 1987, Making Sense of Marx, Cambridge University Press : Cambridge.
Gunn 1989, Marxism and philosophy.Capital&Class. n037.
Gunn 1991a. Reclaiming Experience,Science as Culture n 11.
Gunn 1991 b. Marxism, Metatheory and Critique, in Bonefeld / Holloway 1991.
Hall / Jaques (eds.) 1989, New Times, Lawrence and Wishart : London.
Haeusler / Hirsch 1987, Regulation und Parteien im bergang zum "Post-Fordismus",Das
Argument, n 165. Holloway 1988/1991, The Great Bear : Post-Fordism and Class
Struggle,Capital&Class, n 36, reprinted in Bonefeld / Holloway (eds.) 1991.
Holloway 1991, Capitalis Class Struggle, in Bonefeld / Holloway (eds.) 1991.
Holloway 1992 Crisis, Fetishism, Class Composition, in Bonefeld / Gunn / Psychopedis (eds.)
1992b.
Jessop 1982, The Capitalist Store, Martin-Robertson : Oxford. Jessop 1983, Accumulation
Strategies, State Forms and Hegemonie Projects,Kapitalistllte, n 10/11.
Jessop 1985, Nicos Poulantzas : Marxist Theory and Political Strategy, Macmillan : London 1985.
Jessop 1986a, The Economy, the State and the Law : Theories of Relative Autonomy and
Autopoietic Closure,European University Institute, Florence 1986.
7/27/2019 Aglietta in England
25/26
Jessop 1986b, Warum es keinen Kohlismus gibt,Links, 1/1986.
Jessop 1988, Regulation Theories in Retrospect and Prospect,Staatsaufgaben, University of
Bielefeld, Zentrum fur interdisziplinare Forschung, n 1, Bielefeld.
Jessop 1988/1991, Regulation Theory, Post-Fordism and the State : More than a reply to
Werner Bonefeld,Capital&Class, n 34, reprinted in Bonefeld/Holloway (eds.) 1991.
Jessop 1991, Polar Bears and Class Struggle : Less than a Self-Criticism, in Bonefeld / Holloway
(eds.) 1991.
Jessop et al. 1987, Popular Capitalism, Flexible Accumulation and Lef1 Strategy,New Left
Review. N 165. Jessop et al. 1988, Thatcherism, Polity : London.
Jessop 1990, State Theory, Polity : Cambridge. Migliaro/Misurace 1982, The Theory of Modern
Bureaucracy, in Sasson (ed.),Approaches to Gramsci, Writers and Readers, London.
Peh1ez / Holloway 1990, Learning to Bow : Post-Fordism and 1991 Technological
Determinism,Science as Culture, n 8 ; reprinted in Bonefeld / Holloway (eds.) 1991.
Psychopedis 1991, Crisis of Theory in Contemporary Social Sciences, in Bonefeld / Holloway
(eds.) 1991.
Sasson 1987, Gral11scis Politics.Hutchingson : London
[1] There is no distinctive British regulation school. in Britain, the only theoretical contribution to
the RA has come from Bob Jessop. A popularisation of post-fordist ideas could be found in the
pages of Marxism Today (see the collection of articles edited by Hall/Jaques 1989).
[2] See the collection of articles edited by Bonefeld/Holloway 1991.
[3] See Jessop 1983, 1985, 1986a, 1988, 1988/1991
[4] The following part is heavily dependent on Clarke (1991) and. especially, Psychopedis
(1991).
[5] The notion of realist ontology is taken from R Bhaskar. Bhaskar insists to reassert the basic
Marxist principle according to which the world is materialist and subject to change through the
operation of economic, political and social structures which are dependent upon, but not limited
to, human agency. Bhaskars jumble sale of ideas has been criticized by R. Gunn (1989, 1991).
[6] On the connection between technological determinism and the post-fordist debate see
Palaez/Holloway 1990/1991 and Clarke 1990.
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh1http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh1http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh1http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh3http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh3http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh3http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh4http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh4http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh4http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh5http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh5http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh5http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh6http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh6http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh6http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh6http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh5http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh4http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh3http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh2http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh17/27/2019 Aglietta in England
26/26
[7] The following section is taken from the introduction to Bonefeld/Gunn/Psychopedis (eds.)
1992a.
[8] Voluntarism and determinism are theoretically complementary, bath expressions of the
separation between class struggle and capital (Holloway 1991, p. 170/1 ; see also Bonefeld
1987/1991, 1992 ; Clarke 1983.1991).
[9] See Clarkes (1991) critique of Jessop.
[10] See Psychopedis 1991.
[11] As in Rational Choice Marxism (see Elster 1987, esp. ch. 1), subjects operate and calculate
rationally and individually within a framework of unreeogniszed rules which they seek to
transform through strategic conduct so as to maximize their fortunes.
[12] Jessop (1988) refers affirmatively to the work of Migliaro and Misuraca (1982) and Sasson
(1987).
[13] Scholarly work is seen here, following Agnoli (1990), as a negative task.
[14] See the contributions to the collection of articles edited by Bonefeld/Gunn/Psychopedis
Open Marxism Vol 1 : History and Dialectics and Open Marxism Vol II : Theory and Practice.
Pluto Press : London 1992.
http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh7http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh7http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh7http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh8http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh8http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh8http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh11http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh11http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh11http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh12http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh12http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh12http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh13http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh13http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh13http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh14http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh14http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh14http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh14http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh13http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh12http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh11http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh10http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh9http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh8http://multitudes.samizdat.net/spip.php?page=imprimer&id_article=1062#nh7