198
A Classicist under Constraint Justus Lipsius and the Revival of Stoic Determinism in the De Constantia Peter I. Osorio Honors Thesis Margaret Graver, Advisor Department of Classics Dartmouth College May 2012

A Classicist under Constraint Justus Lipsius and the Revival of Stoic

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • A Classicist under Constraint

    Justus Lipsius and the Revival of Stoic Determinism in the De Constantia

    Peter I. Osorio

    Honors Thesis

    Margaret Graver, Advisor

    Department of Classics

    Dartmouth College

    May 2012

  • Verum quid Seneca, quid Epictetus, quibus te inhaerere video, nobis ad salutem conferunt?

    -L. Torrentius I. Lipsio (1584 04 05)

    Spirat nescio quis calor in Senecae aut Epicteti scriptis, qui ad lectorem quoque pervenit, nec disserere

    illi magis de virtute videntur, quam inserere et inculcare.

    -I. Lipsius L. Torrentio (1584 05 06)

  • Table of Contents

    Abbreviations 1

    Preface 3

    Chapter 1: Justus Lipsius and the De Constantia 5

    Chapter 2: Senecas De Providentia 27

    Chapter 3: Stoic Determinism 41

    Chapter 4: Lipsian Determinism 76

    Chapter 5: The Physiologia 126

    Chapter 6: The De Constantia Reconsidered 150

    Summary of Conclusions 182

    Appendix: Seneca, Epistulae Morales 65.2-14 184

    Bibliography 188

  • 1

    Abbreviations

    Apul. Pl. Apuleius De platone

    August. CD. Augustine De civitate dei

    Calc. Tim. Calcidius Timaeus, commentary

    Cic. Fat. Cicero De fato

    Cic. Fin. Cicero De finibus

    Cic. Parad. Cicero Paradoxa Stoicorum

    Cic. Phil. Cicero Orationes Phillipicae

    De con. Iusti Lipsi De Constantia Libri Duo

    Div. Hal. Iusti Lipsi Diva Virgo Hallensis

    DL Diogenes Laertius Lives

    Ep. ad Belg. Iusti Lipsi Epistolarum Selectarum Centuriae ad Belgas

    Ep. ad Germ Iusti Lipsi Epistolarum Selectarum Centuria Singularis ad Germanos

    Ep. ad Ital. Iusti Lipsi Epistolarum Selectarum Centuria Singularis ad Italos et

    Hispanos

    Ep. Misc. Iusti Lipsi Epistolarum Selectarum Centuriae Miscellaneae

    Ep. Quaest. Iusti Lipsi Epistolicarum Quaestionum Libri V

    Epic. Diss. Epictetus Dissertationes

    Eusebius Praep. ev. Eusebius Praeparatio Evangelica

    Gel. Aulus Gellius Noctes Atticae

    ILE Iusti Lipsi Epistolae

    Isid. Orig. Isidore Origines

    Jerome De vir. ill. Jerome De viris illustribus

    Lactantius Div. Inst. Lactantius Divinae Institutiones

    LS Long and Sedley 1987

    Luc. Lucan Bellum Civile

    Man. Iusti Lipsi Manuductionis ad Stoicum Philosophiam Libri Tres

    Nem. Nat. Hom Nemesius De hominis natura

    Origen Cels. Origen Contra Celsum

    Pol. Iusti Lipsi Politicorum sive Civilis Doctrinae Libri Sex

    PS Iusti Lipsi Physiologiae Stoicorum Libri Tres

    Quint. Inst. Quintilian Institutio Oratoria

    Sen. Ben. Seneca De Beneficiis

    Sen. Clem. Seneca De Clementia

    Sen. Con. Seneca De Constantia Sapientis

    Sen. Cons. ad Hel. Seneca De Consolatione ad Helviam

    Sen. Ep. Seneca Epistulae Morales

    Sen. Nat. Seneca Naturales Quaestiones

    Sen. Prov. Seneca De Providentia

    Stob. Ecl. Phys. Stobaeus Eclogae Physicae et Ethicae

  • 2

    SVF von Armin, Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta

    Thom. Aq. SCG Thomas Aquinas Summa Contra Gentiles

    Thom. Aq. ST Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologica

    Tim. Plato Timaeus

  • 3

    Preface

    In the summer before my freshman fall, I attended a classics summer program at

    Dartmouth. There, I enrolled in Professor Gravers seminar on Marcus Porcius Cato. Incidental

    to reading Livys biography of Cato and Lucans Pharsalia, I was introduced to Senecan

    philosophy. Over the past four years, I have returned to Seneca and his dialogues, the De

    providentia in particular, for his talent to calm and to keep me in appreciation of life. While I

    read Seneca for my benefit, I did not consider my faith threatened by a study of Stoicism.

    Personal interest of compatibilism between Christianity and Stoicism led to my introduction to

    Justus Lipsius, and this thesis is the product of the past year of study. I have made a conscious

    effort to separate personal opinion from my examination of Justus Lipsius and the De constantia,

    and it is everywhere my intention to present an unbiased and critical evaluation of Lipsian

    determinism. I have inevitably come to feel a close kinship with Lipsius, and I am pleased to

    contribute to the literature on this imperfect but endearing classicist.

    I am immensely grateful to Margaret Graver. Her insights on Stoic philosophy were

    necessary to the development of this thesis; her demanding precision of language and reasoning

    has corrected my faults; she has improved my Latin and edited my translations; she has given me

    an appreciation for the intricacies of Stoic physics; but most importantly, she has kindled in me a

    deeper resolution to study classics. I am honored to end my undergraduate studies under the

    guidance of Professor Graver, who first introduced me to Stoicism almost four years ago. I thank

    Professor Ariane Schwartz for agreeing to act as a reader for this thesis and for her help in the

    early phases of this study. Her knowledge of resources for Renaissance texts saved me much

    trouble and hassle. I am also grateful to Professor James Murphy of the government department,

    for his insights early in the development of this thesis. I especially thank Professor Pramit

  • 4

    Chaudhuri. Without his lectures in Epics of Greece and Rome during my freshman fall, I

    would not have studied classics further. His subsequent instruction in Senecan drama, Valerius

    Flaccus, and neo-Latin tragedy has refined my appreciation for the Latin language. For his

    sincere concern for my intellectual and stylistic development, I owe him my regard. I thank my

    other professors of the Classics departmentProfessors Stewart, Ulrich, Kretler, Tell, and

    Farofor their dedication to teaching. They have made Reed hall an easy place for learning. I

    also thank my high school Latin teachers, Mr. Lou Latina, may he rest in peace, and Sister

    Lorraine Forester; they prepared me well. I thank my friends, especially Thomas, Andy, Henry

    and Kelsey, for their fellowship. Finally, I thank my father, mother, sister and brother. They have

    been exceedingly patient as I, perhaps too often, dismissed their calls and emails while writing in

    the library. Above all, I thank my parents for their twenty-two years of sacrifice and support that

    have allowed me to study classics at DartmouthI love you.

  • 5

    Chapter 1: Justus Lipsius and the De Constantia

    1.1. Introduction

    Justus Lipsius (1547-1606) was a Flemish classicist of the Northern Renaissance. Along

    with Erasmus and Hugo Grotius, Justus Lipsius is among the foremost names of Dutch

    humanism. He is considered the father of Neostoicism, a philosophical movement in the

    sixteenth and seventeenth centuries that sought to syncretize ancient Stoicism with contemporary

    Christianity.1 Guillame Du Vair drew directly from the Stoic ideas Lipsius promoted and made

    similar efforts to combine Stoicism with Christian teaching. Du Vairs Philosophie morale des

    Stoques (1594) expressed his hope that his audience would derive comfort from a combination

    of Stoic doctrine and Christian teaching.2 In a similar fashion, Francisco de Quevedo drew upon

    Lipsius Manuductio for the Nombre, origen, inteno, recomendacin y decencia de la doctrina

    estoica (1635).3 Others who took direct influence from Lipsius include: Montesquieu, Bishop

    Bossuet and Pierry Bayle in France; Francis Bacon and Joseph Hall in England; and Juan de

    Vera y Figueroa and Francisco Sanchez in Spain.4 Lipsius work on Stoicism would later inform

    the philosophical systems of Spinoza and Descartes, while Leibniz and Locke used Lipsius as a

    source for information about Stoic philosophy.5

    Lipsius, however, was not the first Renaissance scholar to write on the similarity between

    the philosophy of the Stoa and Christianity. The revival of Stoicism in the Renaissance began

    with Petrarch (1304-74) and his endorsement of Stoic moral philosophy in De remediis utriusque

    fortunae (1366). Nevertheless, Petrarch firmly rejected Stoic doctrines that are in conflict with

    1 Papy 2011.

    2 This work appeared as preface to his edition of Epictetus Enchiridion. See Kraye 1988, 371-2.

    3 Kraye 1988, 372-3.

    4 Papy 2011.

    5 Kraye 1996, 152; Schrijvers 1986, 279; Papy 2011. J.B. Schneewind also links Lipsius and Du Vair with the

    perfectionist ethical theories of Descartes and Leibniz (Cooper 2004, 26). See Schneewind, The Invention of

    Autonomy (1998) chapters 9 and 12.

  • 6

    Christianitye.g., that suicide is tolerable.6 Petrarch, in his Secretum, and Rabelais (d. 1553),

    in his Gargantua, Le Tiers Livre and Le Quart Livre, played with the idea of combining the two

    ethical systems of Stoicism and Christianity, yet both always remained firm in their

    subordination of philosophy to religion.7 Meanwhile, other writers of the Renaissance purposely

    called to mind conflicts between Stoic and Christian moral teachings. Lorenzo Valla (d. 1457)

    criticized the Stoic position that virtue was its own reward, and Montaigne (1533-92) regarded

    the model of the Stoic sage as not only impractical, but presumptuous as well.8 Salutati remarked

    that not even Christ met the Stoics demand for apatheia, and Calvin likewise rejected the Stoic

    claim that pity was a vice, arguing that Christ wept for others.9 Among theologians like Valla or

    Calvin, who saw rising appreciation for Stoicism as a threat to religion, one figure stands out for

    his unconventional relationship with Stoicism. Pietro Pomponazzi (1462-1525) endorses Stoic

    metaphysics in his De fato (which he dared not publish in his lifetime), even though he believed

    that doing so was at odds with Catholic teaching.10

    In the final book of the work, Pomponazzi

    discloses his preference for Stoic determinism and subjects all events to natural and astral laws.

    Nevertheless he considered himself to be a devout Christian. Pomponazzi exemplifies the

    principle that religion and philosophy may be diametrically opposed yet still coexist in the mind

    of the thinker.11

    In general, Stoic moral philosophy is harmonious at many points with Christian ethics.

    Early Christian writers were themselves informed by Stoic ethical doctrines (see 1.4). Although

    writers like Petrarch had already sought to harmonize Christian ethics with Stoic moral

    6 Kraye 2007, 100.

    7 Kraye 1988, 368.

    8 Kraye 1988, 363, 366-7.

    9 Kraye 1988, 368-9. Calvin rejects Stoic ethical doctrines regarding virtue and vice in his preface to his

    commentary of Senecas De clementia and in his Intitutio religionis Christianae (III. 7.2, 8.9). 10

    Poppi 1988, 656-7. 11

    Poppi 1988, 660.

  • 7

    philosophy, there was little effort by Lipsius time to make Stoic physics compatible with

    Christian natural philosophy. Pomponazzi wrote privately about Stoic physics, but he did not

    attempt to harmonize them. What, then, did Lipsius Neostoicism entail: an adaption of Stoic

    ethical doctrines that others had already attempted or an incorporation of Stoic physics as well?

    In this thesis, I examine how Lipsius revives Stoic thought. I am interested in both the

    extent to which Stoicism informs Lipsius philosophy and the manner in which Lipsius presents

    Stoicism. I limit my examination to Lipsius seminal Neostoic work, De Constantia Libri Duo

    (1584).12

    The De constantia was Lipsius first major philosophical work and the only one that is

    explicitly devoted to promulgating a philosophical program.13

    R.V. Young has called the De

    constantia arguably the most significant, influential, and characteristic work of northern

    humanism.14

    The De constantia is concerned with an ethical problem, and Lipsius employs

    determinism to inform his solution. Since determinism is central to the main arguments of the De

    constantia, I narrow the focus of my study to the set of topics involving determinism: causation,

    providence, fate, chance, moral responsibility, and agency. In particular, I am interested in the

    problematic position Lipsius places himself when he speaks on determinism. Namely, I find that

    deterministic (and characteristically Stoic) thought is more pervasive than what Lipsius explicitly

    states about providence and fate. I conclude my study by considering the factors that likely

    caused Lipsius to restrain the presence of Stoic determinism in the De constantia. Lipsius

    natural philosophy is now beginning to receive scholarly interest (see Hirai 2011), but no modern

    scholarsas far as I am aware have spent significant effort evaluating Lipsius determinism as

    presented in the De constantia.

    12

    The earliest publication of the De constantia was August 2, 1583 (ILE I, 83 08 02), but by convention it is usually

    dated to 1584. 13

    Lipsius two later treatises on Stoicism are written with the explicit goal of aiding in the study of Senecas prose

    works by outlining the philosophical system to which he subscribed. 14

    Young 2011, xvii.

  • 8

    In the remainder of this chapter, I introduce Justus Lipsius and outline important details

    of his life. I then provide a sketch of the De constantia, its constituent parts, and important

    arguments. I end this chapter by discussing the important role Seneca plays in Lipsius thought

    and the reception of Seneca that Lipsius inherits. Seneca was a well-received writer of Stoic

    ethics, and a personal favorite of Lipsius, and so I use Seneca as a starting point for my study. In

    chapter two, my intent is to evaluate how well Senecas moral philosophy can explain any Stoic

    influence in Lipsius determinism. In his ethical treatise, De providentia, Seneca has much to say

    about determinism that would be useful for Lipsius. Therefore, I compare Senecas De

    providentia to the De constantia. I find considerable Senecan influence on Lipsius method of

    using determinism as a consolation against public evils. Lipsius arguments, however, go beyond

    the scope that Seneca covers in his De providentia. Apart from his comforting words to the

    reader, Lipsius details a deterministic system of thought that leads to the main arguments of the

    De constantia. In order to evaluate whether Lipsius is drawing upon works of Stoic physics in

    addition to moral philosophy, I specify in chapter three an account of Stoic determinism that is

    accessible and known to Lipsius. In chapter four, I analyze Lipsian determinism as presented in

    the De constantia and judge it against the narrative of Stoic determinism outlined in the previous

    chapter. I find that Lipsian determinism is largely informed by Stoic sources, although there are

    some issues. On several occasions, Lipsius misrepresents Stoicism and threatens the consistency

    of his own determinism by making contradictory claims. In chapter five, I more fully consider

    these issues by examining Lipsius later treatise on Stoic physics, the Physiologia. I end the

    thesis with a consideration of the circumstantial factors that would have caused Lipsius to

    disown the presence of Stoic deterministic thought in his treatise.

  • 9

    1.2. A Brief Biography

    Joost Lips (Latinized as Justus Lipsius) was born in the province of Brabant, Belgium in

    1547. Overijse, the village where he was born, lies just outside of Brussels and Leuven. He

    studied first with the Jesuits in Cologne and later matriculated at the Catholic university of

    Leuven. After compiling three books of textual emendations of Cicero, Propertius, Varro, et al.

    in 1566, he went to Rome as secretary to Cardinal Granvelle and stayed for two years in order to

    study classical literature.15

    After his sojourn in Rome, Lipsius returned to Leuven in 1570 to

    continue his education in law. Soon after, Lipsius was driven by the massacres committed under

    Duke lvarez of Alba, Spanish general and governor of the Netherlands, to the Viennese court

    of Maximillian II and later to the Lutheran university of Jena.16

    With his property sacked by

    Spanish troops, Lipsius spent two years as chair of History at Jena, before returning to Leuven in

    1574.

    In 1577, Janus Dousa, a friend from the time of his study at Leuven, invited Lipsius to the

    newly founded Calvinist university at Leiden, which lies midway between Rotterdam and

    Amsterdam. Around the same time, Don Juan, the new Spanish governor of the Netherlands, was

    preparing a campaign to pacify the Low Countries. In anticipation of the oncoming conflict,

    Lipsius accepted Dousas invitation and left Leuven in early 1578.17

    Lipsius remained in Leiden

    for twelve years (1578-1591) where he was chair of History and Latin literature. Due to

    controversy over one of his publications, Lipsius left Leiden and returned to Leuven, where he

    taught at the Catholic university until his death in 1606.

    Lipsius began his scholarly career as a philologist, publishing various works of textual

    criticism on such Latin authors as Plautus, Cicero, Tacitus, Livy, Suetonius, both Senecas,

    15

    His Variae Lectiones Libri Tres were later published at Antwerp in 1569. 16

    Gerlo, A. et al. 1978, Introduction. 17

    Gerlo, A. et al. 1978, Introduction.

  • 10

    Statius, Apuleius, Persius, and others.18

    His edition of Tacitus (1574) first secured his reputation

    as a scholar of critical excellence. At Leiden, Lipsius published his most popular and influential

    works, his De constantia (1584) and Politica (1589). The former is a philosophical work for the

    benefit of the individual, while the latter is a treatise on proper governance that relies most

    heavily on Tacitus. His other major works are his two treatises on Stoicism, the Manuductio and

    the Physiologia (1604), followed by his edition of Senecas prose works (1605). Lipsius also

    wrote a textbook of epistolary writing, numerous works on Roman history, and a Menippean

    satire on classical scholarship. Finally, there is Lipsius lifetime of letter-writing. There exist

    over four thousand letters from or to Lipsius that spread over the course of his entire life,

    beginning with his early career and ending ten days before his death.19

    Lipsius published about

    800 of these letters during his lifetime by groups of hundreds (in so-called centuriae). There

    remain over a thousand unpublished letters of Lipsius that still remain unstudied.

    Lipsius religious life is a matter of some controversy and uncertainty. Born a Catholic,

    Lipsius studied in his youth with the Jesuits in Cologne. In order to hold the chair at Lutheran

    Jena, Lipsius made an affirmation of Lutheranism. While at Jena, Lipsius made three speeches

    that were particularly critical of the church and the Spanish crown. Lipsius compares the Duke of

    Alba to Tiberius, calling him a furiosus tyrannus20

    and calls the church the scarlet beast and

    the Roman whore in reference to the St. Bartholomews Day Massacre of 1572.21

    In his later

    years, Lipsius disclaimed authorship of such speeches when polemical works against him began

    to appear in 1600.22

    Similarly, Lipsius made some affirmation of Calvinism in order to teach at

    Leiden, although Dousa never pressed Lipsius regarding his religious allegiance. His return to

    18

    See, for example, Lipsius Electorum Libri. 19

    Gerlo, A. et al. 1978, Introduction. 20

    Morford 1991, 130. 21

    Morford 1991, 128-9. 22

    Morford 1991, 126.

  • 11

    Brabant in 1591 required reconciliation with the Jesuits and a re-affirmation of his Catholic faith.

    His unexpected decision to leave Leiden led Protestant colleagues such as Joesph Scaliger and

    Isaac Causabon to defame and criticize him even up until his death.23

    When he was encouraged

    to remember his Stoic consolations on his death-bed, it is said that Lipsius rejected them and

    made a final re-affirmation of his faith, saying, those things are vain...this [pointing to the

    crucifix] is true constancy.24

    On Lispius allegiances and personal beliefs, Morford concludes:

    [The] man still eludes us. His inconstancy in religion, the histrionics of his death (at least as

    described by his Catholic friends), and the editing, suppression, and amplification of his

    correspondence and published work indicate a character whose instinct for self-preservation

    was stronger than adherence to the high Stoic principles of his best writing or to one faith at

    the price of martyrdom.25

    1.3. The De Constantia Libri Duo

    The primary text I use for the De constantia is the first (1584) edition. Lipsius released

    several more editions during his lifetime, with the second edition published just a year after the

    first. Lipsius made no dramatic changes in these later editions, but I do consider these changes in

    chapter six. The De constantia was translated into all major European languages shortly after its

    initial publication, including English in 1594 by John Stradling.26

    R.V. Young has aided my

    study greatly with his 2011 translation with notes, which is the only modern English edition that

    does not rely on Stradlings translation. I use Young (2011) for my translation of the De

    23

    Morford 1991, 132. 24

    illa sunt vana... haec est vera patientia. The account is from Joannes Woverius, Lipsius pupil and executor (Iusti

    Lipsi Opera omnia 1: 185). See Morford 1991, 133n148. 25

    Morford 1991, 133. 26

    Young 2011, xxviii.

  • 12

    constantia unless otherwise noted.27

    The text I use is from the Bayerische Staatsbibliothek in

    Munich, which has been digitized by Google.28

    For the setting of his treatise, Lipsius fictionalizes his 1571 journey to Vienna. In the first

    chapter of book one, Lipsius says that as he was fleeing the disturbances of his native land

    (patriae meae turbas), he stopped by Lige to visit some friends, the most important of whom

    was Charles Languis. Like Lipsius, Languis (ca. 1521-1573) was himself a noted philologist who

    published editions of Ciceros philosophical works and Plautus comedies.29

    Within the De

    constantia, Languis takes the role of the philosophical teacher in dialogue with the young

    Lipsius, the pupil.30

    Through the voice of Languis, Lipsius introduces the philosophical aim of

    the work:

    Itaque non patria fugienda, Lipsi: sed Adfectus sunt: et firmandus ita formandusque hic

    animus, ut quies nobis in turbis sit et pax inter media arma.31

    And so you must not flee your country, Lipsius, but your emotions. The mind must be so

    strengthened and shaped that quiet may be yours amidst tumults and peace amid warfare.

    Languis will advance a series of four arguments for the purpose of treating the young Lipsius

    present mental infirmity. The De constantia is, above all, a work of ethical discourse between the

    philosopher and his student.

    Before Languis sets out his four arguments in support of constancy (constantia), he

    explains to the young Lipsius why the mind becomes afflicted and why constantia is required to

    treat it. Languis explains that the afflicted mind is depressed by itself, not by external wars or

    27

    Young uses a 1605 edition as the basis for his text and translation, with only a few places where my 1584 text

    conflicts. I also deviate from Young at times when I wish to be particularly precise in translating certain

    philosophical terms and concepts. 28

    The URL is

    . 29

    Young 2011, 17n2. 30

    To distinguish between Lipsius the author and Lipsius the character, I will refer to the former simply as Lipsius

    and the latter as Lipsius the pupil or the young Lipsius (Lipsius would have been around 25 when his

    fictionalized conversation with Languis took place). 31

    De con. 1.1.

  • 13

    suffering, and thus constantia, defined as an upright and unmoved vigor of the mind that is

    neither uplifted nor cast down by outward or chance occurrences,32

    is the means by which the

    mind can free itself from anxiety and turmoil. The mind that is plagued by opinion, defined as

    false judgment (iudicium...fallax), is overtaken by volatile emotions, while the mind that is

    fortified through right reason, defined as correct judgment regarding human and divine affairs

    (de rebus humanis divinisque...verum iudicium), is always in a stable, tranquil state.33

    Languis

    thus expounds a theory of the mind in which the interplay between reason and opinion explains

    emotive states.

    After introducing his theory of the psyche, Lipsius explores how the unhealthy mind

    judges things as either good or evil. Because the unhealthy mind is guided by opinion, it makes

    false judgments regarding external objects as either beneficial or harmful. External objects are

    falsely considered good or evil because they are not in us but around us, and strictly speaking

    they neither help nor harm the inner man, that is, the mind.34

    Among false goods are wealth,

    commendations, power, and health; among false evils are poverty, disgrace, weakness, illness

    and death. Lipsius further dissects these false evils into private (privata mala) and public evils

    (publica mala). Since the pupil Lipsius is fleeing from Spanish troops, Lipsius focuses on public

    evils, which include war, plague, famine, tyranny and massacres. Lipsius says that because

    public evils afflict us en masse, and not individually, we are more likely to succumb to sorrow

    when faced by them.

    Due to the shared experience of adversity, we are more likely to grieve over public evils

    even though they are falsely regarded as harmful. In 1.7-12, Lipsius describes three states of

    32

    De con. 1.4: [Constantiam hic appello,] rectum et immotum animi robur, non elati externis aut fortuitis non

    depressi. 33

    De con. 1.4. 34

    De con. 1.7: [Utraque sic appello,] quae non in nobis, sed circa nos, quaeque interiorem hunc hominem, id est

    animum, proprie non iuvant aut laedunt.

  • 14

    mind (adfecti) that inhibit resistance to public evils. They are: deception (simulatio), nationalism

    (pietas), and pity (miseratio). Due to deception, we are able to mask our self-interest as concern

    for others. He uses the following example: if there was war in the Indies no one would care, but

    if in the Low Countries, everyone weeps and wails. To the pupils reply that the Indies is not his

    native country, Languis replies, Fool. Are they not also men of the same stock and seed as

    you?35

    This leads Lipsius to the second of these mental states, pietas. Lipsius acknowledges that

    piety is a virtue when it is defined as the lawful and owed honor and love for God and parents

    (legitimum debitumque honorem et amorem in Deum ac parentes), but people often twist this

    into an excessive love for country. Love for country does not come from nature, but arises out of

    human custom and convention for the protection of property and the safety it provides.36

    Lipsius

    accepts that we owe respect, service, and sometimes our lives to our country, but no one should

    grieve for a contrived institution.37

    Lipsius distinguishes the third adfectus, pity (miseratio), from

    mercy (misericordia). Lipsius defines pity as the vice of despondency at the sight of anothers

    evil (vitium...ad speciem alieni mali collabentis) while mercy is an inclination of the mind

    towards relieving anothers suffering (inclinationem animi ad alienam...luctum sublevandum).38

    If one sees another in need, the virtuous response is aid, not wallowing in sorrow. These three

    states of mind are obstacles to the recognition that public evils are not harmful and inhibit the

    cultivation of constancy.

    With the three passions out of the way, Lipsius spends the remained of the treatise on

    four arguments for why public evils are not worth grieving over. The first argument (1.13-14) is

    35

    De con. 1.9: Stulte. An non et illi homines, eadem stirpe tecum et satu? 36

    De con. 1.11: A natura enim esse vis: reversa autam est a more quodam et instituto (You wish to maintain that

    [the origin of countries] comes from nature, but the truth of the matter is, it comes from custom and education). 37

    De con. 1.11: Quam si iure amari a civibus vis; fatebor. Defendi; agnoscam. Mortem pro ea suscipi; permittam.

    Non illud, ut etiam doleat quis, iaceat, lamentetur (If you wish that [country] be loved by its citizens as a matter of

    right, I admit it; that they should defend it, I acknowledge; that they should die for it, I allow it. I do not concede that

    anyone should grieve for it, lie prostrate, or bewail it). Translation altered. 38

    De con. 1.12.

  • 15

    that all events are directed by Gods providence, and thus there is no cause for anxiety. In fact, to

    complain or weep over them is irreverent to God, who makes provision for all natural and human

    affairs. The second argument (1.15-22) is that public evils are necessary in two ways and, again,

    are not worth worrying about. First, public evils are necessary in that countries inevitably end at

    some point in ruin and destruction; nations and civilizations are as prone to destruction as the

    mortals who comprise them. Since we necessarily die, the institutions of men also necessarily

    die. Second, public evils are necessary by fate. Lipsius is careful to distinguish his theory of fate

    from others, most notably from that of the Stoics. In a similar way to the first argument, Lipsius

    argues that all events are fated by God and thus there is no reason to lament suffering. Lipsius

    also clarifies that fate does not limit Gods freedom, nor does it interfere with our own wills.

    This concludes book one, and book two begins with a discussion about the proper use of

    gardens: they are meant to be places for serious reflection, not places of vanity or sloth. Lipsius

    then makes an exhortation to virtue and encourages young men to incorporate philosophy into

    their studies. After this brief interlude on gardens and wisdom, Lipsius sets out his third

    argument (2.6-17): that public evils are actually beneficial because they come from God. Even if

    they are brought about by evil men, adversities have four useful purposes. First, adversity

    strengthens good men and makes then an example for others (2.8). Second, adversity corrects

    those who on the way to virtue (2.9). Vice thrives easily in prosperity and lack of want, and so

    adversity humbles us and keeps our faults from growing. Third, adversity is a useful punishment

    for those who have sinned (2.10). Fourth, public evils serve purposes that are beyond human

    comprehension (2.11). Lipsius hesitates to guess what these could be: they prevent

    overpopulation or contribute to later human development. To the objection that the innocent are

    often unjustly punished by God, Lipsius responds that humans are in no place to question Gods

  • 16

    justice (2.12). Further, not only are we all guilty of some fault, but it is also incorrect to presume

    that anyone except God can judge who is more innocent or more deserving of punishment

    (2.1539

    ).

    The remainder of the treatise (2.17-26) comprises the fourth and final argument: that the

    ongoing turmoil of the Low Countries is a trifle compared to countless sufferings of human

    history. Lipsius uses the exempla of Roman, Greek and Jewish history, in addition to the more

    recent miseries imposed on the native populations of the Americas. After Languis finishes his

    arguments and makes one last exhortation for the young Lipsius to grow in virtue, they promptly

    rise and head out in the midday sun for lunch.40

    The pupil Lipsius leaves with Languis in a

    joyous mood, crying out I have escaped evil and found the good.41

    Some of Lipsius statements may be shocking or unsavory to modern readers (e.g., that

    everyone deserves punishment or that wars may be ordained by God to reduce overpopulation),

    but Lipsius does not make these claims callously. When recalling European domination of the

    Americas, Languis says:

    Ostende etiam te paullum tu, Peruana, tu Mexicana ora. Heu mira miseramque faciem!

    immensus ille tractus et vere alter Orbis, vastus attritusque apparet, non aliter quam si

    caelesti quodam igne deflagrisset. Mens et lingua mihi cadit, Lipsi, dum haec memoro: et

    video nostra omnia prae istis non aliud quam paleatum cassa esse, ut Comicus ait, aut

    gurguliunculos minutos.42

    Show yourself also for a while, Peruvian land, and you, the Mexican. Alas, what an

    amazing and miserable aspect! That immense expanse, truly another world, appears

    desolate and wiped out, not otherwise than if it had been consumed by some fire from

    heaven. Mind and tongue fail me, Lipsius, as I recall these things; and I see all our

    troubles beside them as nothing but clouds of chaff, as the Comic poet says, or tiny little

    weevils.

    39

    In editions after 1584, Lipsius separated chapter 2.14 into two chapters, increasing the total number of chapters in

    book two from 26 to 27. The convention I use is that of the first edition, so that 2.15 refers to 2.16 in later editions. 40

    De con. 2.26. 41

    De con. 2.26: Effugi malum, repperi bonum. Young (2011, 205n161) notes that Lipsius is quoting from

    Demosthenes (On the Crown 313). 42

    De con. 2.21. Translation altered. The Comicus refers to Plautus, Rudens, 1325 (Young 2011, 187n119).

  • 17

    When Lipsius justifies why bad things happen to good people, he admits that he is not speaking

    from a position of authority.43

    Although Lipsius is aware that his explanations are not always

    palatable, he tries to make sense of calamity according to his understanding of the universe.

    Setting aside judgment of Lipsius justification of public evils, his humanism can still interest

    todays students of classics. Lipsius believed that Greek and Latin literature was valuable not

    only to the academic, but to the general reader. With the De constantia, he calls upon his

    classical learning to address the pressing issues of rebellion and war that afflicted the Low

    Countries. If nothing else, this humanist program makes the De constantia deserving of our

    attention.

    1.4. The Role of Seneca

    Now that we have an outline of the contents of the De constantia, I introduce a Stoic

    writer who is foundational to my study. Some information about Seneca the Younger is

    necessary to contextualize Lipsius own appreciation for the man. Senecas prose philosophy

    was the most important vehicle for the transmission of Stoic ideas through the medieval period

    and into the Renaissance. Due to his ubiquitous presence and reputation as a proto-Christian by

    the sixteenth century, Seneca was a natural source of attraction to Lipsius and other humanists of

    the age. In chapter two, I pay careful attention to Lipsius use or disuse of Seneca because from

    this we can learn something about Stoicisms place in the De constantia. Namely, we may learn

    how deeply Lipsius draws from Stoic sources: does he draw only from Senecas moral

    philosophy, or does he incorporate a richer collection of Stoic texts?

    43

    When prodded for the reasons for divine punishments, Lipsius first says, tutissime dicam, me nescire (the safest

    thing for me to say is, I dont know) (De con. 2.12).

  • 18

    Even in his own day, Lucius Annaeus Seneca (4 BCE 65 CE) was a man of incredible

    influence. Born to the famous statesman and rhetorician of the same name, Seneca the Younger

    was a Roman senator, playwright, and Stoic philosopher. Senecas literary oeuvre encompasses

    Latin tragedy, Menippean satire, and philosophy. His extant philosophical works include 124

    moral epistles, a collection of essays on various ethical topics, and an idiosyncratic work on

    natural science. His Epistulae morales were written to his friend Lucilius and function as

    vehicles for Senecas ethics rather than strictly personal correspondence. Twelve treatises on

    moral subjects survive, though approximately twenty more have not.44

    The surviving treatises

    are: Ad Helviam de Consolatione, Ad Marciam de Consolatione, Ad Polybium de Consolatione,

    De Beata Vita, De Brevitate Vitae, De Constantia Sapientis, De Ira, De Otio, De Providentia, De

    Tranquillitate Animi, De Beneficiis, and De Clementia. The first three are consolatory letters

    written to parents, including Senecas own mother, regarding their children. The remaining nine

    treatises cover a range of philosophical topics falling within the realm of ethics, though De

    Providentia tangentially covers some metaphysics. Finally, the Naturales Quaestiones seeks to

    rationally explain a range of natural phenomena and includes epistemology and theology. On the

    content of Senecas philosophical corpus, Brad Inwood has cautioned against expecting to find a

    unified philosophical program.45

    Rather, Seneca engages with Stoicism in a particularistic

    manner as he reflects on issues that interest him most. While Senecas philosophy is unique in its

    sensitivity to first-hand experience and his attention to the proficiens, he is conservative in

    relation to the earlier Athenian Stoa.46

    Nevertheless, Seneca is a serious philosophical presence

    in the Western tradition, worth the time and energy demanded.47

    44

    Colish 1985, 15. 45

    Inwood 2005, 2. 46

    Inwood 2005, 352. 47

    Inwood 2005, 5.

  • 19

    Christian apologists and Fathers of the early Church received Seneca well despite a tepid

    reputation inherited from Quintilian. The Roman rhetorician came out strongly against Senecas

    style, calling it corrupt and exceedingly dangerous for the style it promotes.48

    Even worse,

    Quintilian characterized Senecas philosophy as parum diligens (lacking thoughtfulness).49

    However, as Stoic ethics would largely become assimilated into the Christian tradition, Christian

    writers unsurprisingly lauded Senecas prose for its moral emphasis.50

    Lactantius (4th

    century)

    credits Seneca as omnium Stoicorum acutissimus (the keenest of all Stoics) and we even have

    fragments from three lost works of Seneca that Lactantius quoted.51

    Tertullian (born c.160)

    famously wrote that Seneca was saepe noster (frequently ours)52

    and while Augustine (354-

    430) charges him with hypocrisy, he does admit there is some truth in Senecas writing.53

    Jerome

    (c. 347-420) includes Seneca in his catalogue of illustrious men.54

    In fact, Jerome writes:

    I would not have placed him in my catalogue of the holy, had I not been moved by those

    letters of Paul to Seneca and of Seneca to Paul, which many have read. In these, when he

    was the teacher of Nero and the most powerful man of that time, he says that he wishes to

    occupy the position among his own that Paul occupies with the Christians. Two years

    before Peter and Paul were crowned with martyrdom, he was killed by Nero.55

    This excerpt contains the earliest recorded mention of the Paul-Seneca correspondence, which

    Jerome unquestioningly accepts as genuine. The Paul-Seneca correspondence was often included

    with the Epistulae Morales from the early Middle Ages, and Jeromes biography served as an

    48

    Quint. Inst. 10.1.29: sed in eloquendo [sententiae] corrupta pleraque, atque eo perniciosissima quod abundant

    dulcibus vitiis. 49

    Quint. Inst. 10.1.29: In philosophia parum diligens, egregarius tamen vitiorum insectatur fuit. 50

    Long 2003, 8. Long views this as detrimental to a later revival of Stoicism as true Stoic doctrines would become

    indistinguishable from their Christian counterparts. 51

    Lactantius Div. Inst. 2.8.23. The three lost works are: the Exhortationes, De immatura morte, and Moralis

    philosophiae libri. We also have quotes from other lost works; Jerome quotes from De matrimonio, Augustine from

    the De superstitione. Cassiodorus quotes from De forma mundi (Reynolds 1983, 358). 52

    Tertullian De anima 20. 53

    August. CD. 6.10: [verum] adfuit enim scribenti, viventi defuit. 54

    Jerome De vir. ill. 12 55

    I use Kers (2009, 182-3) translation here.

  • 20

    introduction in editions of Seneca from at least the 11th

    century.56

    Jeromes Vita Senecae,

    however, does not mention Neros motivewhich we know to be his alleged involvement in the

    Pisonian conspiracyfor ordering the death of Seneca. With the rediscovery of Tacitus Annals

    not occurring until 1370, medieval scholars filled in the gaps of missing information by likening

    Senecas suicide to Christian martyrdom.57

    At first, the rediscovery of Tacitus did little to prevent a Christianization of Seneca. In

    1374, Boccaccio uses the newly found Tacitean account to argue that Seneca not only received a

    baptism of the spirit, but that Seneca baptized himself at the time of his death by consecrating

    water to Jove the Liberator, whom Boccaccio argues is to be understood as Jesus Christ.58

    It was

    not until the 16th

    century that Erasmus properly secularized Seneca. Erasmus admired Seneca,

    calling him the one ancient writer who deserves to be read by Christians.59

    Still, his 1525 edition

    of Seneca definitively proves the Paul-Seneca correspondence a forgery and clarifies the

    biography of Seneca against those who were virtually embracing him as orthodox.60

    Due in part to his reputation as a proto-Christian, Senecas prose works enjoyed a healthy

    transmission from the early Middle Ages to the Italian Renaissance. Most of the main units that

    comprise the manuscript tradition follow a general pattern of brief appearance in the 9th

    through

    11th

    centuries followed by a great resurgence in 12th

    and 13th

    centuries.61

    In the 12th

    century,

    Senecan texts begin to be joined together into a corpus, and most of his major works are bound

    under a single cover beginning in the 14th

    century.62

    Of course other factors beside his content

    56

    Reynolds 1983, 360. Also, Ker 2009, 188. 57

    Ker 2009, 187. One 9th

    century pseudo-Senecan manuscript fabricates the story that Seneca objected to Neros

    Great Fire of 64CE. Senecas death is then compared to the contemporaneous deaths of Peter and Paul. 58

    Ker 2009, 201-2. This account is found in Boccaccios Commento Di Dante (c. 1374) as a response to Dantes

    placing of Seneca in Limbo. 59

    Kraye 2001/2002, 31. 60

    Ker 2009, 210. 61

    Reynolds 1983, 359. 62

    Reynolds 1983, 360.

  • 21

    aided his reception. As already mentioned, Seneca wrote in a pithy, sententious style

    characteristic of silver Latin, and this style lends itself well to quotations and excerpting. In the

    early Middle Ages, florilegia (gathering of flowers, compilations of quotations) contain

    abundant extracts from (sometimes pseudo-)Seneca. Florilegium Gallicum, Proverbia Senecae,

    Senecae Monita, and the Liber de moribus are just a few of those that contain quotes attributed to

    Seneca. Collections of short maxims by Seneca also became popular in the 16th

    century.63

    These

    compendia allowed publishers to censor Senecas philosophy so that only the most palatable

    sayings are published.64

    Imitating Senecan style and content, forgeries and pseudo-Senecan

    works also abound, including the aforementioned Proverbia Senecae and Liber de moribus. The

    most cited plagiarist, however, was Martin Braga of the 6th

    century who wrote De ira, Formula

    vitae honestae, and De quattuor virtutibus cardinalibus.65

    Finally, remember that Seneca is the

    sole ancient Stoic philosopher who wrote in Latin. Translations of Greek sources such as

    Epictetus remained lacking until the 15th

    century.66

    For a Medieval Latin reader, Seneca and

    Cicero were the primary source for information about Stoicism.67

    As a philologist Lipsius himself contributed to the study of Senecan texts. In his

    Electorum Libri (1582) Lipsius first made the conclusive distinction between the Elder and the

    Younger Seneca, and Lipsius worked with Andreas Schott to publish the Declamationes (1603)

    under the heading of the correct Seneca. Most importantly, Lipsius published a new edition of

    Senecas prose works (1605) that greatly aided in the establishment of an authoritative text. He

    63

    Kraye 2001/2002, 37-8. 64

    Incidentally, Seneca himself condemned reading a Stoic author in this manner. While in his Epistulae Seneca

    initially provides Lucilius with short maxims drawn usually from Epicurus beginning with Ep. 4, Seneca later stops

    the practice. In Ep. 33.2, he states that the writings of his Stoic forebears have an interwoven logical structure that is

    not suited to excerption. Even more, Seneca views snatching at flowerets (Ep. 33.7) to be shameful for one trying

    to make real moral progress. I thank Margaret Graver for introducing me to this point. See Graver (forthcoming). 65

    Colish 1985, 16. 66

    Verbeke 1983, 7. 67

    Verbeke 1983, 7.

  • 22

    claimed to have been the first to establish the correct punctuation and division of words and

    phrases, and his profound knowledge of Senecas style and vocabulary allowed him to be

    extraordinarily accurate in his corrections (Morford 1991, 173).

    Like others before him, Lipsius greatly admired Seneca. In a 1585 letter written to

    Laevinus Torrentius, friend and vicar general of the archbishop of Lige, Lipsius writes A kind

    of fervor lies in the writings of Seneca or Epictetus, which also comes upon the reader, and they

    do not seem so much to discuss virtue as to sow and cultivate it within him.68

    And in his

    dedication to Pope Paul V of his edition of Seneca, Lipsius calls him the most praiseworthy

    writer among all the ancients (laudatissimum inter omnes veteres scriptorem) and nearly

    Christian (paene Christianus).69

    Lipsius admiration, however, extended beyond respect for the

    moralizing quality of his philosophy. In the introduction to his edition of Seneca, Lipsius defends

    the philosopher against the judgment of Quintilian. Whereas Quintilian saw Senecas style as

    antithetical to proper Roman rhetoric, Lipsius counters that:

    Proprium aliquod et suum genus habuit: ut solent ista vel cum aetatibus mutari, vel

    pro ingenio atque animo cuiusque formari. Quis Ciceronem Gracco aut Catoni

    similem dicat, aut velit?

    He [Seneca] had his own particular and characteristic style: as such things habitually

    change with the passing ages or are shaped in accordance with the intellect and spirit

    of each. Who would say that Cicero is like Gracchus or Cato? And who would want

    him to be?

    Lipsius also aimed to reverse the earlier judgment of humanists like Erasmus who approved of

    the moral content of his writing, but whonot unlike Quintiliancriticized his writing as flat.70

    68

    ILE, II, 84 05 06 (no. 342): Spirat nescio quis calor in Senecae aut Epicteti scriptis, qui ad lectorem quoque

    pervenit: nec disserere illi magis de virtute videntur, quam inserere et inculare. 69

    Opera Omnia Senecae, Epistola Dedicatoria: En Annaeum Senecam, laudatissimum inter omnes veteres

    scriptorem et virtutis studio paene Christianum (ita nostri censuerunt), emendatum varie et illustratam damus et

    deponimus ad sacros tuos pedes (Behold, I give and place at your holy feet Annaeus Seneca, the most praiseworthy

    writer among all the ancients and often Christian (so our writers have judged) in the study of virtue, variously

    emended and illustrated). Also see Papy 2004, 50. 70

    Kraye 1999, 458.

  • 23

    Regarding Senecas sententiousness, Lipsius regards it as complementary to moral instruction

    and to Stoicism in particular:

    neque abnuo, crebras et minutas istas sententias intervenire. Sed pondera etiam

    rerum frangere?hoc nego, in istis quidem philosophicis libris, qui exstant. Augent

    magis, et intendunt. Stoicorum hoc proprium fuit, non gladiis, sed pugiunculis, rem

    gerere: et brevi et accincto sermone esse.71

    Nor do I deny that those frequent, short sentences crop up. But that they break the

    balance of things? I deny this, certainly in those philosophical works which are

    extant. Rather they enrich and direct. This was characteristic of the Stoics, to carry

    out war not with swords but with little knives: and to be of concise and well-girdled

    speech.

    Senecan brevity and pith is characteristic of Lipsius own writing, filled with forceful, terse

    sentences.72

    For example, Lipsius describes those infected by the Dutch tulip craze as follows:

    Hi sunt, quorum litterae in Thraciam, Graeciam, Indiam discurrunt: idque seminis exigui

    aut bulbuli caussa. Hi, quibus aegrius sit florem aliquem novum mori, quam veterem

    amicum.73

    These are the men whose letters run to and fro into Thrace, Greece, and India, and that

    for the sake of a few seeds or bulbs. These are the men for whom it would be more

    distressing should some new flower die, than an old friend.

    Here we see Lipsius abbreviating his already compact sentences and ending with a quick punch-

    line that stabs at his targets dehumanizing behavior. Note the contrast between the new bulbs

    and the old friend; the tulip craze distracts priorities from the long-standing to the fickle. Finally,

    Lipsius objects to Quintilians criticism of Seneca as a philosopher lacking critical power, and

    instead makes an attack on Quintilians own perspicacity:

    At culpat etiam Fabius, ut in Philosophia parum diligentem. Quid hoc est? aut de

    qua parte loqui eum putem?...Sed Fabii mentem ego hanc arbitror, non inquisisse

    nimis aut penetrasse in interiora Philosophiae; externa hac populari, et velut

    medicante, contentum. 71

    For characterization of Stoic rhetoric as small and sharp-pointed, see Cic. Fin. 4.7: Pungunt quasi aculeis

    interrogatiunculis angustis; also Cic. Parad., Prooemium 2: sed minutis interrogatiunculis quasi punctis quod

    proposuit efficit. 72

    Lipsius Senecan style would later influence a group of rationalistic thinkers of the late 16th

    century, including

    Montaigne, du Vair, Richelieu, Montesquieu, Fancis Bacon, Joseph Hall, etc. (Saunders 1955, 15-16). 73

    De con. 2.3.

  • 24

    But Fabius [i.e., Marcus Fabius Quintilian] still censures that there is little insight in

    his philosophy. What is this? And about what part should I think him to speak of? ...

    But I judge that this is the mind of Fabius, that he has not inquired enough or

    penetrated into the innermost of philosophy; that he was content with the outer,

    popular, and, as it were, medicating part of this philosophy.

    Lipsius clearly had a high opinion of both Senecas stylistic and philosophical contributions, and

    was willing to make a forceful attack on perhaps the most respected authority on Latin rhetoric.

    Before we can look to Lipsius De constantia in detail for Senecan influence, we must

    first verify that Lipsius was familiar with Seneca when writing his treatise. During his three years

    in Rome from 1568 to 1570 as secretary to Cardinal Granvelle, the young Lipsius gained the

    friendship of the French scholar Marc-Antoine Muret. It was under the guidance of Muret that

    Lipsius was formally introduced to Seneca, and their discussions about Seneca would later

    become a source of contention between the two.74

    It appears the first mention Lipsius makes of

    Seneca is in a letter addressed to Gerhard Falkenberg from August 1575.75

    Lipsius lists Socrates,

    Seneca, Helvidius Priscus and Thrasea Paetus as exemplars of constancy in the face of tyranny.76

    It is interesting that Lipsius only mentions Seneca within a catalogue of notable sapientes, and it

    would appear that Lipsius particular appreciation for Seneca has not yet blossomed. A year

    later, in 1576, Muret writes to Lipsius accusing him of plagiarizing his emendations to Seneca

    which they discussed during their time in Rome.77

    Muret is referring to two of Lipsius lectures

    74

    Morford 1991, 157. Kraye 1988, 371. 75

    Falkenberg was a Protestant, secretary to Thomas Rehdinger, to whom Lipsius devoted Antiquae Lectiones late in

    1574. Falkenberg had indirectly criticized Lipsius return to the Spanish Netherlands (Morford 1991, 152). 76

    ILE, I, 75 08 01 (Ep. Misc. 1.4): Quis servus est, perire modo qui non timet?Hoc enim firmum adversus externa

    omnia telum, non timere propter quod timentur. Sic Socrates adfectus, qui Athenas non deservit, insessas non uno

    sed triginta tyrannis; sic Seneca, qui sub Nerone, imo cum Nerone vixit; sic Helvidius, sic Thrasea, et magna illa

    sapientum manus (Who is a slave who does not fear to die? For this weapon is firm against all external affairs, to

    not fear them on account of that they are feared. Thus Socrates possessed it, who did not desert Athens, occupied not

    by a single but by thirty tyrants; so did Seneca, who lived under, nay, rather with Nero; Thus Helvidius and Thrasea

    and that great band of wise men). 77

    ILE, I, 76 09 05 (no. 74): Et negas te a me quidquam accepisse praeter unum aut alterum locum, in quibus etiam

    vis facta a te mentionem mei (And you deny that you have taken anything from me besides one or another point, in

    which also you wish that my mention came about from you ).

  • 25

    in which he recommended 29 emendations to Senecas prose works.78

    After Christophe Plantin,

    a mutual friend and Lipsius publisher, reunited the two scholars in 1579, Lipsius writes to Muret

    to preserve their failing friendship:

    Electorum librum iam nunc vulgavi. paro Saturnalium sermonum, et De vita ac scriptis

    Annaei Senecae. quem nec invitus ad te miserim, quasi vadem amicitiae coeuntis et

    sanescentis.79

    I have already published Electorum Librum. I am preparing Saturnalium sermonum [a

    book on gladiators] and a work on the life and writings of Annaeus Seneca which I may

    have sent to you not begrudgingly, but in earnest of a friendship that is coming together

    and beginning to recover.

    Lipsius never published the work on Senecas life and writings, but it appears as one of the many

    introductory portions of his 1605 edition of Seneca.

    Within the next few years, evidence for Lipsius appreciation for Seneca and Stoicism

    becomes more substantial. In a letter written on New Years Eve 1580 to Janus Lernutius, a

    fellow Belgian humanist, Lipsius says he is digging deeply into Stoic philosophy and reading

    Seneca, Epictetus and Arrian.80

    A year later Lipsius writes a charming letter in which we learn

    that he has recommended Seneca to Alexander Ratlo, and Lipsius is glad to hear that his friend

    enjoys the Stoics as much as he. He writes:

    Senecam nostrum tibi placere ex animo gaudeo. Scio non alios e priscis magis consentire

    cum Christiana pietate, quam eos qui e Stoica domo. In quo numero etiam Arrianus est,

    qui digessit Graece dissertationes Epicteti, mihi valde probatas. Quaere, moneo, et

    lege.81

    I rejoice from my heart that our Seneca is pleasing to you. I know of none among the

    great ancients that agree more with Christian piety than those of the Stoic school. And in

    whose number is also Arrian, who distributed in Greek the Discourses of Epictetus,

    which are very much in agreement to me. Look for and, I urge you, read them.

    78

    Morford 1991, 157. 79

    Ep. Misc. 1.53. 80

    ILE, I, 80 12 31 (Ep. ad Belg. 2.1): nec medicina ulla nisi a litteris: non istis amoenioribus sed ab illis

    robustoribus. Philosophiam dico, in quam me penetro: et quidem Stoicam (Reading is my only comfortnot those

    more pleasant works, but stronger medicine. Philosophy, I meanStoic Philosophyinto which I am digging

    deeply). I use Morfords (1991, 158) translation. 81

    ILE, I, 82 01 23 R (Ep. misc. 1.33).

  • 26

    Six months later, Lipsius writes to Andreas Schott, a friend from his time at university, that I

    approve that you are preparing to publish Seneca the Elder, but the wisdom in the Younger

    uniquely pleases me.82

    In the ensuing years, Lipsius began writing his De Constantia, with the

    first copy sent to the Treasurer and Advocate of Antwerp on October 15, 1583 before it was

    formally published in 1584.83

    Prior to writing the De Constantia, then, Lipsius was both familiar

    with Senecan manuscripts as well as personally vested in the philosophical content of Senecas

    prose.

    82

    ILE, I, 82 07 07 (Ep. misc. 1.45): Senecam patrem quod paras, approbo. Unice me sapientia in filio delectat. 83

    ILE, I, 83 10 15 P (Ep. misc. 1.59). See Morford 1991, 103.

  • 27

    Chapter 2: Senecas De Providentia

    Works like the De constantia that betrayed a Stoic ethical influence were quite

    uncontroversial in 16th

    century Europe. In the case of the De constantia, the influence of

    Senecas De providentia stands out. In this chapter I will show that the De providentiaand by

    extension Stoic ethicsis essential to Lipsius concerns with determinism. Nevertheless, it is

    also an insufficient model to satisfactorily explain determinism in the De constantia. The result

    of this analysis is a preliminary indication of the degree to which Lipsius revives Stoicism. While

    the De providentia provides some glimpses into Stoic physics, it is wholly a work of ethics.

    Since I find that the De providentia is insufficient for explaining the full breadth of Lipsius

    concerns with determinism, I may continue my investigation as to whether Lipsisus metaphysics

    features a revival of Stoic causal determinism. I clarify that I do not seek to merely show that

    Lipsius draws upon the De providentia; that much is obvious from Lipsius own excerpting from

    the work. Rather, I seek to reveal to what extent the De providentia is a guide for the De

    Constantia.

    The De providentia is an incomplete essay in six sections that seeks to answer this

    question posed by Lucilius: why, if the world is governed by providence, it is still the case that

    good men suffer from many misfortunes?84

    The crux of the De providentia is to resolve the

    apparent problem of human suffering despite a provident and beneficent God. Specifically,

    Seneca is concerned about the perceived inappropriateness of hardship and discomfort in the

    lives of good men. In addition, Seneca assumes that God is provident when he frames the

    question; he does not set out to prove that providence does preside over all of us and that God

    84

    Sen. Prov. 1.1: [Quaesisti a me, Lucili, quid ita,] si providentia mundus agetur, multa bonis viris mala acciderent.

    I refer to John Davies (2007) translation unless otherwise noted.

  • 28

    concerns himself with us.85

    At the beginning of the next section, Seneca states his central thesis:

    nothing bad can happen to a good man: opposites do not mix.86

    Clarifying this proposition,

    Seneca notes the difference between experiencing hardships and judging them to be evil:

    ita adversarum impetus rerum viri fortis non vertit animum: manet in statu et quidquid

    evenit in suum colorem trahit; est enim omnibus externis potentior. Nec hoc dico, non

    sentit illa, sed vincit87

    so adversitys onslaughts are powerless to affect the spirit of a brave man: it remains

    unshaken and makes all events assume its own color; for it is stronger than all external

    forces. I do not mean that he is insensible to those forces but that he conquers them...

    Seneca later repeats this sentiment:

    Pro ipsis ergo bonis uiris est ferre quae non sunt mala nisi male sustinenti...88

    Accordingly it is expedient even for good men to endure with a patient mind things

    that are bad only to the one who bears them badly...

    Good men do not feel harmed by misfortune because they perceive that external objects are not

    truly evil, defined as that which is unconditionally harmful. Seneca next explains that adversity is

    properly judged to be training for virtuous living. After using Cato the Younger as an exemplum

    of a good man unaffected by misfortune, Seneca outlines the rest of his treatise as follows: first,

    that adversity benefits the individual and the human race; second, that good men are eager for

    adversity; third, that good men are fated to face adversity; finally, that one should not pity a good

    man for he is never wretched.89

    Seneca finishes the remainder of the third section with the

    analogy of adversity as medicine or surgery, followed by the exempla of Mucius Scaevola,

    Fabricius Luscinus, Rutilius Rufus, Atilius Regulus, Socrates, and, for the second time, Cato.

    Surely we dont count these men as miserable, Seneca argues, and they were beset with

    85

    Sen. Prov. 1.1: [Hoc commodius in contextu operis redderetur,] cum praeesse universis providentiam probaremus

    et interesse nobis deum. 86

    Sen. Prov. 2.1: Nihil accidere bono viro mali potest: non miscentur contraria. 87

    Sen. Prov. 2.1-2. 88

    Sen. Prov. 4.16. 89

    Sen. Prov. 3.1.

  • 29

    adversity. In the next section, he says that not only are the good left unharmed by misfortune, but

    that those with good fortune will experience unhappiness eventually.90

    That good men

    experience adversity is also educational to the rest of humanity as they teach us what is truly

    good and evil.91

    Consolation also lies in the understanding that God directs all things according

    to his will.92

    After succinctly clarifying what truly harmssin and crimethe treatise abruptly

    ends with an argument in favor of suicide should life become unbearable.93

    The central argument of the De providentia, that adversity is beneficial as a form of

    mental training, reappears in Languis third argument for achieving constantia:

    Utilia enim sunt, haec quae patimur Publica mala: et cum interno nostro fructu

    commodisque coniuncta. Mala autem? imo Bona verius, si remoto hoc Opinionum velo,

    oculos ad Ortum eorum referes et ad Finem.94

    For they are useful, these public evils that we suffer, joined with our fruit and profit. Yet

    are they evils? They are rather more truly goods, if, having removed this veil of opinion,

    you will take a look at their origin and end.

    The publica mala of Lipsius are harmful only due to a false judgment of the mind. Although I do

    not consider in depth Lipsius use of Stoic psychic theory in this thesis, Lipsius is evidently

    familiar with the idea that external objects are not in reality good or evil. A few lines later,

    Lipsius illustrates how adversity can be beneficial by means of a medical analogy similar to

    Senecas: these hardships are like medications: severe to the sense, healthful in substance

    and outcome.95

    While we immediately see a parallel structure to Seneca, the third argument for

    constancy considers the role of adversity more systematically than the De providentia. Whereas

    90

    Sen. Prov. 4.7: Erratis enim si quem iudicatis exceptum... quisquis uidetur dimissus esse dilatus est (You are

    wrong if you think anyone has been exempted from ill... Whoever seems to have been set free from this has only

    been granted a delay). 91

    Sen. Prov. 5.1. 92

    Sen. Prov. 5.6-8. 93

    Sen. Prov. 6. 94

    De con. 2.6. 95

    De con. 2.6: velut medicamenta sunt: sensu tristia, re salubria et eventu. Cf. Sen. Prov. 3.1: miraberis quosdam

    ferro et igne curare.

  • 30

    Lucilius only laments good men suffering misfortune, Lipsius holistically considers adversity in

    relation to the good, the bad, and those in between. De con. 2.6-7 introduces the thesis that

    adversity is beneficial and begins by considering its source (i.e., God). The next chapter

    introduces three purposes for adversity: it exercises the good (2.8), corrects the imperfect

    proficiens (2.9), and punishes the wicked (2.10). Lipsius conjectures a fourth purpose in 2.11:

    that publica mala protect the world against overpopulation and enable future human

    development. Lipsius the pupil raises objections in 2.12 that Languis addresses in the four

    subsequent chapters. First, wicked men never go unpunished; rather punishment is delayed or

    internalized (2.13-14). Second, no one is innocent and all deserve some degree of punishment

    (2.16). Finally, punishments are sometimes transferred to ones descendants, but only in the form

    of external misfortune and not internal guilt or fault (2.17).

    Senecas De providentia plays the most important role in De const. 2.8 where Lipsius

    explains adversity as it concerns good men. Lipsius fills nearly the entire chapter with Senecan

    analogies, ideas, and a quotation that is directly lifted from the De providentia. Languis begins to

    explain adversity as exercise with the simile like a gymnasium where God trains His own to

    endurance and virtue.96

    Within this gymnasium we see athletes exercised by harsh routines

    (Athletas per multa aspera exerceri videmus), and these training athletes first appeared before

    our eyes (Athletas videmus) in Seneca.97

    Taking Seneca further, Lipsius makes God a harsher

    exercitor (trainer) of wise men, requiring suffering that extends beyond sweat; he requires

    blood. Compare:

    Seneca: Itaque cum uideris bonos uiros acceptosque dis laborare sudare...98

    And so, when you see good men of whom the gods approve toiling and

    sweating...

    96

    De con. 2.8: velut gymnasium est, in quo deus suos ad robur instituit et virtutem. 97

    De con. 2.8; cf. Sen. Prov. 2.3 98

    Sen. Prov. 1.6.

  • 31

    Lipsius: Laboris patientiaeque exactor, non ad sudorem tantum, sed ad cruorem.99

    He demands exertion and endurance of us not only until we sweat but until we

    bleed.

    Immediately after the gymnasium, Lipsius transitions to a parental metaphor that appears twice

    in the De providentia.100

    Unlike mothers who excessively pamper their children to their own

    detriment, God loves us truly and severely (De con. 2.8: vere nos diligit et severe) and rears with

    severity, just as harsh fathers do (Sen. Prov. 1.5: sicut severi patres, durius educat). Next,

    Lipsius argues that afflictions are necessary for becoming a mature individual:

    Si nautam te esse velis, per tempestates doceare; si militem, per pericula; si vere virum;

    cur recusas adflictiones? non enim alia ad robur via.101

    If you wish to be a sailor, you may be instructed by storms; if a soldier, by dangers. If

    you wish truly to be a man, why do you object to afflictions? There is no other way to

    strength.

    In this passage Lipsius borrows both philosophical content and literary device from Seneca.

    First, there is the Stoic idea that a healthy mind is the necessary element to virtuous living and,

    99

    De con. 2.8 100

    Sen. Prov. 1.5: immo etiam necessitudo et similitudo, quoniam quidem bonus tempore tantum a deo differt,

    discipulus eius aemulatorque et uera progenies, quam parens ille magnificus, uirtutum non lenis exactor, sicut

    seueri patres, durius educat (No, rather it is a bond of relationship and similarity, since undoubtedly a good man

    differs from God only in the sphere of time; he is Gods pupil and imitator, his true offspring whom that illustrious

    parent, no gentle trainer in virtue, rears with severity, as strict fathers do). Sen. Prov. 2.5: Non uides quanto aliter

    patres, aliter matres indulgeant? illi excitari iubent liberos ad studia obeunda mature, feriatis quoque diebus non

    patiuntur esse otiosos, et sudorem illis et interdum lacrimas excutiunt; at matres fouere in sinu, continere in umbra

    uolunt, numquam contristari, numquam flere, numquam laborare. 6. Patrium deus habet aduersus bonos uiros

    animum et illos fortiter amat (Do you not see how differently fathers and mothers show their love? The father

    orders his children to be roused early to pursue their studies, not allowing them to be idle even on a holiday, and

    wrings from them sweat and sometimes tears; but the mother wants to cherish them in her embrace and keep them

    out of the suns glare, and wishes them never to know sadness, never to shed tears, never to toil. It is a fathers heart

    that God shows to good men; he loves them in a manly way). Cf. De con. 2.8: Molliter eum habere suos censes?

    Deliciis fovere aut luxu? non facit. Matres sunt, quae plerumque specie dulcium corrumpunt, et enervant liberos:

    patres, qui tristium specie servant. Pater autem ille nobis est: ideoque vere nos diligit et severe (Do you think that

    he should treat his own more gently and fondle them with delights and excess? He doesnt do that. Mothers are

    generally the ones who corrupt their children with the semblance of living-kindness and enfeeble them. It is fathers

    who preserve them with the appearance of sternness. God is our Father, however, and so He loves us truly and

    severely). 101

    De con. 2.8. Another sailor analogy that carries an equivalent meaning is made later in this paragraph: Vela

    gubernatori ventus semper a puppi impleat: artem nusquam explicabit (Let the wind always fill the sails for the

    helmsman from the sternhe will never develop his skill).

  • 32

    further, that adversity makes the mind healthy. In Prov. 4, Seneca mentions twice that the part of

    the body that is in constant use is the strongest and encourages the reader to continually endure

    adversity for the sake of strengthening his mind.102

    As we find in Lipsius, Seneca couples this

    idea with comparisons to sailors and soldiers: gubernatorem in tempestate, in acie militem

    intellegas (you would come to know a ships pilot in a storm and a soldier in the line of battle)

    and sunt nauticis corpora ferendo mari duraad excutienda tela militares lacerti valent (the

    bodies of mariners are tough from the buffeting of the sea the muscles of soldiers enable them

    to hurl the javelin).103

    Lipsius, following Seneca, then juxtaposes the athletes, sailors and

    soldiers against those with good fortune:

    Seneca: Languent per inertiam saginata nec labore tantum sed motu et ipso sui onere

    deficiunt.Non fert ullum ictum inlaesa felicitas.104

    Bodies that have become fat grow sluggish through lack of use, and not effort

    alone but even movement and their very own weight cause them to fail. Prosperity

    that is undiminished cannot withstand a single blow.

    Lipsius: Videsne languida illa et umbratica corpora, quae rarus sol vidit, ventus non

    strinxit, aura tristior non libavit? tales mollium istorum et perpetim felicium

    animi sunt, quos deiiciet et resoluet minima adversantis Fortunae aura.105

    Dont you see those languid pallid bodies that the sun has rarely seen, the wind

    has not grazed, and a harsher gale has not touched? Such are the minds of these

    flabby, perpetually lucky types, whom the least gust of adverse Fortune reduces to

    dejection and dismay.

    Those with weak characters but good fortune are so unaccustomed to adversity that they feel

    harmed at the slightest discomfort. Finally, Lipsius ends the paragraph with another analogy for

    the good man drawn from the De providentia: ut arbores ventis agitatae, altius radices agunt:

    102

    Sen. Prov. 4.12: saepius adierimus, fortiores erimus: solidissima corporis pars est quam frequens usus agitauit

    (the more often we engage in it, the stronger our hearts will be: the sturdiest part of the body is the one that is kept

    in constant use); Prov. 4.13: id in quoque solidissimum est quod exercuit (in each case the part of the body

    exercised is the strongest). 103

    Sen. Prov. 4.5,13. 104

    Sen. Prov. 2.6. 105

    De con. 2.8.

  • 33

    sic boni in virtute magis comprehendunt (as trees buffeted by the wind put down deeper roots,

    even so the good lay hold of virtue more firmly). Compare this with Senecas: non est arbor

    solida nec fortis nisi in quam frequens uentus incursat; ipsa enim uexatione constringitur et

    radices certius figit (No tree is sturdy or firm-rooted without enduring many an assault from the

    wind; for the battering itself makes it tighten its grip and fix its roots more securely).106

    As a

    whole, this single paragraph reiterates an impressive amount of Senecas material. As for style,

    every sentence is concise, colorful, and forceful; it is entirely Senecan.

    The remainder of chapter 2.8 contains a few other hints to the De providentia. Lipsius

    compares God to a general who only chooses the best men to join his ranks, and he uses a

    quotation attributed to Demetrius that Seneca provides in Prov. 3.8: Nihil mihi videtur infelicius

    eo, cui nihil evenit adversi (Nothing seems more unhappy to me than someone who has never

    experienced adversity).107

    The chapter ends with a rephrasing of Senecas argument that good

    men suffer misfortune in order to help the rest of humanity know what is truly good. Lipsius

    does not identify true evils as in Seneca and instead emphasizes a characterization of good men

    as beacons of virtue.108

    Lipsius characterizes the good man as a light in the dark world (lumen in

    tenebroso mundo) and that torch (ista face).

    106

    Sen. Prov. 4.16. 107

    De con. 2.8: Non enim parcit Imperator noster talibus, sed diffidit; nec indulget, sed abiicit et contemnit.

    Expungit, inquam, eos e legionum suarum numeris, ut ignavos quosdam et imbelles (For our Commander does not

    spare such men [who have not endured], but suspects them; he does not indulge them, but degrades and dismisses

    them. He removes them, I say, from the tally of his legions, as malingerers and cowards). Cf. Sen. Prov. 4.8: Quare

    deus optimum quemque aut mala ualetudine aut luctu aut aliis incommodis adficit? quia in castris quoque

    periculosa fortissimis imperantur (Why does God afflict the best men with bad health, or grief, or other

    misfortunes? Because in the army the bravest men are ordered to carry out dangerous missions). 108

    Sen. Prov. 5.1: Adice nunc quod pro omnibus est optimum quemque, ut ita dicam, militare et edere operas. Hoc

    est propositum deo quod sapienti uiro, ostendere haec quae uulgus adpetit, quae reformidat, nec bona esse nec

    mala; apparebit autem bona esse, si illa non nisi bonis uiris tribuerit, et mala esse, si tantum malis inrogauerit

    (Take into account the further fact that it is to everyones benefit that all the best men become soldiers, so to speak,

    and do service. Gods purpose, and the wise mans, too, is to show that what ordinary men desire, and what they

    fear, are not either goods or evils; but it will appear that there are goods, if these are granted only to good men, and

    that there are evils, if these penalize only bad men).

  • 34

    Other components of Languis third argument for constancy show indebtedness to the De

    providentia as well. While Seneca is only interested in adversity affecting good men, the De

    providentia contributes to Lipsius dialogue regarding the other two groups of individuals: the

    venially sinful (2.9) and the genuinely wicked (2.10). For those experiencing temporary

    difficulty in exercising virtue, adversity serves as a means of correction. For the sake of moral

    improvement, God may harm our bodies, our fields, our wealth, and all external things but

    does not affect our integral selves.109

    This distinctly Stoic separation between our proper selves

    and our external goods appears in Prov. 5, but it is by no means unique to the work or Seneca.

    Finally, Seneca assures Lucilius in Prov. 4.7 that the wicked, while now happy with good

    fortune, will eventually experience misfortune:

    Erratis enim si quem iudicatis exceptum: ueniet ad illum diu felicem sua portio;

    quisquis uidetur dimissus esse dilatus est.

    You are wrong if you think anyone has been exempted from ill; the man who has known

    happiness for many a year will receive his share some day; whoever seems to have been

    set free from this has only been granted a delay.

    Lipsius shares this sentiment in chapters 2.13-14. First, Lipsius restates the general proposition

    that ones share of unhappiness, or punishment, has only been postponed:

    Malos, ais, divina ultio male praeterit. Itane praeterit? imo, ut ego sentio, differtAtqui

    idem facit magnus ille deus, cui cum poenam improbi omnes debeant, ab istis eam statim

    exigit, in aliis differt, sed cum faenore solvendam.110

    Divine vengeance, you say, badly misses the bad. But does it miss them? Rather, I

    imagine, it delayssince all the wicked owe Him a penalty, He demands it from some

    immediately, for others He delays, but it must be paid with interest.

    Lipsius separates himself from Seneca and Stoicism, however, by stressing divine retribution.

    Whereas Seneca only mentions some share (portio) of unhappiness that necessarily accompanies

    men of weak character, Lipsius introduces divine vengeance (divino ultio) and punishment

    109

    De con. 2.9: sed corpus, agros, opes, et omnia externa. 110

    De con. 2.14.

  • 35

    (poenam). Lipsius enumerates three possible forms of punishment: external misfortunes of the

    body, internal sufferings of the mind, and posthumous torment. While wicked men may

    sometimes have good fortune, they will always experience the mental suffering and everlasting

    punishment after death.111

    Although Lipsius and Seneca both acknowledge the harm felt by

    wicked men resulting from imperfect rationality, Stoicism does not posit that souls retain any

    individuating qualitieslet alone are capable of sufferingafter death.

    Until now, I have examined the De providentia as contributing to Lipsius third

    argument: public evils are beneficial. Accordingly, this discussion has largely focused on the De

    providentia as an ethical discourse on the proper attitude one should adopt towards misfortunes

    like war, poverty, and sickness. It is undeniable that the De providentia serves as a guide for

    Lipsius on this topic. He takes over the ethical axiology that underpins Senecas De providentia

    to conclude that public evils are not actually evil; rather, good men have the mental clarity to

    properly value external objects as indifferent. It is not the misfortune that causes unhappiness,

    but the imperfectly rational mind that falsely believes itself harmed. As a result, good men are

    able to exercise virtue amidst the threat of bodily pain. In fact, adversity actually makes it easier

    for the good man to be virtuous. This argument resolves the complaint of Lucilius in De

    providentia, but Lipsius expands upon this reasoning to include how public evils benefit all

    individuals, not just the wise men. Still, this all occurs only in the second book of De constantia

    and three further arguments remain. In the first and second arguments, Lipsius deals with the

    metaphysical issues of providence, necessity and fate.112

    In Lipsius letter to Lernutius (dated

    December 31, 1580), he says he is penetrating (penetro) into Stoicism. Recall that Lipsius also

    111

    De con. 2.14: Et est quidem plerumque, ut eae omnes iusto quodam dei iudicio in impios convenient: certe

    quidem priores duae semper (And for the most part it is the case that all these by some just judgment of God

    converge upon the wickedassuredly the first two always). 112

    The fourth argument is essentially a catalogue of historical wars and does not contain much philosophical matter.

  • 36

    makes the charge against Quintilian that he has not penetrated into the innermost of Philosophy

    (non penetrasse in interiora Philosophiae) in his Opera Omnia Senecae (1605). Does such a

    deeper knowledge of Stoicisma knowledge that extends beyond ethical thoughtfind a

    presence in the De constantia?

    As its title suggests, providence lies at the core of the De providentia. However, Seneca

    himself says in Prov. 1.1 that he will not set out to systematically explain providence or prove it

    exists:

    Quaesisti a me, Lucili, quid ita, si prouidentia mundus ageretur, multa bonis uiris mala

    acciderent. Hoc commodius in contextu operis redderetur, cum praeesse uniuersis

    prouidentiam probaremus et interesse nobis deum.

    You have asked me Lucilius, why, if the world is governed by providence, it is still the

    case that good men suffer from many misfortunes. This question would receive a more

    fitting answer in a coherent work that set out to prove that providence does preside over

    us all and that God concerns himself with us.

    Seneca limits himself in this treatise to the reconciliation between providence and adversity.

    Through this reconciliation, Lucilius and the reader may improve themselves by responding

    properly to adversity. Seneca tells us immediately that the physics fundamental to Lucilius

    question will be left out. Nevertheless, we should proceed cautiously and consider the De

    providentia as a possible vehicle for Stoic physics before we search for other works that may

    have influenced Lipsius. Despite Senecas warning that he will not prove providence, there are

    traces of Stoic determinism in parts one and five of the De providentia that demand attention.

    In the opening segments of the De providentia, Seneca briefly introduces an important

    principle of Stoic physics before settling into the main argument of the work. While Seneca is

    sure Lucilius already knows all this (Supervacuum est in praesentia ostendere), he sets out a

  • 37

    critical property of the Stoic cosmos: it is regulated by some rational and non-random power.113

    Providing clarification, Seneca explains that there exist fixed laws that provide the stars and

    planets with orderly, predictable movement.114

    Further, it is evident that this system is not

    characteristic of matter that moves randomly (non esse materiae errantis hunc ordinem).115

    The

    term materiae errantis refers to Epicurean randomness of atoms; Seneca means that the observed

    patterns of the universe are not characteristic of randomly moving bodies. Further:

    nec quae temere coierunt tanta arte pendere ut terrarum grauissimum pondus sedeat

    inmotum et circa se properantis caeli fugam spectet, ut infusa uallibus maria molliant

    terras nec ullum incrementum fluminum sentiant, ut ex minimis seminibus nascantur

    ingentia.116

    [It is superfluous to show] that such combinations as do result from chance are not

    dependent on the great artistry that makes the earth with all its mighty weight remain

    stationary, observing the swift passage of the heavens as they whirl around it, that makes

    the seas, flooding the valleys, soften the land, and feel no increase from the rivers, and

    makes enormous growths arise from the smallest seeds.

    Seneca makes reference again to a designing principle (arte) that is responsible for the physical

    laws that govern the earth. This design codes the seminal principles in all living things, guiding

    their biological functions and growth. Natural events like thunderstorms, volcanoes, and

    earthquakes are all likewise determined according to this design.117

    This designs influence

    extends to phenomena which are taken to be miraculous because the setting in which w